Schenkerian Analysis and Occam's Razor
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Schenkerian Analysis and Occam’s Razor L. Poundie Burstein In his book Contemplating Music, Joseph Kerman perceptions of skilled listeners, and thus which famously criticized Schenkerian analysis as a may bear empirical investigation. These attitudes positivistic enterprise (1985: 73–74). Schenkerian also accord with the rhetoric found in many scholars largely have seemed hesitant to refute Schenkerian analyses, which typically refer to this accusation, perhaps betraying a reluctance things like prolongations or hidden motivic to deny the notion that Schenkerian analysis has connections as if these items actually reside within objective and experiential grounding. Some have the composition itself, waiting to be brought to even argued that Schenkerian analysis should light by the analyst.4 rightly have an empirical basis.1 However, it is not so clear how one can confi rm Indeed, it has often been suggested that that the connections described in a Schenkerian Schenkerian analysis seeks to describe certain analysis do indeed inhere in the work itself, or how concrete elements found in compositions, one can test whether the more subtle features demonstrating things such as the “coherence cited by Schenkerian analyses are perceived by the or the working-out of long-range implications average educated listener. Adding to the problems […] in the masterpieces of the tonal repertory” in this regard is the murky ontological status of (Schulenberg 1985: 304–5) or “the unity of [a] work what is examined by Schenkerian analysis. If the and the necessity of its constituent moments” compositions studied were performed by digital (Treitler 1989: 32), that it uncovers “connections computers in a strictly prescribed manner and for among tones that are not readily apparent” a clearly defi ned audience, then one might better (Cadwallader and Gagné 1998: 4), as well as the be able to produce analytic predictions of sorts. degree to which a composition may be regarded The notated compositions examined by the typical as tonal (Brown, Dempster, and Headlam 1989: Schenkerian analysis, however, admit a variety of 157). 2 Some have further argued that Schenkerian possible valid realizations in performances that analyses properly should reveal structures that are intended for a variety of types of audiences, are perceived by listeners, and thereby “should and this in turn creates severe diffi culties for predict how suitably qualifi ed auditors might those who attempt to make empirically verifi able respond to features characteristic of tonal music” statements about subtle features that may exist (Brown, Dempster, and Headlam 1989: 157).3 Such in a composition or that may be heard by skilled attitudes promote the notion that Schenkerian listeners. analyses seek to study objective elements that There is another way in which one may view the are present in the pieces themselves or in the goals of Schenkerian analysis, however, one that I 1 See, for instance, Brown 2005; and Brown, Dempster, and Headlam 1989; see also recent discussion in Debellis 2010. 2 Published comments suggesting that Schenkerian analyses seek to describe features that inhere in composition are by no means uncommon; see for instance, the statement in Debellis 2010: 114 that “a central tenet of [Schenkerian] theory is that a piece has a structure of a certain kind” (emphasis added). More often, however, authors tend to state the aims of Schenkerian analysis in a more elliptical fashion. For instance, it is common to fi nd claims that the Schenkerian method is a theory of tonal unity and coherence, without clear specifi cation whether the coherence and unity involved is to be regarded as a feature of the music itself or simply a proposed possible way in which one may experience the music; see, for instance, Salzer 1962: xv; see also discussion of “descriptive” and “suggestive” theories in Temperley 1999 and discussion below. 3 See also Walton 1993: 39, which states that analyses are “…specifi cations of what we hear. The possibility is open that even the Schenkerian deep structure of a piece, or the fact that the foreground and middleground are elaborations of the deep structure, is in fact an unacknowledged part of the content of musical experiences”; see also critique in Keiler 1978. 4 As Steven Rings notes, Schenkerian analyses tend to be “of the ‘theory of the piece,’ or immanent, variety […]. Such an immanent perspective is evident in familiar locutions in Schenkerian discourse, such as ‘The work is a ^3-line’” (Rings 2011: 36). 112 L. Poundie Burstein feel more accurately refl ects its fi nest applications. Does this analysis by Schenker refl ect how According to this alternate view, Schenkerian most skilled musicians hear this excerpt? My analysis is essentially a hermeneutic process, one own experience suggests not. I have discussed that seeks to propose persuasive and eff ective this passage in various undergraduate classes, ways of how a composition may be heard. As graduate classes, doctoral seminars, and work- such, the Schenkerian method functions as shops with students, professors, scholars, and what David Temperley refers to as a “suggestive” performers from around the world, and through theory rather than a “descriptive” theory; that is, this informal empirical survey I have found that it suggests what the analyst believes is a plausible almost nobody comes up with a reading similar and rewarding manner of perceiving a given to what Schenker has proposed. This suggests composition (Temperley 1999).5 For those who that Schenker’s reading does not predict how the can “hear” the work in a manner proposed by a typical qualifi ed auditor perceives this excerpt – Schenkerian reading (that is, for those who can unless one relies on a tautology by arguing that perceive a direct analogy between the analytic anybody who reads it diff erently than Schenker is model and the piece at hand) and who fi nd this therefore to be regarded as unqualifi ed (a stance proposed hearing to be a gratifying one, the admittedly that Schenker himself probably would analysis will prove successful. have taken). Consider Schenker’s reading of the theme I have found that the reading most people of the fi nale to Beethoven’s Sonata for Piano in adopt (at least before seeing Schenker’s reading) D Minor, Op. 31, No. 2 (Example 1).6 In citing an is more like what is shown in Example 2. With this analysis by Schenker himself, incidentally, I do not alternate reading, the tonic harmony is prolonged mean to suggest that Schenkerian analysis must from bars 1–12. Accordingly, the IV chord of bar conform to Schenker’s own analytic readings.7 9 does not connect to the V of bar 13. Since this What is called “Schenkerian analysis” represents alternate analysis avoids having a tonic couched a general approach that grew out of Schenker’s within a larger progression from IV to V, it thereby methods and concepts, and that since his time arguably presents a simpler, more direct reading has developed and evolved through a series of than was off ered by Schenker. As such, if one’s goal clarifi cations, misreadings, modifi cations, and in analysis is to demonstrate the tonal coherence extensions. The reason I cite this particular analysis and unity of a passage, or how this passage by Schenker is because I feel that it is an especially might be organically generated, then by applying fi ne example of Schenkerian interpretation, and Occam’s razor this alternate analysis would have that whether one agrees with the interpretation to be regarded as more successful than the put forth here, it exhibits elements that are worthy one put forth by Schenker. After all, it explains of emulation. the passage’s tonal coherence and unity in a As shown in Example 1b, Schenker reads this plausible manner that is at least as consistent as in passage as embraced by an Ursatz replica in which Schenker’s reading, but it does so in a simpler and a Zug from F to D in the upper voice is supported more direct fashion. And if the goal of the analysis by the Stufenkreise I–IV–V–I in D minor. Note is to demonstrate how qualifi ed listeners perceive that Schenker interprets the dominant-to-tonic the work, then the reasons mentioned above succession in bars 11–12 as couched within a larger likewise would support the reading presented in motion from IV to V. Also note that the Roman Example 2 as the better one. numeral V is placed under the bass-note D in the To be sure, there are various melodic, formal, hypermetrically weak bar 12, not under the bass- dynamic, and textural nuances that are concretely note A in bar 13. found in the score itself that could be cited 5 This roughly corresponds to what Debellis (2002: 119) describes as a “view of musical analysis [that] fi nds its value not in explanation but in its cultivation of an enriched mode of hearing on the listener’s part, where the listener hears the music in a new way, or becomes aware of new relationships to hear in it.” 6 Schenker’s analysis is from Schenker 1979, Figure 104.1. I discuss this analysis at length in Burstein 2009. 7 In this sense, the term “Schenkerian analysis” is an unfortunate one, since it wrongly might suggest that such analyses necessarily refl ect Schenker’s own views. Schenker himself likely would have frowned upon this term: he tended to view his theory not as one possible method for understanding music, but rather as the only appropriate method. 113 Schenkerian Analysis and Occam’s Razor Example 1a. Beethoven, Sonata in D Minor, Op. 31, No. 2, III, mm. 1–15. Example 1b.