An Introduction to Cooperative Game Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Introduction to Cooperative Game Theory Definitions Stability notions Other solution concepts Subclasses An Introduction to Cooperative Game Theory Maria Serna Fall 2016 AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Definitions Stability notions Other solution concepts Subclasses References G. Chalkiadakis, E. Elkind, M. Wooldridge Computational Aspects of Cooperative Game Theory Morgan & Claypool, 2012 Wikipedia. G. Owen Game Theory 3rd edition, Academic Press, 1995 AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses 1 Definitions 2 Stability notions 3 Other solution concepts 4 Subclasses AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Non-Cooperative versus cooperative Games Non-cooperative game theory model scenarios where players cannot make binding agreements. Cooperative game theory model scenarios, where agents can benefit by cooperating, and binding agreements are possible. In cooperative games, actions are taken by groups of agents, coalitions, and payoffs are given to the group, that has to divided it among its members: Transferable utility games. individuals: Non-transferable utility games. For the moment we focus on TU games Notation: N, set of players, C; S; X ⊆ N are coalitions. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together usually it is assumed that v is normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D A coalition is any subset of N N itself is called the grand coalition. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory usually it is assumed that v is normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D A coalition is any subset of N N itself is called the grand coalition. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D A coalition is any subset of N N itself is called the grand coalition. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together usually it is assumed that v is AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory A coalition is any subset of N N itself is called the grand coalition. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together usually it is assumed that v is normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory N itself is called the grand coalition. Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together usually it is assumed that v is normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D A coalition is any subset of N AGT-MIRI Cooperative Game Theory Definitions TU characteristic function games Stability notions Outcomes Other solution concepts Imputations Subclasses Characteristic Function Games A characteristic function game is a pair (N; v), where: N = f1; :::; ng is the set of players and v : 2N ! R is the characteristic function. for each subset of players C ⊆ N, v(C) is the amount that the members of C can earn by working together usually it is assumed that v is normalized: v(;) = 0, non-negative: v(C) ≥ 0, for any C ⊆ N, and monotone: v(C) ≤ v(D), for any C, D such that C ⊆ D A coalition is any subset of N N itself is called the grand coalition.
Recommended publications
  • Game Theory Lecture Notes
    Game Theory: Penn State Math 486 Lecture Notes Version 2.1.1 Christopher Griffin « 2010-2021 Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 3.0 United States License With Major Contributions By: James Fan George Kesidis and Other Contributions By: Arlan Stutler Sarthak Shah Contents List of Figuresv Preface xi 1. Using These Notes xi 2. An Overview of Game Theory xi Chapter 1. Probability Theory and Games Against the House1 1. Probability1 2. Random Variables and Expected Values6 3. Conditional Probability8 4. The Monty Hall Problem 11 Chapter 2. Game Trees and Extensive Form 15 1. Graphs and Trees 15 2. Game Trees with Complete Information and No Chance 18 3. Game Trees with Incomplete Information 22 4. Games of Chance 24 5. Pay-off Functions and Equilibria 26 Chapter 3. Normal and Strategic Form Games and Matrices 37 1. Normal and Strategic Form 37 2. Strategic Form Games 38 3. Review of Basic Matrix Properties 40 4. Special Matrices and Vectors 42 5. Strategy Vectors and Matrix Games 43 Chapter 4. Saddle Points, Mixed Strategies and the Minimax Theorem 45 1. Saddle Points 45 2. Zero-Sum Games without Saddle Points 48 3. Mixed Strategies 50 4. Mixed Strategies in Matrix Games 53 5. Dominated Strategies and Nash Equilibria 54 6. The Minimax Theorem 59 7. Finding Nash Equilibria in Simple Games 64 8. A Note on Nash Equilibria in General 66 Chapter 5. An Introduction to Optimization and the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker Conditions 69 1. A General Maximization Formulation 70 2. Some Geometry for Optimization 72 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theoretic Interaction and Decision: a Quantum Analysis
    games Article Game Theoretic Interaction and Decision: A Quantum Analysis Ulrich Faigle 1 and Michel Grabisch 2,* 1 Mathematisches Institut, Universität zu Köln, Weyertal 80, 50931 Köln, Germany; [email protected] 2 Paris School of Economics, University of Paris I, 106-112, Bd. de l’Hôpital, 75013 Paris, France * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +33-144-07-8744 Received: 12 July 2017; Accepted: 21 October 2017; Published: 6 November 2017 Abstract: An interaction system has a finite set of agents that interact pairwise, depending on the current state of the system. Symmetric decomposition of the matrix of interaction coefficients yields the representation of states by self-adjoint matrices and hence a spectral representation. As a result, cooperation systems, decision systems and quantum systems all become visible as manifestations of special interaction systems. The treatment of the theory is purely mathematical and does not require any special knowledge of physics. It is shown how standard notions in cooperative game theory arise naturally in this context. In particular, states of general interaction systems are seen to arise as linear superpositions of pure quantum states and Fourier transformation to become meaningful. Moreover, quantum games fall into this framework. Finally, a theory of Markov evolution of interaction states is presented that generalizes classical homogeneous Markov chains to the present context. Keywords: cooperative game; decision system; evolution; Fourier transform; interaction system; measurement; quantum game 1. Introduction In an interaction system, economic (or general physical) agents interact pairwise, but do not necessarily cooperate towards a common goal. However, this model arises as a natural generalization of the model of cooperative TU games, for which already Owen [1] introduced the co-value as an assessment of the pairwise interaction of two cooperating players1.
    [Show full text]
  • Stability and Median Rationalizability for Aggregate Matchings
    games Article Stability and Median Rationalizability for Aggregate Matchings Federico Echenique 1, SangMok Lee 2, Matthew Shum 1 and M. Bumin Yenmez 3,* 1 Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125, USA; [email protected] (F.E.); [email protected] (M.S.) 2 Department of Economics, Washington University in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO 63130, USA; [email protected] 3 Department of Economics, Boston College, Chestnut Hill, MA 02467, USA * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: We develop the theory of stability for aggregate matchings used in empirical studies and establish fundamental properties of stable matchings including the result that the set of stable matchings is a non-empty, complete, and distributive lattice. Aggregate matchings are relevant as matching data in revealed preference theory. We present a result on rationalizing a matching data as the median stable matching. Keywords: aggregate matching; median stable matching; rationalizability; lattice 1. Introduction Following the seminal work of [1], an extensive literature has developed regarding matching markets with non-transferable utility. This literature assumes that there are agent-specific preferences, and studies the existence of stable matchings in which each Citation: Echenique, F.; Lee, S.; agent prefers her assigned partner to the outside option of being unmatched, and there Shum, M.; Yenmez, M.B. Stability and are no pairs of agents that would like to match with each other rather than keeping their Median Rationalizability for assigned partners. Aggregate Matchings. Games 2021, 12, In this paper, we develop the theory of stability for aggregate matchings, which we 33.
    [Show full text]
  • Rationalizable Implementation of Correspondences∗
    Rationalizable Implementation of Correspondences∗ Takashi Kunimotoyand Roberto Serranoz This Version: May 2016 Abstract We come close to characterizing the class of social choice correspon- dences that are implementable in rationalizable strategies. We identify a new condition, which we call set-monotonicity, and show that it is necessary and almost sufficient for rationalizable implementation. Set-monotonicity is much weaker than Maskin monotonicity, which is the key condition for Nash implementation and which also had been shown to be necessary for rationalizable implementation of social choice functions. Set-monotonicity reduces to Maskin monotonicity in the case of functions. We conclude that the conditions for rationalizable implementation are not only starkly differ- ent from, but also much weaker than those for Nash implementation, when we consider social choice correspondences. JEL Classification: C72, D78, D82. Keywords: Complete information, implementation, Maskin monotonicity, rationalizability, set-monotonicity, social choice correspondence. 1 Introduction The design of institutions to be used by rational agents has been an important research agenda in economic theory. As captured by the notion of Nash equilib- rium, rationality is encapsulated in two aspects: these are (i) the best responses of agents to their beliefs, and (ii) that those beliefs are correct, the so-called rational ∗Financial support from the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (24330078, 25780128) (Kunimoto) is gratefully acknowledged. All remaining errors are our own. ySchool of Economics, Singapore Management University, 90 Stamford Road, Singapore 178903; [email protected] zDepartment of Economics, Brown University, Providence, RI 02912, U.S.A.; roberto [email protected] 1 expectations assumption. One can drop the latter and retain the former, moving then into the realm of rationalizability.
    [Show full text]
  • Cooperative and Non-Cooperative Game Theory Olivier Chatain
    HEC Paris From the SelectedWorks of Olivier Chatain 2014 Cooperative and Non-Cooperative Game Theory Olivier Chatain Available at: https://works.bepress.com/olivier_chatain/9/ The Palgrave Encyclopedia of Strategic Management Edited by Mie Augier and David J. Teece (http://www.palgrave.com/strategicmanagement/information/) Entry: Cooperative and non-cooperative game theory Author: Olivier Chatain Classifications: economics and strategy competitive advantage formal models methods/methodology Definition: Cooperative game theory focuses on how much players can appropriate given the value each coalition of player can create, while non-cooperative game theory focuses on which moves players should rationally make. Abstract: This article outlines the differences between cooperative and non-cooperative game theory. It introduces some of the main concepts of cooperative game theory as they apply to strategic management research. Keywords: cooperative game theory coalitional game theory value-based strategy core (solution concept) Shapley value; biform games Cooperative and non-cooperative game theory Game theory comprises two branches: cooperative game theory (CGT) and non-cooperative game theory (NCGT). CGT models how agents compete and cooperate as coalitions in unstructured interactions to create and capture value. NCGT models the actions of agents, maximizing their utility in a defined procedure, relying on a detailed description of the moves 1 and information available to each agent. CGT abstracts from these details and focuses on how the value creation abilities of each coalition of agents can bear on the agents’ ability to capture value. CGT can be thus called coalitional, while NCGT is procedural. Note that ‘cooperative’ and ‘non-cooperative’ are technical terms and are not an assessment of the degree of cooperation among agents in the model: a cooperative game can as much model extreme competition as a non-cooperative game can model cooperation.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Social Interactions
    Beta September 2015 version 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS Les Joueurs de Carte, Paul Cézanne, 1892-95, Courtauld Institute of Art A COMBINATION OF SELF-INTEREST, A REGARD FOR THE WELLBEING OF OTHERS, AND APPROPRIATE INSTITUTIONS CAN YIELD DESIRABLE SOCIAL OUTCOMES WHEN PEOPLE INTERACT • Game theory is a way of understanding how people interact based on the constraints that limit their actions, their motives and their beliefs about what others will do • Experiments and other evidence show that self-interest, a concern for others and a preference for fairness are all important motives explaining how people interact • In most interactions there is some conflict of interest between people, and also some opportunity for mutual gain • The pursuit of self-interest can lead either to results that are considered good by all participants, or sometimes to outcomes that none of those concerned would prefer • Self-interest can be harnessed for the general good in markets by governments limiting the actions that people are free to take, and by one’s peers imposing punishments on actions that lead to bad outcomes • A concern for others and for fairness allows us to internalise the effects of our actions on others, and so can contribute to good social outcomes See www.core-econ.org for the full interactive version of The Economy by The CORE Project. Guide yourself through key concepts with clickable figures, test your understanding with multiple choice questions, look up key terms in the glossary, read full mathematical derivations in the Leibniz supplements, watch economists explain their work in Economists in Action – and much more.
    [Show full text]
  • Dynamics of Profit-Sharing Games
    Proceedings of the Twenty-Second International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence Dynamics of Profit-Sharing Games John Augustine, Ning Chen, Edith Elkind, Angelo Fanelli, Nick Gravin, Dmitry Shiryaev School of Physical and Mathematical Sciences Nanyang Technological University, Singapore Abstract information about other players. Such agents may simply re- spond to their current environment without worrying about An important task in the analysis of multiagent sys- the subsequent reaction of other agents; such behavior is said tems is to understand how groups of selfish players to be myopic. Now, coalition formation by computationally can form coalitions, i.e., work together in teams. In limited agents has been studied by a number of researchers in this paper, we study the dynamics of coalition for- multi-agent systems, starting with the work of [Shehory and mation under bounded rationality. We consider set- Kraus, 1999] and [Sandholm and Lesser, 1997]. However, tings where each team’s profit is given by a concave myopic behavior in coalition formation received relatively lit- function, and propose three profit-sharing schemes, tle attention in the literature (for some exceptions, see [Dieck- each of which is based on the concept of marginal mann and Schwalbe, 2002; Chalkiadakis and Boutilier, 2004; utility. The agents are assumed to be myopic, i.e., Airiau and Sen, 2009]). In contrast, myopic dynamics of they keep changing teams as long as they can in- non-cooperative games is the subject of a growing body of crease their payoff by doing so. We study the prop- research (see, e.g. [Fabrikant et al., 2004; Awerbuch et al., erties (such as closeness to Nash equilibrium or to- 2008; Fanelli et al., 2008]).
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Game Theory Trying to Accomplish?
    1 What Is Game Theory Trying to Accomplish? 1 Introduction The language of game theory—coalitions, payo¤s, markets, votes— suggests that it is not a branch of abstract mathematics; that it is moti- vated by and related to the world around us; and that it should be able to tell us something about that world. Most of us have long realized that game theory and the ‘‘real world’’ (it might better be called the complex world) have a relationship that is not entirely comfortable; that it is not clear just what it is that we are trying to do when we build a game- theoretic model and then apply solution concepts to it. This is the subject I would like to explore in this paper. I might add that much the same questions apply to economic theory, at least the kind that those of us working in mathematical economics see most often; and that much of my paper will apply, mutatis mutandis, to economic theory as well. There is a branch of philosophy that deals with theory in the social sciences, so some of the things I have to say are unquestionably old hat. But I am not trying to be particularly original: I am only trying to open this topic, which I think concerns all of us, for discussion, and to suggest a particu- lar point of view. No doubt others have thought about these questions more thoroughly and deeply than I have, and are better versed in the history and philosophy of science in general. I will be grateful to anybody who sets me straight when I err, and who gives me references for the things I get right.
    [Show full text]
  • Solution Concepts in Cooperative Game Theory
    1 A. Stolwijk Solution Concepts in Cooperative Game Theory Master’s Thesis, defended on October 12, 2010 Thesis Advisor: dr. F.M. Spieksma Mathematisch Instituut, Universiteit Leiden 2 Contents 1 Introduction 7 1.1 BackgroundandAims ................................. 7 1.2 Outline .......................................... 8 2 The Model: Some Basic Concepts 9 2.1 CharacteristicFunction .............................. ... 9 2.2 Solution Space: Transferable and Non-Transferable Utilities . .......... 11 2.3 EquivalencebetweenGames. ... 12 2.4 PropertiesofSolutions............................... ... 14 3 Comparing Imputations 15 3.1 StrongDomination................................... 15 3.1.1 Properties of Strong Domination . 17 3.2 WeakDomination .................................... 19 3.2.1 Properties of Weak Domination . 20 3.3 DualDomination..................................... 22 3.3.1 Properties of Dual Domination . 23 4 The Core 25 4.1 TheCore ......................................... 25 4.2 TheDualCore ...................................... 27 4.2.1 ComparingtheCorewiththeDualCore. 29 4.2.2 Strong ǫ-Core................................... 30 5 Nash Equilibria 33 5.1 Strict Nash Equilibria . 33 5.2 Weak Nash Equilibria . 36 3 4 CONTENTS 6 Stable Sets 39 6.1 DefinitionofStableSets ............................... .. 39 6.2 Stability in A′ ....................................... 40 6.3 ConstructionofStronglyStableSets . ...... 41 6.3.1 Explanation of the Strongly Stable Set: The Standard of Behavior in the 3-personzero-sumgame ............................
    [Show full text]
  • Games in Coalitional Form 1
    GAMES IN COALITIONAL FORM EHUD KALAI Forthcoming in the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, second edition Abstract. How should a coalition of cooperating players allocate payo¤s to its members? This question arises in a broad range of situations and evokes an equally broad range of issues. For example, it raises technical issues in accounting, if the players are divisions of a corporation, but involves issues of social justice when the context is how people behave in society. Despite the breadth of possible applications, coalitional game theory o¤ers a uni…ed framework and solutions for addressing such questions. This brief survey presents some of its major models and proposed solutions. 1. Introduction In their seminal book, von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) introduced two theories of games: strategic and coalitional. Strategic game theory concentrates on the selection of strategies by payo¤-maximizing players. Coalitional game theory concentrates on coalition formation and the distribution of payo¤s. The next two examples illustrate situations in the domain of the coalitional approach. 1.1. Games with no strategic structure. Example 1. Cost allocation of a shared facility. Three municipalities, E, W, and S, need to construct water puri…cation facilities. Costs of individual and joint facilities are described by the cost function c: c(E) = 20, c(W ) = 30, and c(S) = 50; c(E; W ) = 40, c(E; S) = 60, and c(W; S) = 80; c(E; W; S) = 80. For example, a facility that serves the needs of W and S would cost $80 million. The optimal solution is to build, at the cost of 80, one facility that serves all three municipalities.
    [Show full text]
  • THE HUMAN SIDE of MECHANISM DESIGN a Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont
    THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley December 4, 2008 [email protected] http://www.econ.berkeley.edu/~mcfadden/index.shtml ABSTRACT This paper considers the human side of mechanism design, the behavior of economic agents in gathering and processing information and responding to incentives. I first give an overview of the subject of mechanism design, and then examine a pervasive premise in this field that economic agents are rational in their information processing and decisions. Examples from applied mechanism design identify the roles of perceptions and inference in agent behavior, and the influence of systematic irrationalities and sociality on agent responses. These examples suggest that tolerance of behavioral faults be added to the criteria for good mechanism design. In principle-agent problems for example, designers should consider using experimental treatments in contracts, and statistical post-processing of agent responses, to identify and mitigate the effects of agent non-compliance with contract incentives. KEYWORDS: mechanism_design, principal-agent_problem, juries, welfare_theory JEL CLASSIFICATION: D000, D600, D610, D710, D800, C420, C700 THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden1 1. Introduction The study of mechanism design, the systematic analysis of resource allocation institutions and processes, has been the most fundamental development
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Conditional Strategies for Prisoners' Dilemmata Under The
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 30 May 2019 doi:10.20944/preprints201905.0366.v1 Peer-reviewed version available at Appl. Sci. 2019, 9, 2635; doi:10.3390/app9132635 Article Quantum conditional strategies for prisoners’ dilemmata under the EWL scheme Konstantinos Giannakis* , Georgia Theocharopoulou, Christos Papalitsas, Sofia Fanarioti, and Theodore Andronikos* Department of Informatics, Ionian University, Tsirigoti Square 7, Corfu, 49100, Greece; {kgiann, zeta.theo, c14papa, sofiafanar, andronikos}@ionio.gr * Correspondence: [email protected] (K.G.); [email protected] (Th.A.) 1 Abstract: Classic game theory is an important field with a long tradition of useful results. Recently, 2 the quantum versions of classical games, such as the Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD), have attracted a lot of 3 attention. Similarly, state machines and specifically finite automata have also been under constant 4 and thorough study for plenty of reasons. The quantum analogues of these abstract machines, like the 5 quantum finite automata, have been studied extensively. In this work, we examine some well-known 6 game conditional strategies that have been studied within the framework of the repeated PD game. 7 Then, we try to associate these strategies to proper quantum finite automata that receive them as 8 inputs and recognize them with probability 1, achieving some interesting results. We also study the 9 quantum version of PD under the Eisert-Wilkens-Lewenstein scheme, proposing a novel conditional 10 strategy for the repeated version of this game. 11 Keywords: quantum game theory, quantum automata, prisoner’s dilemma, conditional strategies, 12 quantum strategies 13 1. Introduction 14 Quantum game theory has gained a lot of research interest since the first pioneering works of the 15 late ’90s [1–5].
    [Show full text]