Haybron-Happiness-And-Pleasure.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Haybron-Happiness-And-Pleasure.Pdf International Phenomenological Society Happiness and Pleasure Author(s): Daniel M. Haybron Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 62, No. 3 (May, 2001), pp. 501-528 Published by: International Phenomenological Society Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2653534 Accessed: 22-12-2018 23:56 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and Phenomenological Research This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Sat, 22 Dec 2018 23:56:41 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXII, No. 3, May 2001 Happiness and Pleasure1 DANIEL M. HAYBRON Rutgers University This paper argues against hedonistic theories of happiness. First, hedonism is too inclu- sive: many pleasures cannot plausibly be construed as constitutive of happiness. Second, any credible theory must count either attitudes of life satisfaction, affective states such as mood, or both as constituents of happiness; yet neither sort of state reduces to plea- sure. Hedonism errs in its attempt to reduce happiness, which is at least partly disposi- tional, to purely episodic experiential states. The dispositionality of happiness also undermines weakened nonreductive forms of hedonism, as some happiness-constitutive states are not pleasures in any sense. Moreover, these states can apparently fail to exhibit the usual hedonic properties; sadness, for instance, can sometimes be pleasant. Finally, the nonhedonistic accounts are adequate if not superior on grounds of practical and theoretical utility, quite apart from their superior conformity to the folk notion of happiness. "And does his philosophy make you happy?" "I have never searched for happiness. Who wants happiness? I have searched for pleasure. " Oscar Wilde, The Picture of Dorian Gray (p. 209) 1. Introduction Some unlucky soul might, over a period of time, be depressed, despondent, beset with anxiety, "stressed out," seething with rage, overwhelmed by fear, worried sick, heartbroken, grief-stricken, lonely, in low spirits, burdened with shame, overcome with boredom, deeply dissatisfied with life, haunted by a sense of dread or by feelings of emptiness, or simply be melancholy. A more fortunate counterpart might be in high spirits, joyful, exhilarated, elated, jubilant, carefree, deeply contented, at peace, delighted with her life, or blessed with a profound sense of fulfillment or well-being. Persons of the For helpful discussion and comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I wish to thank Bengt Brulde, Irwin Goldstein, Douglas Husak, Barry Loewer, Colin McGinn, Brian McLaugh- lin, Alex Michalos, Jonathan Schaffer, George Sher, T. L. S. Sprigge, Stephen Stich, L. W. Sumner, Barry Ward, and Robert Woolfolk, as well as audiences at the April 2000 Pacific Division conference of the'American Philosophical Association and the May 1999 conference of the New Jersey Regional Philosophy Association, where I presented excerpts from this paper. HAPPINESS AND PLEASURE 501 This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Sat, 22 Dec 2018 23:56:41 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms former sort we naturally deem unhappy. Those of the latter we call happy. Indeed, these would seem to be prototypical cases of unhappiness and happi- ness, at least in one important sense of these expressions. Concerned parents probably have circumstances like these in mind when they inquire as to whether their children are happy. Likewise for young job seekers who worry that they may not be happy if they choose the wrong vocation. Let 'hedonism' denote the venerable doctrine that happiness, so construed, reduces completely to a subject's balance of pleasure over displeasure: happi- ness is merely the condition of having a favorable balance of pleasure over displeasure. I wish to argue that this theory is false. Indeed, it never had a chance of being true, for it fundamentally misconstrues the nature of the mental states that could constitute anything plausibly called happiness. I shall not defend a particular conception of happiness, but I will suggest that there are two basic candidates for such a theory: the affective state and life satisfaction views. As we shall see, these accounts appear to share key features that the hedonistic theory lacks. There are other problems with hedo- nism as well. 2. Preliminaries 2.1 The different things called happiness We can mean any number of things by 'happiness'.2 In such cases as the foregoing-henceforth the "paradigm cases"-we typically intend to denote nothing more profound than a state of mind. In our more lyrical moments, we might refer to it as a condition of the soul or spirit. Though such talk bears unfortunate connotations of cheap New Age sentimentality, these terms are here used in a common secular and naturalistic sense, and are meant to suggest something psychologically deep, intimate and important to us. To distinguish our subject from other things commonly called happiness, we may call this state of mind psychological happiness. So construed, happiness is a purely psychological, nonevaluative kind.3 Philosophers often use 'happiness' with other meanings, most frequently to denote a particularly enviable condition in life: a type of well-being or flourishing. Thus we commonly see the patently evaluative Greek expression 'eudaimonia' translated as 'happiness'. This evaluative kind I refer to as 2 To simplify matters I shall generally refer only to happiness, assuming that whatever is said of happiness also applies, mutatis mutandis, to unhappiness. 3 Philosophers who appear to accept hedonism about psychological happiness include, among many others, such historical thinkers as Bentham, Locke, and Sidgwick; and more recently, Brandt (1959; 1979; 1989; 1992); Campbell (1973); Carson (1978a; 1978b; 1979; 1981); Davis (1981b; 1981a); Ebenstein (1991); Griffin (1979; 1986); Mayerfeld (1996; 1999); Sen (1987); Sprigge (1987; 1991); and Wilson (1968). Casual references to happiness in the philosophical literature frequently assume it to be hedonistic. Hedonism has adherents in psychology as well, such as Allen Parducci (1995) and Daniel Kahne- man (1999). 502 DANIEL M. HAYBRON This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Sat, 22 Dec 2018 23:56:41 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms prudential happiness. Whereas a correct theory of prudential happiness is determined by asking what sorts of lives make us better off, the task of providing a theory of psychological happiness-our task-is to determine the nature of a certain type of psychological state.4 We can distinguish other senses of 'happiness', but the foregoing remarks should suffice for our purposes.' Of more immediate concern is the possibility that there may be no single psychological kind answering to the psychological sense of 'happiness'. Or maybe the vernacular notion is so ill-defined that it admits of no satisfactory analysis. Maybe there is no well-defined folk notion to analyze. No doubt such worries have led many philosophers to conclude that happiness is not a worthwhile object of study. Let us suppose, for the sake of argument, that these concerns are well-founded. It hardly follows that there is no subject matter worth studying. There are clearly aspects of our psychology that we denote, however imprecisely or confusedly, under the guise of happiness. These aspects are almost universally taken to be immensely valuable- indeed, to comprise a central element of human well-being. We have no reason to doubt this belief. We therefore ought to learn something about these phenomena. Even if they simply reduce to familiar psychological cate- gories, we shall have discovered something important; and then we can determine just how valuable happiness is. Maybe, when all is said and done, we will find that happiness is not so valuable after all. And if the resulting kind or kinds do not correspond neatly to our vernacular notion of happiness, we may need to revise our concept somewhat. If more than one kind answers to the name, then we may wish to distinguish further senses of 'happiness', restrict its proper use to just one of the kinds, or dispense with the term altogether. But the idea that such weighty matters do not deserve serious philosophical scrutiny at all is simply obtuse. I shall employ some intuitional evidence in making my case. This may make some readers nervous in light of the foregoing concerns. However, the intuitions exploited appear to be both firm and widely held if any are in this realm. Should anyone's intuitions differ nonetheless, or should worries arise I use terms like 'kind' and 'category' very loosely here, with no particular metaphysical commitments in mind. For instance, the relevant psychological kinds may have no place in scientific, versus folk, psychology. I talk of psychological kinds only to distinguish the present concept from evaluative notions such as that of prudential happiness. To illustrate: one might wish to argue that psychological happiness is the proper measure of well-being-and many have done so (mistakenly, in my view). But this is different from making an a priori stipulation that happiness-whatever it is-must char- acterize what it is to have an especially enviable life. The theorists who do so are not involved in the same business that engages us here. Thus even if well-being consists solely in the psychological state of pleasure, well-being is still an evaluative, and not psychological, kind. i For more on the uses of 'happiness' and cognates, see my (2000; unpublished ms-c), as well as Davis (1981b), Goldstein (1973), and Thomas (1968).
Recommended publications
  • Exploring the Emotional and Moral Lives of Animals
    MARC BEKOFF & JONATHAN BALCOMBE Humans have long tried to imagine what other species think and how they may feel, projecting our own perspec - tives and emotions onto the Minds of Thei r Own animal experience. The sight of Exploring the emotional and moral lives of animals a hawk spiraling effortlessly on an updraft or two horses cantering side by side in a field is enough to inspire wonder about the inner lives of other creatures. And people observ - ing their pets’ activities and moods view the existence of cat and dog emotions—in the form of joy, grief, even jealousy—as beyond question. What seems blatantly apparent to many animal lovers, however, is often chal - lenged by scientists as nothing more than sentimental anthro - pomorphism. Portrayal of ani - E M mals as lesser beings without I T S M A E thought or emotion dates at least as far back as the days of Aristotle. animals, a concept rarely considered within the scientific community . R D / N E E But ethologists engaged in the study of animal behavior are Now teaching a course on animal minds and behavior for U Q C A drawing from a growing body of evidence to build a case to the Humane Society University, the two authors have new books out this M E C U R B contrary. On the forefront of the burgeoning field are scientists and year. Bekoff’s latest, The Animal Manifesto: Six Reasons for Expanding ; E M I T S authors Marc Bekoff and Jonathan Balcombe. After years of research - Our Compassion Footprint , was published in February; Balcombe’s M A E R D / ing the emotions of animals, Bekoff began exploring the concepts new book, Second Nature: The Inner Lives of Animals , is out in March.
    [Show full text]
  • Advances in Neuroscience Imply That Harmful Experiments in Dogs Are Unethical Jarrod Bailey,1 Shiranee Pereira2
    JME Online First, published on July 24, 2017 as 10.1136/medethics-2016-103630 Current controversy J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2016-103630 on 24 July 2017. Downloaded from Advances in neuroscience imply that harmful experiments in dogs are unethical Jarrod Bailey,1 Shiranee Pereira2 1Cruelty Free International, ABSTRACT environments (common features of most laboratory London, UK Functional MRI (fMRI) of fully awake and unrestrained kennels), kennel noise and restricted sight lines are 2People for Animals, Chennai, India dog 'volunteers' has been proven an effective tool to acknowledged stressors, and together these factors understand the neural circuitry and functioning of the lead to well-characterised stereotypies—repeti- Correspondence to canine brain. Although every dog owner would vouch tive, invariant behaviour patterns with no obvious Dr Jarrod Bailey, Cruelty Free that dogs are perceptive, cognitive, intuitive and capable goal or function, which include circling, pacing, International, 16a Crane Grove, of positive emotions/empathy, as indeed substantiated whirling, jumping, wall bouncing, and repetitive London, N7 8NN, UK; by ethological studies for some time, neurological grooming or self-biting—as well as other abnormal ja rrod .bailey@ c rueltyf reeinte rnat iona l. org investigations now corroborate this. These studies show behaviours such as polydipsia or polyphagia (eating that there exists a striking similarity between dogs and drinking to a great degree), compulsive staring Received 18 April 2016 and humans in the functioning of the caudate nucleus and excessive barking, for example (see ref 5). Revised 18 May 2017 (associated with pleasure and emotion), and dogs Such welfare concerns constitute a large part of Accepted 9 June 2017 experience positive emotions, empathic-like responses the ethical objection to dog experimentation.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Feelings Stray: Sources of Affective Misforecasting in Consumer Behavior Vanessa M
    Why Feelings Stray: Sources of Affective Misforecasting in Consumer Behavior Vanessa M. Patrick, University of Georgia Deborah J. MacInnis, University of Southern California ABSTRACT drivers of AMF has considerable import for consumer behavior, Affective misforecasting (AMF) is defined as the gap between particularly in the area of consumer satisfaction, brand loyalty and predicted and experienced affect. Based on prior research that positive word-of-mouth. examines AMF, the current study uses qualitative and quantitative Figure 1 depicts the process by which affective misforecasting data to examine the sources of AMF (i.e., why it occurs) in the occurs (for greater detail see MacInnis, Patrick and Park 2005). As consumption domain. The authors find evidence supporting some Figure 1 suggests, affective forecasts are based on a representation sources of AMF identified in the psychology literature, develop a of a future event and an assessment of the possible affective fuller understanding of others, and, find evidence for novel sources reactions to this event. AMF occurs when experienced affect of AMF not previously explored. Importantly, they find consider- deviates from the forecasted affect on one or more of the following able differences in the sources of AMF depending on whether dimensions: valence, intensity and duration. feelings are worse than or better than forecast. Since forecasts can be made regarding the valence of the feelings, the specific emotions expected to be experienced, the INTRODUCTION intensity of feelings or the duration of a projected affective re- Before purchase: “I can’t wait to use this all the time, it is sponse, consequently affective misforecasting can occur along any going to be so much fun, I’m going to go out with my buddies of these dimensions.
    [Show full text]
  • Affective Neuroscience of Pleasure: Reward in Humans and Animals
    Psychopharmacology (2008) 199:457–480 DOI 10.1007/s00213-008-1099-6 REVIEW Affective neuroscience of pleasure: reward in humans and animals Kent C. Berridge & Morten L. Kringelbach Received: 3 July 2007 /Accepted: 31 January 2008 /Published online: 3 March 2008 # Springer-Verlag 2008 Abstract Introduction Introduction Pleasure and reward are generated by brain circuits that are largely shared between humans and other Affective neuroscience has emerged as an exciting disci- animals. pline in recent years (Berridge 2003a; Damasio 2004; Discussion Here, we survey some fundamental topics Davidson et al. 2003; Davidson and Sutton 1995; Feldman regarding pleasure mechanisms and explicitly compare Barrett and Wager 2006; Kringelbach 2005, 2008; LeDoux humans and animals. and Phelps 2000; Leknes and Tracey 2008; Panksepp 1991; Conclusion Topics surveyed include liking, wanting, and 1998; Rolls 2005). Many important insights have been learning components of reward; brain coding versus brain gained into brain mechanisms of affect, motivation, and causing of reward; subjective pleasure versus objective emotion through studies of both animals and humans. hedonic reactions; roles of orbitofrontal cortex and related A particularly important topic for affective neuroscience cortex regions; subcortical hedonic hotspots for pleasure is to understand how brains generate pleasure and other generation; reappraisals of dopamine and pleasure-electrode psychological components of reward because reward is controversies; and the relation of pleasure to happiness. important in daily life. Pleasure is essential to a normal sense of well-being. Pathological losses of pleasure may be Keywords Reward . Pleasure . Motivation . Hedonic . a devastating part of many affective disorders ranging from Food . Addiction . Nucleus accumbens . depression to schizophrenia and addiction.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Sexuality, Volume 2: the Use of Pleasure
    The Use of Pleasure Volume 2 of The History of Sexuality Michel Foucault Translated from the French by Robert Hurley Vintage Books . A Division of Random House, Inc. New York The Use of Pleasure Books by Michel Foucault Madness and Civilization: A History oflnsanity in the Age of Reason The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences The Archaeology of Knowledge (and The Discourse on Language) The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical Perception I, Pierre Riviere, having slaughtered my mother, my sister, and my brother. ... A Case of Parricide in the Nineteenth Century Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison The History of Sexuality, Volumes I, 2, and 3 Herculine Barbin, Being the Recently Discovered Memoirs of a Nineteenth­ Century French Hermaphrodite Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977 VINTAGE BOOKS EDlTlON, MARCH 1990 Translation copyright © 1985 by Random House, Inc. All rights reserved under International and Pan-American Copyright Conventions. Published in the United States by Vintage Books, a division of Random House, Inc., New York, and simultaneously in Canada by Random House of Canada Limited, Toronto. Originally published in France as L' Usage des piaisirs by Editions Gallimard. Copyright © 1984 by Editions Gallimard. First American edition published by Pantheon Books, a division of Random House, Inc., in October 1985. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Foucault, Michel. The history of sexuality. Translation of Histoire de la sexualite. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. Contents: v. I. An introduction-v. 2. The use of pleasure. I. Sex customs-History-Collected works.
    [Show full text]
  • The Building Blocks of Anticipatory Pleasure: Prospection, Memory & Imagery by Janelle Marie Caponigro a Dissertation Subm
    The Building Blocks Of Anticipatory Pleasure: Prospection, Memory & Imagery By Janelle Marie Caponigro A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Psychology in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Ann Kring, Chair Professor Sheri Johnson Professor Jodi Halpern Fall 2015 Abstract The Building Blocks Of Anticipatory Pleasure: Prospection, Memory & Imagery by Janelle Marie Caponigro Doctor of Philosophy in Psychology University of California, Berkeley Professor Ann Kring, Chair Anticipatory pleasure deficits have been recently documented in people with schizophrenia (Kring & Caponigro, 2010). However, less is known about the extent to which particular processes that support anticipatory pleasure, including memory, prospection, and imagery, are disrupted in schizophrenia. We asked 32 people with schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorder and 29 people without schizophrenia to provide prospection narratives in response to positive, negative, and neutral event cues. Prior to prospection, participants provided personal memory narratives or completed a control task. When prompted with salient event cues, the content and experience of personal memories rendered by people with schizophrenia did not differ from those of controls. Further, people with and without schizophrenia reported similar vividness of mental imagery and their prospections varied by valence in similar ways. However, we found interesting group differences
    [Show full text]
  • Reward and Emotion: an Affective Neuroscience Approach
    Reward and emotion: An affective neuroscience approach David Sander1 & Lauri Nummenmaa2 1Swiss Center for Affective Sciences (CISA), Campus Biotech, and Laboratory for the Study of Emotion Elicitation and Expression, Department of Psychology, Faculty of Psychology and Educational Sciences (FPSE), University of Geneva, Geneva, Switzerland 2TurKu PET Centre, TurKu University Hospital, and Department of Psychology, University of TurKu, Finland Address Correspondence to: Lauri Nummenmaa Turku PET Centre c/o Turku University Hospital FI-20520 Turku, Finland Email: [email protected] Tel: +358 50 574 7933 Acknowlegements This study was supported by the Academy oF Finland (grants #294897 and #332225), Sigrid Juselius stiftelse and Signe och Anet Gyllenberg’s stiftelse, and by the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant 100019_188966). DS and LN thank Brian Knutson For in-depth discussions concerning several aspects of this paper. Conflicts of interest None Abstract Pleasure and reward are central for motivation, learning, feeling and allostasis. Although reward is without any doubt an affective phenomenon, there is no consensus concerning its relationship with emotion. In this mini-review we discuss this conceptual issue both from the perspective of theories of reward and emotion as well as human systems neuroimaging. We first describe how the reward process can be understood and dissected as intertwined with the emotion process, in particular in light of the appraisal theories, and then discuss how different facets of the reward process can be studied using neuroimaging and neurostimulation techniques. We conclude that future worK needs to focus on mapping the similarities and differences across stimuli and mechanisms that are involved in reward processing and in emotional processing, and propose that an integrative affective sciences approach would provide means for studying the emotional nature of reward.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophies of Happiness Appendix 4: Aristotle: Pleasure Without
    Philosophies of Happiness Appendix 4: Aristotle: Pleasure Without Sensation In Book 3.10, Aristotle attributes pleasure to thinking (dianoia); he writes that though the lover of honor or learning enjoys or takes pleasure (khairei) in the thing he loves, his body is not affected at all, only his thought.i As contemporary Aristotelian scholar J.O. Urmson notes, “this remark puzzled the commentator Aspasius to the point of exasperation: ‘What does he mean,’ he protests, ‘when he says that the enjoyment of lovers of learning or honour involves a condition of the intelligence? For enjoyment and the pleasures are not in the intelligence but in the affective (pathetiko) part of the soul.’” Urmson then comments: “Aspasius never understands Aristotle's view that enjoyment of learning is exhibited in the effortless concentration of the intelligence on its problems rather than in getting some feeling as a result or concomitant of one's study.”ii In other words, Aristotle held a “modal” rather than a “sensate” view of pleasure; pleasure is a mode of engaging in activity, rather than a feeling experienced as a result of activity. When the activity is a sensory one, Aristotle regards pleasure as the enjoyment of sensation, rather than as itself a sensation.iii Thus, although in 1.8, he does say that pleasure is among the things “of the soul,”iv the passage in 3.10 suggests that a thinking being without soul can take pleasure in whatever way it can think without an organ of thought, through understanding (nous) alone. Pleasure does not require sensation; we may take pleasure in a physical sensation, but Aristotle does not seem to regard physical sensation itself as pleasure.
    [Show full text]
  • Pleasure and Emotion in Sad Music Listening Experiences
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-10-2021 Moved by Sad Music: Pleasure and Emotion in Sad Music Listening Experiences Matthew Dunaway Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Dunaway, Matthew, "Moved by Sad Music: Pleasure and Emotion in Sad Music Listening Experiences." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2021. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/304 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Moved by Sad Music: Pleasure and Emotion in Sad Music Listening Experiences by Matthew Dunaway Under the Direction of Andrea Scarantino, PhD A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the College of Arts and Sciences Georgia State University 2021 ABSTRACT In this thesis, I consider the dialectic surrounding the Puzzle of Musical Tragedy i.e. why do people listen to sad music that makes them sad? I agree with Sizer (2019) that the best solutions to this puzzle construe the listening experience itself as pleasant. However, against Sizer, I argue that the feelings music induces are best construed as emotions, not moods. Since sad music can promote the perception of a sad person, I argue that music can be an unconscious object of one’s sad feelings. This suggests that sadness – not sad mood – best characterizes the experience of listening to sad music.
    [Show full text]
  • Music, Feelings, and the Human Brain
    Psychomusicology: Music, Mind, and Brain © 2014 American Psychological Association 2014, Vol. 24, No. 1, 92–102 0275-3987/14/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/pmu0000033 Music, Feelings, and the Human Brain Assal Habibi and Antonio Damasio University of Southern California Music of varied kinds consistently triggers a large range of drives and emotions, which, in turn, induce a particular class of mental experiences known as feelings. The feelings are often pleasurable, though not necessarily. Neuroimaging and electrophysiological studies, in normal individuals as well as in patients with focal neurological lesions, reveal that music can change the state of large-scale neural systems of the human brain. The changes are not confined to brain sectors related to auditory and motor processing; they also occur in regions related to the regulation of life processes (homeostasis), including those related to emotions and feelings, most prominently in the insula and cingulate cortices, in the ventral striatum, in the amygdala, and in certain upper brainstem nuclei. The ease with which music leads to feelings, the predictability with which it does so, the fact that human beings of many cultures actively seek and consume music, and the evidence that early humans engaged in music practices lead us to hypothesize that music has long had a consistent relation to the neural devices of human life regulation. It is conceivable that, as a result, music-induced feelings can be informative and nourishing at the individual level and can also operate as significant promoters of sociocultural organization. We venture that the close relationship between music and feelings along with music’s effectiveness in certain personal and social contexts, that is, its roles in homeostasis, explain, at least in part, the considerable degree of selection and replication of music-related phenomena, both biologically and culturally.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Sentience and Emotions
    Animal Sentience and Emotions: The Argument for Universal Acceptance © iStock.com/TheImaginaryDuck © iStock.com/Eriko Hume © iStock.com/Eriko © iStock.com/global_explorer © iStock.com/Delpixart Prepared by Ingrid L. Taylor, D.V.M. Research Associate, Laboratory Investigations Department 1 People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals | 2021 © iStock.com/Jérémy Stenuit than “learning and memory.”4 Thus, in observations of Introduction animal behavior, descriptive labels that did not attribute any intentionality were acceptable. Noted primatologist Frans de Though the fact of animal sentience is implicit in Waal describes how, when he observed the way chimpanzees experimentation,1 researchers have traditionally downplayed would reconcile with a kiss after a fight, he was pressured to and ignored certain aspects of it, and in nonvertebrate use the phrase “postconflict reunions with mouth-to-mouth species they have often denied it altogether. While it is contact” rather than the terms “reconciliation” and “kiss.” established that vertebrate animals feel pain and respond to He goes on to state that for three decades in primatology pain drugs in much the same ways that humans do,2 emotions research, simpler explanations had to be systematically such as joy, happiness, suffering, empathy, and fear have countered before the term “reconciliation” was accepted often been ignored, despite the fact that many psychological in situations in which primates quite obviously “monitored and behavioral experiments are predicated on the assumption and repaired social relationships.”5 De Waal notes that this that animals feel these emotions and will consistently react dependence on descriptive labels, i.e., that animals can be based on these feelings.
    [Show full text]
  • An Affective Neuroscience Model of Boosting Resilience in Adults
    An Affective Neuroscience Model of Boosting Resilience in Adults Golnaz Tabibnia University of California, Irvine Correspondence should be addressed to: Golnaz Tabibnia Department of Psychological Science University of California, Irvine 4201 Social and Behavioral Sciences Gateway Irvine, CA 92697 (949) 824-3002 Fax [email protected] Page 1 of 123 Abstract Although research has identified dozens of behavioral and psychosocial strategies for boosting resilience in adults, little is known about the common underlying pathways. A comprehensive review of these strategies using an affective neuroscience approach indicates three distinct general routes to resilience (Fig. 1A): 1) down-regulating the negative (e.g., exposure, cognitive reappraisal) by reducing distress-related responses of the amygdala, hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal axis, and autonomic nervous system; 2) up-regulating the positive (e.g., optimism, social connectedness) by activating mesostriatal reward pathways, which in turn can buffer the effects of stress; and 3) transcending the self (e.g., mindfulness, religious engagement) by reducing activation in the default mode network, a network associated with self-reflection, mind-wandering, and rumination. Some strategies (e.g., social support) can boost resilience via more than one pathway. Under- or over-stimulation of a pathway can result in vulnerability, such as over- stimulation of the reward pathway through substance abuse. This tripartite model of resilience-building is testable, accounts for a large body of data on adult resilience, and makes new predictions with implications for practice. Keywords: resilience; well-being; emotion regulation; affective neuroscience; amygdala; stress; reward; default mode Page 2 of 123 1. Introduction Whether surviving a natural disaster, loss of a loved one, or violence, most people experience a traumatic event at some point in their lives.
    [Show full text]