Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.Indb

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.Indb EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT ALSO AVAILABLE FROM BLOOMSBURY Kant’s Transition Project and Late Philosophy , Oliver Th orndike Kant on Spontaneity , Marco Sgarbi Th e Visibility of the Image , Lambert Wiesing Aesthetics, Arts, and Politics in a Global World , Daniel Herwitz EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT MARIA BORGES BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square, London, WC1B 3DP, UK 1385 Broadway, New York, NY 10018, USA BLOOMSBURY, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in Great Britain 2019 Copyright © Maria Borges, 2019 Maria Borges has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identifi ed as Author of this work. For legal purposes the Acknowledgments on p. viii constitute an extension of this copyright page. Cover design by Maria Rajka Cover image: Immanuel Kant, German philosopher, historical illustration, 1859 © Alamy Stock Photo Cover illustration (background) © Getty Images This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution Non-commercial No Derivatives Licence. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher. Bloomsbury Publishing Plc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any third-party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in this book were correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher regret any inconvenience caused if addresses have changed or sites have ceased to exist, but can accept no responsibility for any such changes. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN: HB: 978-1-3500-7836-9 ePDF: 978-1-3500-7837-6 eBook: 978-1-3500-7838-3 Typeset by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India To fi nd out more about our authors and books visit www.bloomsbury.com and sign up for our newsletters. To Laydes and Paulo Borges (in memoriam) CONTENTS Acknowledgments viii Abbreviations ix Translations x Introduction 1 1 Action, reason, and causes in Kant 5 2 Can we act without feelings? Respect, sympathy, and other forms of love 35 3 A place for aff ects and passion in the Kantian system 61 4 What can Kant teach us about emotions? 85 5 Physiology and the controlling of aff ects in Kant’s philosophy 105 6 Kantian virtue as a cure for aff ects and passions 125 7 Th e beautiful and the good: Refi nement as a propaedeutic to morality 139 8 Women and emotion 153 9 Evil and passions 165 Conclusion: An emotional Kant? 179 N o t e s 183 B i b l i o g r a p h y 198 Index 202 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I began to write this book in 1999 during my stay as a visiting scholar at the University of Pennsylvania, supported by a CAPES/Brazil fellowship. I would like to thank Paul Guyer for his suggestions and comments on the earlier versions of some chapters, and the former Kant Group of the Department of Philosophy of the University of Pennsylvania, especially Julian Wuerth, Cynthia Schossberger, Lucas Th orpe, and James Trainor. Some parts of the book were written during my stay at the Humboldt Universit ä t, Berlin, from 2006 to May 2007, supported by a CAPES fellowship. I would like to thank Rolf Peter Horstmann, Dina Edmundts, Tobias Rosefeldt, Stefanie Gr ü ne, and Brendan Th eunissen for their discussion of my ideas. Th is book was fi nally fi nished at Columbia University, where I spent a semester in 2014. I want to thank Patricia Kitcher for that. I would also like to thank my university, the University of Santa Catarina, for the leaves that made it possible to write this book and CAPES for the scholarship that allowed me to live abroad. I thank the CNPQ, which gave me a grant in Brazil, and the Brazilian government for its educational incentives. I would also like to thank Robert Louden, Gary Hatfi eld, Jeniff er Mensh, Karl Ameriks, the late Valerio Rohden, Zeljko Loparic, Guido de Almeida, Christian Hamnn, Andre Klaudat, Alfredo Storck, J ú lio Esteves, the late Juan Bonacinni, Vera Bueno, Vin í cius Figueiredo, Christian Hamm, Virg í nia Figueiredo, Pedro Rego, and the late Cl é lia Martins, Daniel Omar Perez, who helped me to improve this book through the discussion of the earlier versions of some chapters. I would like to thank my colleagues Delamar Dutra, Darlei Dall'Agnol, Luiz Henrique Dutra, Marco Frangiotti, Alessandro Pinzani, and Claudia Drucker for their discussion of some issues in the book. I am also very grateful to Alvaro Prata for his intellectual encouragement and to Pablo Muchnik who stimulated me to publish this book. ABBREVIATIONS Kant sources Kants gesammelte Schrift en ( K ö niglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaft en , Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900–). A n t M Anthropologie Mrongovius (1784/85) (AA 25) A n t Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht (AA 7) AntC Anthropologie Collins (1772/73) (AA 25) AntPa Anthropologie Parow (1772/73) (AA 25) G Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (AA 4) KpV Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (AA 5) M Vorlesungen ü ber Metaphysik (AA 28, 29) M M Metaphysik Mrongovius (AA 28) M S Metaphysik der Sitten (AA 6) R e k Rektoratsrede (AA 15) R e l Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (AA 6) T L Tugendlehre V E Vorlesungen ü ber Ethik (AA 27) Th e Critique of Pure Reason (KrV) will be cited according to the editions A (fi rst edition) and B (second edition). TRANSLATIONS I used the translation of the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, with the exception of the Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View , for which I used Victor Dowdell’s translation, in: Kant, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View , Southern Illinois University Press, 1978. Introduction Th is is a book about practical reason, action, and emotion in Kant. My aim is to answer what is the real importance of emotion for Kant. I will try to show that Kant had considerable views about emotions and that he was not blind to their importance in action in general. My object is not moral action, but action in general, including weak and even evil ones. My purpose is to show that Kant dedicated a considerable part of his work to the study of the relation between reason and emotion. In Chapter 1, I analyze Kant’s theory of action and what can count as a reason for or cause of an action. First, I begin with the distinction between motiva and stimulus in the pre-critical lessons on ethics and metaphysics. In the Groundwork , Kant explains this distinction in terms of objective and subjective grounds for actions: the motive (Bewegungsgrund ) is the objective ground of an action and the incentive (Triebfeder ) is the subjective one. Next, I analyze the possibility of the overdetermination of actions, understood as the possibility of two possible causes for the same action. I will argue that according to the incorporation thesis, there is only one motive for an action. Second, I try to reconcile the weakness of the will and the incorporation thesis. I will show that, according to the incorporation thesis, Kant is committed to a strong thesis concerning causation of actions. Reason and only reason can be the cause of an action. If we accept weakness, however, we must have a humbler solution to the Kantian theory of action: the domain of rational agency does not have the same extension of voluntary action. In the model of rational agency there is no room for weakness, although it is a fact in real actions. Th e domain of the voluntary is, then, wider than the 2 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT domain of rational agency. Th e weakness of the will applies to the fi rst and the incorporation thesis applies only to the second. In Chapter 2, I shall analyze whether human beings can act morally without being moved by sensible feelings. I will show that the answer in the Critique of Pure Reason , the Groundwork , and the Critical of Practical Reason is undoubtedly yes, but that Kant is ambiguous in Th e Metaphysics of Morals and also in the Anthropology . In the Metaphysics of Morals , Kant claims that there are some sensible conditions for the reception of the concept of duty: moral feeling, conscience, love of one’s neighbor, and respect for one self (self- esteem). I examine moral feeling and the love of human beings, trying to fi gure out whether or not they are necessary sensible preconditions for moral actions. In Chapter 3, I ask whether there is a place for aff ects and passions in the Kantian system. I intend to show that this place is the empirical part of morals, which can be understood as anthropology. I follow the development of the idea of anthropology in Kant’s moral works, showing the division between a moral metaphysics and a practical anthropology, aiming at exploring the impure part of Kantian ethics. I also try to compare the concepts of practical anthropology, pragmatic anthropology, and transcendental anthropology. In Chapter 4, I analyze Kant’s theory of emotions and what he can teach us about them. I will challenge two models that have been used to explain his theory. I begin with Sabini/Silver’s position, according to which emotions for Kant follow the pain model: they are precognitive and involuntary phenomena. Next, I analyze Baron’s objection, according to which Kant held that we are responsible for our emotions.
Recommended publications
  • Humanitas–Clementia and Clementia Caesaris Ancient and Modern Caesar
    European Journal of Science and Theology, September 2012, Vol.8, No.3, 263-269 _______________________________________________________________________ HUMANITAS–CLEMENTIA AND CLEMENTIA CAESARIS ANCIENT AND MODERN CAESAR Iulian-Gabriel Hruşcă* Romanian Academy, Iasi Branch, Str. T. Codrescu, Nr. 2, Iasi, Romania (Received 11 May 2012) Abstract Humanitas Romana is a concept that crosses both the Republican age of Rome and the Roman imperial period. In the Republic, clementia was both a personal attribute and a public virtue, intended to differentiate the Romans from the other peoples of antiquity in a sense of a moral superiority. In the Roman imperial period, the concept of humanitas Romana began to manifest more and more significantly through its component part, clementia, which became a cardinal virtue of the emperor and a judicial principle. With the coming to power of Julius Caesar, the notion of Clementia Caesaris was born. Afterwards, the status of Clementia Caesaris was enhanced during the Principate of Augustus. The emperor tends to become a provider of human rights. In a certain respect, if we refer to the principles of democracy, this transfer of the centre of gravity to the emperor in terms of human rights is negative. However, we could not assert that at that time were only negative aspects. We might consider as positive aspects the evolution of the concept of humanitas Romana through its component, the virtue of clementia, or the increased multicultural side of the Roman state. Despite the negative perception of Rome today, the clemency of ancient Caesar had reminiscences over time. The modern Caesar has tried to turn to Rome for lessons both positive and negative.
    [Show full text]
  • Idealizing Humanitas in Cicero's De Oratore, Or, Why Herbert O. Morrison
    Idealizing Humanitas in Cicero’s De oratore, or, why Herbert O. Morrison was wrong Taylor Putnam, 2016 Political Theory Research Workshop University of Toronto Working paper - please do not cite or circulate This paper draws primarily from material I intend to use in the introduction and first chapter of my dissertation, the latter of which will provide a more extensive account of Ciceronian humanitas against the backdrop of the waning Roman Republic. The larger dissertation project focuses on the concept of humanitas in the broader Roman context – traced through Cicero, Seneca the Younger, Tacitus, and Augustine - as a means to confront and challenge the modern understanding of “Humanity.” I greatly appreciate any and all feedback people are willing to share. Oh, my, get out of the way, please! It's burning and bursting into flames, and the - and it's falling on the mooring-mast and all the folks agree that this is terrible, this is one of the worst catastrophes in the world. […] It's–it's–it's the flames, […] oh, four- or five-hundred feet into the sky and it ... it's a terrific crash, ladies and gentlemen. It's smoke, and it's flames now ... and the frame is crashing to the ground, not quite to the mooring-mast. Oh, the humanity and all the passengers screaming around here. I told you, I can't even talk to people whose friends are on there. Ah! It's–it's–it's–it's ... o–ohhh! I–I can't talk, ladies and gentlemen. Honest, it's just laying there, a mass of smoking wreckage.
    [Show full text]
  • The Self-Sufficiency of the Good Man Against the Need for Friendship
    THE SELF-SUFFICIENCY OF THE GOOD MAN AGAINST THE NEED FOR FRIENDSHIP. A DISCUSSION CONCERNING THE IMPORTANCE OF FRIENDSHIP FOR THE GOOD MAN IN CICERO. CORY SLOAN SUBMITTED WITH A VIEW TO OBTAIN THE DEGREE OF M.LITT. NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF IRELAND, MAYNOOTH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, FACULTY OR ARTS, CELTIC STUDIES, AND PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2012 HEAD OF DEPARTMENT DR. MICHAEL DUNNE SUPERVISED BY DR. AMOS EDELHEIT 1 Summary Cicero wrote in Book Three of On Duties, that the Stoic sage being absolutely good and and perfect was the only one that could be truly happy. For his happiness was based in his virtue and as he had perfect virtue, he had perfect and lasting happiness. Yet the Peripatetics saw that happiness was not a self-sufficient idea and was instead an amalgamation of external goods. Virtue for them was a factor that contributed to happiness, for the Stoics it was essential for happiness. It would appear on inital observation that the life of the Stoic sage was a solitary one, aloof from the rest of humanity. Yet the Stoics maintained that this was the best and happiest form of life, a life lived in accordance with Nature. However, the Peripatetics maintained that nature loves nothing solitary and man is not a solitary animal. In order for him to fullfill his natural end and achieve eudaimonia he would natually be drawn towards the company of others. Cicero highlights the tension between Stoic idealism and Peripatetic pragmatism in his discussion on happiness. When he essentially he askes in Book Five of the Tusculan Disputations.
    [Show full text]
  • Hispanism and Humanitas in the Market University
    u 7 Hispanism and Humanitas in the Market University David R. Castillo and William Egginton As we look back at the inaugural volume of the now well-established Hispanic Issues On Line series, we are struck by the remarkable degree of disciplinary self-awareness displayed by the volume contributors, and also by their willingness to air Hispanism’s dirty laundry, so to speak, in their quest to expose and transcend internal divides and potentially paralyzing forms of institutional inertia. Indeed, the range of the discussion is nothing short of unprecedented in this type of essay collection, moving from questions of object selection and the place of canonical texts vis-à-vis underrepresented fields and constituents, to geo-political rifts, most notoriously between the Peninsular and Latin American sub-disciplines and/or between center and margins, to methodological debates on the relative merits of philological, historicist, and theoretical approaches, and the promise of new horizons of plurality and inclusion associated with the rise of transnational and transdisciplinary directions. While these debates and the issues that animate them have not lost currency, they seem to have receded into the background in recent years within the circles of Hispanic Studies in the United States. This may be due, in part, to the emergence of a “quiet” consensus around the notion that the existence of a plurality of perspectives, different interpretive methodologies, and differing political views is ultimately a sign of disciplinary health. Yet, we would argue that the withering of internal debates within Hispanism, as with other literary, linguistic and artistic fields, and indeed other Humanities and Social Science disciplines, such as Media Studies and History is also, to a large extent, a byproduct of the “survival mode” in which we find ourselves since the latest proclamation of crisis for the Humanities.
    [Show full text]
  • Epictetus, Stoicism, and Slavery
    Epictetus, Stoicism, and Slavery Defense Date: March 29, 2011 By: Angela Marie Funk Classics Department Advisor: Dr. Peter Hunt (Classics) Committee: Dr. Jacqueline Elliott (Classics) and Dr. Claudia Mills (Philosophy) Funk 1 Abstract: Epictetus was an ex-slave and a leading Stoic philosopher in the Roman Empire during the second-century. His devoted student, Arrian, recorded Epictetus’ lectures and conversations in eight books titled Discourses, of which only four are extant. As an ex- slave and teacher, one expects to see him deal with the topic of slavery and freedom in great detail. However, few scholars have researched the relationship of Epictetus’ personal life and his views on slavery. In order to understand Epictetus’ perspective, it is essential to understand the political culture of his day and the social views on slavery. During his early years, Epictetus lived in Rome and was Epaphroditus’ slave. Epaphroditus was an abusive master, who served Nero as an administrative secretary. Around the same period, Seneca was a tutor and advisor to Nero. He was a Stoic philosopher, who counseled Nero on political issues and advocated the practice of clemency. In the mid to late first-century, Seneca spoke for a fair and kind treatment of slaves. He held a powerful position not only as an advisor to Nero, but also as a senator. While he promoted the humane treatment of slaves, he did not actively work to abolish slavery. Epaphroditus and Seneca both had profound influences in the way Epictetus viewed slaves and ex-slaves, relationships of former slaves and masters, and the meaning of freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Renaissance Humanism in Shakepeare's Plays
    [VOLUME 3 I ISSUE 3 I JULY – SEPT. 2016] e ISSN 2348 –1269, Print ISSN 2349-5138 http://ijrar.com/ IJRAR Impact Factor 3.215 Renaissance Humanism in Shakepeare’s plays Dr. Sunita Nimavat Assistant Professor of English N.P.College of Computer & Mgt., Kadi (North Gujarat). Received July 02, 2016 Accepted July 25, 2016 ABSTRACT The term ‘humanism’ is complex but enlightening. It was first employed by German philosophers for the Renaissance emphasizes on classical studies of Greek philosophy and literature. It included the study of poetry, rhetoric, history and moral philosophy The Latin Word ‘humanitas’ denoted the development of human virtues to their fullest extent. These virtues were understanding, benevolence, compassion, mercy, prudence, fortitude, eloquence and even love for honor.In this paper, I will start with the source of the word Humanism. Then I will focus on views of different people and eras on Humanism e.g. Renaissance influenced literature, politics, education, scientific and rational outlook while Greeks glorified human body, human nature and human virtues influencing literature, politics, education, scientific and rational outlook in sixteenth century. Then I have focused on the outcomes of Humanism and its effect seen on different ages. Then I have focused on the contribution and expression of Humanism in the works of various writers and Shakespeare in Particular. Many scholars, thinkers and writers began to explore the untrodden territory of knowledge. Plato , Petrarch, Aristotle, Dante, Machiavelli, Cicero and other thinkers became the guiding angels for many thinkers who have been referred to in my paper. I have referred to various works where we find humanism e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Transhumanism, Post-Humanism, and Human Technological Enhancement Whither Goes Humanitas? Gregory J
    Volume 8, No 2, Fall 2013 ISSN 1932-1066 Transhumanism, Post-Humanism, and Human Technological Enhancement Whither goes Humanitas? Gregory J. Walters [email protected] Abstract: This essay introduces seven articles on transhumanity from a Jaspersian perspective, briefly discusses the meaning, nature, and scope of transhumanist and post-humanist philosophies in relation to Jaspers' philosophy of the encompassing, and critically engages some key ideas concerning enhancement technologies and enhanced human/ trans/post-human beings in the current historical situation. Possible posthuman Existenz remains an open possibility. Keywords: Transhumanism; transhuman; post-humanism; post-human; human; humanitas; technology; technological enhancement; Jaspers, Karl; possible Existenz; Kass, Leon; Sandel, Michael J.; bioconservatives; futurology; social inequality; economic inequality; life expectancy; equality; public health; social determinants of health; humaneness; care; dehumanization. As a finite living creature man is subject to the phases of On March 30, 2013, the Karl Jaspers Society of North growth, maturity and ageing and also to death. But this America, meeting in conjunction with the American sequence of age in man can at the same time contain the progress of his freedom manifesting itself in Time. Philosophical Association annual Pacific Division Man in his finiteness stands within the infinite. There can be meeting (San Francisco, CA), hosted a group session no lasting coincidence of the two in Time. Only the moment on the topic: "The Future of Humanity and the provides a place where both meet in order to break the finite Question of Post-Humanity."2 The articles published phenomenon apart once more. Hence all human activity in this volume of Existenz uniquely address the and thought is at the service of something incomprehensible within which it operates and by which it is absorbed and meaning, nature, and scope of transhumanist and post- overborne whether we like to call it fate or providence.
    [Show full text]
  • HUMANITAS Readings in the Development of the Medical Humanities Perspectives in Medical Humanities
    HUMANITAS Readings in the Development of the Medical Humanities Perspectives in Medical Humanities Perspectives in Medical Humanities publishes scholarship produced or reviewed under the auspices of the University of California Medical Humanities Consortium, a multi-campus collaborative of faculty, students and trainees in the humanities, medicine, and health sciences. Our series invites scholars from the humanities and health care professions to share narra- tives and analysis on health, healing, and the contexts of our beliefs and practices that impact biomedical inquiry. General Editor Brian Dolan, PhD, Professor of Social Medicine and Medical Humanities, University of California, San Francisco (UCSF) Recent Titles Health Citizenship: Essays in Social Medicine and Biomedical Politics By Dorothy Porter (Winter 2012) What to Read on Love, Not Sex: Freud, Fiction, and the Articulation of Truth in Modern Psychological Science By Edison Miyawaki, MD, Foreword by Harold Bloom (Fall 2012) Patient Poets: Illness from Inside Out Marilyn Chandler McEntyre (Fall 2012) (Pedagogy in Medical Humanities series) Bioethics and Medical Issues in Literature Mahala Yates Stripling (Fall 2013) (Pedagogy in Medical Humanities series) Heart Murmurs: What Patients Teach their Doctors Edited by Sharon Dobie, MD (Fall 2014) www.UCMedicalHumanitiesPress.com [email protected] This series is made possible by the generous support of the Dean of the School of Medicine at UCSF, the Center for Humanities and Health Sciences at UCSF, and a University of California Research Initiative, Grant ID 141374. HUMANITAS Readings in the Development of the Medical Humanities Edited by Brian Dolan First published in 2015 by the University of California Medical Humanities Press UCMedicalHumanitiesPress.com © 2015 University of California Medical Humanities Consortium 3333 California Street, Suite 485 San Francisco, CA 94143-0850 Designed by Virtuoso Press Cover photo courtesy of the Wellcome Library, London.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and the Enlightenment
    Kant and The Enlightenment Antonio Pele Assistant Professor in Legal Philosophy Universidad Carlos III de Madrid [email protected] Published in: Philosophical and humanistic postmodern views : international scientific conference : Iasi,̧ 21st of May – 3rd of June 2012 / coord.: Ana Caras, Elena Unguru. - Iasi̧ : Lumen, 2012 ISBN 978-973-166-336-4, pp. 493-506 Abstract This paper aims to understand Kant’s conception of Enlightenment and, in particular the idea of “Sapere Aude” (dare to think for yourself), described in his article published in 1784 An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment ? where he defines pre-enlightened people as living in a self-imposed “minority”. In the first part of the article, I will develop this notion, along with a process of domestication of human beings. In the second part, I will examine the solutions proposed to overcome this situation, with particular emphasis on the development by the State, of the so-called “public use of reason”. Key-words Kant, Enlightenment, Sapere Aude, Reason, Philosophy 1 Introduction Kant’s ideas on the Enlightenment are especially prevalent in his well-known article “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” published in the Berlinishe Monatsschrift (a monthly journal published in Berlin) in December of 1784. As its title indicates, it is an answer to a question that the reverend Zöllner posed one year earlier in the same journal. For Foucault, Kant’s article will have important consequences in relation to modern philosophy, not only for its attempt to define the Enlightenment, but most importantly for connecting philosophy to its present and for being “at the crossroads of critical reflection and reflection on history.
    [Show full text]
  • History, Reason and Hope: a Comparative Study of Kant, Hayek and Habermas
    Dialogue on Personal and Political Ethics History, Reason and Hope: A Comparative Study of Kant, Hayek and Habermas Richard B. Day University of Toronto In the Critique of Practical Reason, Immanuel Kant expressed awe Every human and admiration for “the starred heaven above me and the moral consciousness law within me”. With reference to the heavens, Kant was struck contains by human insignificance in “the incalculable vastness of worlds universality of the moral law. upon worlds, of systems within systems, over endless ages”. Within this sensible order of cosmic proportions, man appeared to be but an “animal-like being”, condemned to return to the dust of a planet which itself is “a mere speck in the universe”. At the same time, however, Kant believed that every human consciousness contains within itself the universality of the moral law. As intelli- gible beings, we live “a life independent of animality and even of the entire world of sense”. The moral law elevates human exist- ence into “a world . which can be sensed only by the intellect”. Moral self-determination, said Kant, “radiates into the infinite”.1 Lucien Goldmann’s interpretation of Kant emphasizes the need to overcome this division between the sensible and intelligible do- mains. Kant conceived moral autonomy as an attribute of rational individuals, but he also contemplated a universal community, in- tegrated through the practical Idea of human freedom—an “ethi- cal commonwealth” and a “kingdom of ends”. Goldmann argues that the absolute necessity of realizing this totality is “the centre 1 Carl J. Friedrich, ed., The Philosophy of Kant: Immanuel Kant’s Moral and Po- litical Writings (New York: Modern Library, 1949), 261-62.
    [Show full text]
  • Temperament 67 Relationship Between Temperament and Humours 73 Tissues, Organs, Energies, Faculties and Functions 74 an Integrated System 77
    I DISCLAIMER This book is a reference work not intended to treat, diagnose, or prescribe. The information contained herein is in no way to be considered as a substitute for consultation with a healthcare professional. First Edition in July 2000 (2000 copies) Second Edition (Revised) May 2001 (5000 Copies) Electronic Edition (Revised) January 2014 II - Dedication – This book is dedicated to the memory of my late parents Hassen Ebrahim Bhikha & Amina Mohamed Dockrat. III - Tibb Traditional Roots of Medicine in Modern Routes to Health – A Product of the Ibn Sina Institute of Tibb The Ibn Sina Institute of Tibb is a non-profit organization operating as a trust (waqf). The Institute was founded by the Bhikha Family Trust and is academically supported by the Hamdard University (Pakistan), Aligarh University and Jamiah Hamdard (India). P.O. Box 43209 Industria, 2042 Gauteng, South Africa Tel: 27-11-991-7300 Email address: [email protected] Website: www.tibb.co.za IV Contents Contents Introduction 1 Chapter One 7 Why modern medicine cannot give you the whole picture! 7 Holism 11 The early rise of holistic medicine 13 The rise of scientific western medicine 15 Rediscovering the ancient wisdom of holistic medicine 22 Evaluating alternative therapies 25 Chapter Two Traditional Roots of Medicine in Modern Routes to Health 29 Muslim contributions to medicine 30 A brief history of Ibn Sina and the formulation of Tibb 33 Conclusion 36 Chapter Three 40 The Path to Health 40 Defining health holistically 41 Physis - The organizing principle 48 Chapter Four The relationship between personality and illness 57 A 15-billion-year-old energy conservation program 57 V Contents An economy of energy 59 Heat and Moisture 60 Humours 64 Temperament 67 Relationship between Temperament and Humours 73 Tissues, organs, energies, faculties and functions 74 An Integrated System 77 Chapter Five 79 Six Factors Determining Health 79 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Evaluating Steiner's Understanding of Temperament Using the EAS Survey
    Evaluating Steiner’s Understanding of Temperament using the EAS Survey Lena Mueller A thesis submitted to Auckland University of Technology in fulfilment of the requirements for a degree of Master of Education Faculty of Culture and Society 2017 I Abstract Over the last hundred years, Steiner education has become established in countries around the world. One of the key concepts of this enduring pedagogy is that of the temperaments, though it has been criticised for being outmoded and unsupported by empirical research. This study will assess and evaluate potential correlations between Steiner teachers’ understanding of the temperaments and the results gained from using Buss’ and Plomin’s Emotionality, Activity and Sociability/Shyness (EAS) survey. Data will be collected by surveying parents and teachers, as well as holding teacher interviews. This data will allow potential similarities and differences to be identified highlighting the degree to which Steiner’s century-old pedagogical ideas can be supported by a standard analytical tool. II Attestation of authorship I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and that, to the best of my knowledge and belief, it contains no material previously published or written by another person (except where explicitly defined in the acknowledgements), nor material which to a substantial extend has been submitted for the award of any other degree or diploma or a university or other institution of higher learning. Name: ___________________________ Signature: ________________________ III Acknowledgements I would like to thank a number of people for their support, encouragement and inspiration. Thank you to the Auckland University of Technology Ethics Committee (AUTEC) for granting consent to undertake this study; application number 17/381 accepted on the 19th September 2017.
    [Show full text]