Irrationality and the DSM-III-R Definition of Mental Disorder

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Irrationality and the DSM-III-R Definition of Mental Disorder Bernard Gert Irrationality and the DSM-III-R Definition of Mental Disorder Abstract: I provide an account of irrationality that takes the concept of an irrational action as more basic than that of an irrational belief. Whil e ex­ plaining the various elements of the OSM- 111-R definition of mental dis­ orders1 I show that even though ( x) not all mental disorders involve irrational beliefs or delusions1 (z) not all irrational actions are due to mental disorders, and (3) not all mental disorders Iead to irrational actions 1 there is a close conceptual connection between irrationality and mental disorders because both involve suffering or an increased risk of suffering an evil or harm, independent of the circumstances one is in. lrrationality and mental disorders are obviously related to each other, but before the exact nature of that relationship can be provided it is necessary to have a clear account of each of the concepts involved. Many philo­ sophers hold that the relationship between mental disorders and irrationa­ lity is Straightforward; mental disorders always involve irrational beliefs. But this is false1 not all mental disorders involve irrational beliefs, some involve irrational actions or desires without any irrational beliefs, e.g. 1 1 volitional disabilities such as compulsions and phobias. Further 1 many mental disorders do not involve any kind of irrationality at all but simply inappropriate suffering of anxiety or sadness or irritability, e.g. dys­ phoric moods (0, 401). However, this does not mean that there is not a close relationship between irrationality and mental disorders1 for irrationa­ lity and mental disorders are related at a deeper Ievel, both of them must be defined by means of the same Iist of evils or harms. Before beginning the generat discussion it is relevant to point out that delusions are equivalent to what I call irrational beliefs. The OSM- 111-R Glossary defines a delusion as "A personal false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality and firmly sustained in spite of what almost everyone eise believes and in spite of what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person•s culture or subculture (i.e., it is not an article of religious 10 faith) • ( 0 I 395) Analyse & Kritik 12 (1990), S. 34-46 Q Westdeutscher Verlag, Opladen lrrationality and the DSM- 11 1-R Definition of Mental Disorder 35 I define an irrational belief as follows: " (I) it is held by a person with sufficient knowledge and intelligence to know that it is false, (2) it is in confl ict, either logically o r empirically, with a great number of beliefs t hat one knows to be true, and (3) this conflict is apparent to almost all people with similar knowledge and intelligence." (Gert 1988, 2 1 ) lt is quite clear that t hese two definit io ns are attempts to. pick out the same beliefs, and that if they result in different beliefs being regarded as ir rational or as delusions , this would be taken as an indication that one or the ot her of t he definitions is inadequate. The Concept of lr rationality The concept of irrationality is one of the most fundamental concepts in philosophy. ln philosophy, as weil as in ordinary life, to show t hat an action, desire, or belief, is irrational is taken as showing that it should be avoided or given up. Whether it is explicitly acknowledged or not, most philosophers who put torward a descriptive account of an irrational action do so in order to condemn that way of acting. When they or anyone for whom they are concerned are considering acting in a certain way, showing that the action is ir rational is sufficient to r ule it out. That is wh y it is so important to have an accurate acoount of irrational actions . If one accepts an inadequate account of an irrational action, then one may rule out a certain way of acting t hat should not be ruled out or fail to rule out a wa y of acting t hat should be ruled out. lt is because of its normative implications that the concepts of rationality and irrationalit y are fu ndamental to morality and to any general theor y of value. I shall not deal with these matters here , but shall concentrate on providing an ad­ equate account of rational and irrational actions and showing how these are related to mental disorder s. •\1 ssc :II e •• p er ssse:mu ef u*ina' sud · ,. I reacare utae · ~ never actenaea, otz ., tll5 t Eile Biste aeli:aus::s at al- 1 5 ;rv ?Qd jssae;e p • )")) Jbbb h0 gi: 0 j 1 f d j , i.e., in some ....._.. way that mentions r p 'f'e e ::ss::a. Almost all economist s, political scientists, sociologists and contemporary Anglo­ American philosophers as diverse as .a...-k, in " ·u , id · tlr, ....,._, and ~. do not even consider the possibility that the basic definitions of rationality and irrationality must be given in terms of a specific content, e.g., a Iist, and that there is no formal way to generate that Iist. The failu re to even consider t hat the basic definitions of rationality and ir­ rationality must be given in terms of a Iist has resulted in all of the Standard accounts of rationality being seriously inadequate. Further, - Nt tl a saatrat ol'ows ;e 2 f alit; es bt t Ei!ltEU td ffi@hdii GISOl dCl S 111 tlie appup r f. Bernard Gert Definition of an Irrational Action People act irrationally when they act in ways that they lcnow (justifiably believe) or should lcnow, will significantly increase the probability that they, or those for whom they are concerned, will suffer any of the items on the following Iist: death, pain (including mental suffering), disability, loss of freedom, or loss of pleasure, and they do not have an adequate reason for so acting. A reason for acting is a conscious belief that one's action (or the rule or policy that requires the action) will significantly increase the probability either that someone will avoid suffering any of the items on the previous Iist or that they will gain greater ability, freedom or pleasure. This belief must not be irrational (a delusion). A reason (in this paper I use the term "reason" to mean a reason for acting) is adequate if any !arge group of otherwise rational persons (persons who do not signi­ ficantly increase their chances of suffering death, pain, etc., with no reason) regard what will be a voided or gained as at least as important as what will be suffered. All intentional actions that are not irrational count as rational (Gert 1988, eh . 2). This account of rational and irrational actions conflicts with much that economists, political scientists, philosophers and others have traditionally said about them, but it is the only account that allows us to use "ir­ rational" as the basic normative term, i.e., allows us to hold that no one should ever act irrationally. This use of "irrational" explains why irratio­ nality is such an important concept, fo r if we did not hold that no one ever ought to act irrationally, it wou ld malce sense to aslc "Why should one act rationally?". lj h ep ·a ••igl:t S:j EI: t s h I I t :af lly , and even be tempted *o o'hr 1 1:; c::e sl:cald acc Ii iitlbiially. This shows the confusion that arises once one gives up the view that irratio­ nality is the basic or fundamental normative concept. Chsu•rriaiA8 ~ro­ pose d 2' tios 18 itt&liöii&l iLLOClues a8oisiug tliöSC föt Nl:öiil c.>are c-gcecg•d not • I tl at äCtiöll. Contrary to what philosophers often main­ tain, characterizing an action as rational does not necessarily involve ad­ vising those for whom we are concerned to act in that way, for there are often two or more incompatible but rational ways of acting, e.g., vacation­ ing in the mountains versus at the sea shore. An action is rationally required only if not acting in that way is irrational, e.g., jumping out of the way of a speeding car. Most rational actions are merely rationally allowed, e.g., going to a play. We are often in Situations where all of the proposed alternatives are rational, e. g., choosing between alternative places to vacation. Rejectin g a rational way of acting does not mean one is choosing an irrational way of acting. That incompatible ways of acting can all be rational proves that a proposed Course of action can be rational and yet not everyone would advise their friends to do it. This shows that not all rational actions are lrrationality and the DSM-111-R Definition of Mental Disorder 37 rationally required, some are merely rationally allowed. We cannot be in a Situation where all of the alternatives are irrational. lt may have been irrational to get oneself into a situation where any alternative one chooses results in one's suffering death or pain, etc., but once one is in that situation, at least one of the alternatives has to be a rational one. For even if that alternative involves suffer ing death or pain, etc., it enables one to avoid suffering at least comparable evils, and so since one has an adequate reason for choosing that alternative, one's action is not ir­ rational.
Recommended publications
  • Lecture 10: Psychology of Probability: Predictable Irrationality
    Lecture 10: Psychology of probability: predictable irrationality. David Aldous October 5, 2017 Here are two extreme views of human rationality. (1) There is much evidence that people are not rational, in the economist's sense [maximization of expected utility (MEU)]. Some would argue we need descriptive economics; I would argue that all should be taught about probability, utility and MEU and act accordingly [Dennis Lindley, Understanding Uncertainty.] (2) You mentioned research which revealed that shoppers often prefer \50% extra free" to a notionally more generous 33% reduction in price, and you cited this as evidence of irrationality or poor mathematical ability on the part of consumers. Since all value is subjective, if people value 50% extra free more highly than 33% off, then that is an end of the matter. Whether or not the resulting behaviour conforms to some autistic neoclassical idea of rationality is irrelevant. [Rory Sutherland, Ogilvy & Mather UK. Letter to The Economist July 21 2012.] The 2011 best-seller Thinking, Fast and Slow by Nobel Prize winning Kahneman gives a wide-ranging and very non-technical account of human rationality and irrationality. The key point is that we're not arbitrarily irrational but that our intuition is \predictably irrational" (title of popular 2008 Ariely book) in ways one can describe. The part of this field relevant to STAT 157 concerns \decisions under uncertainty", which necessarily involves issues of probability and utility. Psychology research gets real data from real people, but the data mostly consists of subjects' answers to hypothetical limited explicit relevant data exam-style questions involving uncertainty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Biological Basis of Human Irrationality
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 119 041 CG 010 346 AUTHOR Ellis, Albert TITLE The Biological Basis of Human Irrationality. PUB DATE 31 Aug 75 NOTE 42p.; Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Psychological Association (83rd, Chicago, Illinois, August 30-September 2, 1975) Reproduced from best copy available EDRS PRICE MF-$0.83 HC-$2.06 Plus Postage DESCRIPTORS *Behavioral Science Research; *Behavior Patterns; *Biological Influences; Individual Psychology; *Psychological Patterns; *Psychological Studies; Psychotherapy; Speeches IDENTIFIERS *Irrationality ABSTRACT If we define irrationality as thought, emotidn, or behavior that leads to self-defeating consequences or that significantly interferes with the survival and happiness of the organism, we find that literally hundreds of major irrationalities exist in all societies and in virtually all humans in those societies. These irrationalities persist despite people's conscious determination to change; many of them oppose almost all the teachings of the individuals who follow them; they persist among highly intelligent, educated, and relatively undisturbed individuals; when people give them up, they usually replace them with other, sometimes just as extreme, irrationalities; people who strongly oppose them in principle nonetheless perpetuate them in practice; sharp insight into them or their origin hardly removes them; many of them appear to stem from autistic invention; they often seem to flow from deepseated and almost ineradicable tendencies toward human fallibility, overgeneralization, wishful thinking, gullibility, prejudice, and short-range hedonism; and they appear at least in part tied up with physiological, hereditary, and constitutional processes. Although we can as yet make no certain or unqualified claim for the biological basis of human irrationality, such a claim now has enough evidence behind it to merit serious consideration.
    [Show full text]
  • The Irrationality of Rationality
    7 THE IRRATIONALITY OF RATIONALITY Traffic Jams on Those “Happy Trails” distribute or cDonaldization has swept across the social landscape because it offers increased efficiency, predictability, calculability, and control. MDespite these advantages, as the preceding chapters have shown, McDonaldization has some serious disadvantages. Rational systems inevitably spawn irrationalities that limit,post, eventually compromise, and perhaps even undermine their rationality. The irrationality of rationality is simply a label for many of the negative aspects of McDonaldization. Irrationality can be seen as the opposite of rationality. Most generally, McDonaldization can be viewed as leading to inefficiency, unpredict- ability, incalculability, and loss of control.1 More specifically, the wider range of irrationalitiescopy, discussed in this chapter includes inefficiency, excessively high cost, false friendliness, disenchantment, health and environmental hazards, homog- enization, and dehumanization. Also discussed are the problems associated with notthe McJobs spawned by the process of McDonaldization. As problematic as those jobs are, perhaps even more of a problem is their loss as a result of nonhuman technologies (i.e., automation, robotization) replacing them. Most of this chapter, Do like Chapters 3 and 4, focuses on the irrationalities that confront consumers in McDonaldized settings. However, as in Chapters 5 and 6, we will also deal with the workers in these settings and the irrationalities associated with their occupa- tions, especially their McJobs. Irrationality also means that rational systems are 167 Copyright ©2019 by SAGE Publications, Inc. This work may not be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means without express written permission of the publisher. 168 The McDonaldization of Society disenchanted; they have lost their magic and mystery.
    [Show full text]
  • The Irrationality of Religious Beliefs
    The Irrationality of Religious Beliefs Published in Think 15, 15-33. Bryan Frances Abstract: Many highly educated people think religious belief is irrational and unscientific. If you ask a philosopher, however, you’ll likely get two answers: most religious belief is rational in some respects and irrational in other respects. In my previous essay I explained why they think so many religious beliefs are rational. In this essay I explain why they think those same beliefs are irrational. The charge of irrationality applied to religious belief could come from any of several distinct groups: philosophy professors who have studied rationality and religious belief for many years; intellectuals such as Richard Dawkins, Christopher Hitchens, Paul Zachary Myers, and Sam Harris who have serious intellectual training but virtually no serious study of rationality (which is a subset of epistemology); intelligent atheists with little intellectual training at all; or unintelligent atheists who foam at the mouth on blogs and in bars. Different groups bring significantly different charges under the heading ‘irrational’. In this essay I will be articulating what professional philosophers think on the matter, just like how I described in the previous essay the primary factors that professional philosophers think make much religious belief rational. For the most part I will not be commenting on the strength of the charges—that is, I won’t attempt to figure out whether the charges show that religious belief is irrational in any worrisome sense. As I mentioned in the first essay, my methodology of listening to voices in my head is flawed. Even so, I think nine of the most common philosophical complaints about the epistemic status of most religious belief (which are not always the ones that get published in professional philosophy journals and books) begin as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Humean Theory of Practical Irrationality
    THE HUMEAN THEORY OF PRACTICAL IRRATIONALITY BY NEIL SINHABABU JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 6, NO. 1 | NOVEMBER 2011 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT © NEIL SINHABABU 2011 JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY | VOL. 6, NO. 1 THE HUMEAN THEORY OF PRACTICAL IRRATIONALITY Neil Sinhababu The Humean Theory of Practical Irrationality Neil Sinhababu N “THE NORMATIVITY OF INSTRUMENTAL REASON,” Christine Korsgaard presents a problem for those who accept similarly I structured Humean views of both action and rationality.1 (I will call the conjunction of views she criticizes the double-Humean view.) Korsgaard contends that the double-Humean view implies the impossibility of irrational action, as it claims that we can only perform the actions that it deems rational. First I will develop Humean views of rationality and action so as to display the force of Korsgaard’s objection. Then I will respond by showing how double-Humeans can develop their view to account for just as much practical irrationality as there is. Double-Humeans can answer Korsgaard’s objection if their views of action and rationality measure agents’ actual desires differently. What determines what the agent does should be the motivational forces that desires produce in the agent at the moment when she decides to act. That is when her desires play their causal role in determining action. What determines what it is rational to do should be the agent’s dispositional desire strengths. Our normative intuitions about rationality concern these states. Since the action that desire motivates us most strongly to do at the moment of action may not be the action that would best satisfy our dispositional desires, irrational action is possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Crowd Psychology and American Culture, 1890-1940
    "Mental Epidemics": Crowd Psychology and American Culture, 1890-1940 Eugene E. Leach In 1900, disillusioned with high-powered newspaper work and weary of cities, progressive journalist Ray Stannard Baker quit New York and fled to Arizona. Going west to find himself was a gesture of affiliation sanctified by both national myth and his family folklore of pioneer stock ancestry and his father's move west to start over after failing in business. But the Arizona deserts had no power to heal him. In his memoirs he recounted a moment of reckoning with the omnipotence of crowds: he could not forget the congestion that lay just beyond the horizon. For better or worse, to him America was epitomized by suffocating New York: What a different world I knew from that of my ancestors! They had the wilderness, I had crowds. I found teeming, josding, restless cities; I found immense smoking, roaring industries; I found a labyrinth of tangled communication. I found hugeness and evil.1 Baker decided that learning to navigate this world of crowds would be "the prime test" of the modern citizen. E. A. Ross had a grimmer and more intellectualized encounter with crowds. In 1894, he jotted down "thirty-three distinct means by which society controls its members" in a list that became twenty American Journal of Sociology articles and the popular book Social Control (1901).2 Ross' work grew from his assumption, shared with Frederick Jackson Turner, that the closing of the frontier would 0026-3079/92/3301 -005$ 1.50/0 5 inaugurate a difficult new epoch for America.
    [Show full text]
  • Davidson on Irrationality and Division
    Davidson on Irrationality and Division Miguel Amen1, Abstract: Donald Davidson in ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality’ (1982) claims that to understand irrationality one has to postulate a divided mind, absent which one could not make sense of the phenomenon. Here I want to defend his position against some objections advanced by John Heil in ‘Divided Minds’. Heil has two complaints against Davidson’s theory; first he seems to believe that when we cash out the metaphor of a divided mind to give an account of irrationality, the result is an implausible picture; secondly that there are other models to explain irrationality that do not rely on Division. The idea is that even if the concept of a divided mind could be sufficient to explain irrationality it is not necessary one, and in view of the cumbersome nature of Davidson’s explanation it would seem altogether superfluous. This is a serious attack, but to my mind entirely misguided. In this Paper I will show why. First by showing that Heil seems to develop an erroneous account of division and the function of partitioning. Secondly by showing that Heil’s model is not consistent with important doctrines that he seems to accept and are central to Davidson. In the end Heil’s counterexample is a failure at explanation. Resumo: Em ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality’ Donald Davidson defende que para compreendermos a irracionalidade temos que postular uma mente divida, sem o que não conseguiremos dar sentido ao fenómeno. Neste artigo quero defender a posição de Davidson contra algumas objecções avançadas por John Heil em ‘Divided Minds’.
    [Show full text]
  • Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations
    Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 2015 Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations Dennis Whitcomb Western Washington University Heather Battaly California State University, Fullerton Jason Baehr Loyola Marymount University, [email protected] Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/phil_fac Part of the Epistemology Commons, and the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Baehr, Jason, Dennis Whitcomb, Heather Battaly, and Dan Howard-Snyder. “Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2015), doi: 10.1111/phpr.12228. This Article - pre-print is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Digital Commons @ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons@Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations Forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Dennis Whitcomb, Western Washington University Heather Battaly, California State University Fullerton Jason Baehr, Loyola Marymount University Daniel Howard-Snyder, Western Washington University In the preface to Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Robert Nozick wonders why philosophical writings seem so arrogant: ...the usual manner of presenting philosophical work puzzles me. Works of philosophy are written as
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Political Theory As an Anti-Enlightenment Project
    Dennis C. Rasmussen Brown University Contemporary Political Theory as an Anti-Enlightenment Project [NB: I am aware that the argument of this paper – that the majority of contemporary political theorists seek to dissociate themselves from the Enlightenment – isn’t actually much of an argument. I am currently beginning a book project that will seek to defend the Enlightenment (to some extent or another) from the attacks of its contemporary critics; the material gathered here includes part of the introduction and the introductions to each of the five substantive chapters, along with a few underdeveloped remarks at the beginning and end that seek to tie things together. In other words, this material wasn’t written as a stand-alone paper, so I apologize if it seems incomplete – it is! I also apologize for the length; for those who don’t have the time or desire to read it all, the main line of argument comes in the first 18 pages, with the rest fleshing out some details. I will, however, be eager to hear your thoughts about the charges I have outlined, and especially if I have missed any major critics or criticisms of the Enlightenment.] Like it or not, we are all children of the Enlightenment, utterly incapable of escaping the clutches of ideals and arguments put forth over two centuries ago. Or so, at least, many critics of the Enlightenment seem to believe. Michel Foucault claims, for instance, that the Enlightenment has largely determined “what we are, what we think, and what we do today,”1 and John Gray insists that “all schools of contemporary political thought are variations on the Enlightenment project.”2 There is, of course, something to such claims: given the number of values, practices, and institutions that we have inherited from the eighteenth century, it is difficult to imagine what our world would look like without its Enlightenment heritage.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke on the Naturalness of Rights
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1992 John Locke on the naturalness of rights Peter C. Myers Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Myers, Peter C., "John Locke on the naturalness of rights" (1992). Dissertations. 3017. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/3017 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1992 Peter C. Myers JOHN LOCKE ON THE NATURALNESS OF RIGHTS By Peter c. Myers VOLUME II A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy January 1992 CHAPTER V NATURAL HISTORY AND THE STATE OF NATURE In the second section of chapter III above, we re­ ferred to Locke's apparent relegation of morality to the periphery of his concern in writing the Essay. Locke seems in effect to promise that however novel in other respects may be his empiricist account of natural science, that account leaves relatively inviolate the province of moral­ ity; he declares in closing that the study of nature is "wholly separate and distinct" (4.21.5) from the science of ethics or morality. We have noted too that Locke's asser­ tions of the possibility of a demonstrative, mixed-mode science of morality appear to entail an insistence on precisely such a strict separation of the respective sciences of morality and nature.1 In fact, however, there are significant ambiguities in Locke's presentation of this proposal.
    [Show full text]
  • The Imaginary and Descartes' Paradoxical Rationality
    THE IMAGINARY AND DESCARTES’ PARADOXICAL RATIONALITY Fulden İBRAHİMHAKKIOĞLU* ABSTRACT The imaginary plays a distinctive role in Descartes’ writings. While its place is often articulated in negative terms (as that which is illusory or deceptive), it nonetheless serves as an important ground for the Cartesian project to unfold. Descartes’ search for clear and distinct ideas takes place through reason’s interplay with the imaginary. While its reliability as a source of knowledge is ultimately dismissed, the imaginary is that which is never truly mastered or overcome. It is a source of dread and anxiety; which reason seeks to mitigate. This essay explores such interplay between the real and the imaginary, between reason and “unreason” in Descartes’ Meditations as well as his Olympica, which contains some precursor themes and tropes to The Meditations. While the Cartesian project seeks to separate the real from the imaginary and reason from unreason, I argue that the manner in which his discourse unfolds reveals their inextricable tie. Keywords: The imaginary, Descartes, rationality, Olympica, the body HAYALİ OLAN VE DESCARTES’IN PARADOKSAL RASYONELLİĞİ ÖZ Hayali olanın Descartes’ın yazınındaki rolü oldukça kendine özgüdür. “Asılsız,” “yanıltıcı” gibi olumsuz terimler üzerinden düşünülüyor olsa da, hayali olan, Kartezyen projenin serimlenmesinde önemli bir zemin görevi üstlenir. Descartes’ın açık-seçiklik ve kesinlik arayışı aklın hayali olanla karşılıklı etkileşimi üzerinden kurulur. Epistemolojik güvenilirliği bulunmamakla beraber, hayali olan asla tamamıyla hükmedilemez ve üstesinden nihai olarak gelinemez olandır; akıl ile yatıştırılmaya çalışılan bir korku ve endişe kaynağıdır. Bu makale, Descartes’ın Meditasyonlar’ında ve Olympica’sında gerçek olan ile hayali olan ve akıl ile akıldışı arasındaki paslaşmaları incelemektedir.
    [Show full text]
  • Søren Kierkegaard Reflected in Indian Philosophy
    Sincronía ISSN: 1562-384X [email protected] Universidad de Guadalajara México Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Hajko, Dalimír Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=513852378037 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Filosofía Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Dalimír Hajko [email protected] Constantine the Philosopher University in Nitra, Eslovaquia Abstract: Analysis of the postulates of Kierkegaard in the Indian world. Transcendence and breaking of boundaries are approached from a critical analysis based on the conceptualization of existentialism, knowing their contribution in the context of the Upanishads, Vedantas, Neo-Vedantas, as well as their western influence in a non- Western scenario. Keywords: Kierkegaard, Hindu philosophy, Existentialism. Resumen: Análisis de los postulados de Kierkegaard en el mundo índico. La trascendencia y rompimiento de las fronteras son abordadas desde un análisis crítico partiendo de la conceptualización del existencialismo, conociendo su aportación en el Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 contexto de los Upanishads, Vedantas, Neo-Vedantas, así como su influencia occidental en un escenario no occidental. Universidad de Guadalajara, México Palabras clave: Kierkegaard, Filosofía hindú, Existencialismo. Received:
    [Show full text]