Explaining the Discontinuity Between Human and Nonhuman Minds

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Explaining the Discontinuity Between Human and Nonhuman Minds BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2008) 31, 109–178 Printed in the United States of America doi: 10.1017/S0140525X08003543 Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds Derek C. Penn Department of Psychology, University of California–Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095; Cognitive Evolution Group, University of Louisiana, Lafayette, LA 70504 [email protected] http://reasoninglab.psych.ucla.edu/ http://www.cognitiveevolutiongroup.org/ Keith J. Holyoak Department of Psychology, University of California–Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095 [email protected] http://reasoninglab.psych.ucla.edu/ Daniel J. Povinelli Cognitive Evolution Group, University of Louisiana, Lafayette, LA 70504 [email protected] http://www.cognitiveevolutiongroup.org/ Abstract: Over the last quarter century, the dominant tendency in comparative cognitive psychology has been to emphasize the similarities between human and nonhuman minds and to downplay the differences as “one of degree and not of kind” (Darwin 1871). In the present target article, we argue that Darwin was mistaken: the profound biological continuity between human and nonhuman animals masks an equally profound discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. To wit, there is a significant discontinuity in the degree to which human and nonhuman animals are able to approximate the higher-order, systematic, relational capabilities of a physical symbol system (PSS) (Newell 1980). We show that this symbolic-relational discontinuity pervades nearly every domain of cognition and runs much deeper than even the spectacular scaffolding provided by language or culture alone can explain. We propose a representational-level specification as to where human and nonhuman animals’ abilities to approximate a PSS are similar and where they differ. We conclude by suggesting that recent symbolic- connectionist models of cognition shed new light on the mechanisms that underlie the gap between human and nonhuman minds. Keywords: analogy; animal cognition; causal learning; connectionism; Darwin; discontinuity; evolution; human mind; language; language of thought; physical symbol system; reasoning; same-different; theory of mind 1. Introduction many prominent comparative researchers have claimed that the traditional hallmarks of human cognition – for Human animals – and no other – build fires and example, complex tool use, grammatically structured wheels, diagnose each other’s illnesses, communicate language, causal-logical reasoning, mental state attribu- using symbols, navigate with maps, risk their lives for tion, metacognition, analogical inferences, mental time ideals, collaborate with each other, explain the world travel, culture, and so on – are not nearly as unique as in terms of hypothetical causes, punish strangers for we once thought (see, e.g., Bekoff et al. 2002; Call breaking rules, imagine impossible scenarios, and 2006; Clayton et al. 2003; de Waal & Tyack 2003; teach each other how to do all of the above. At first Matsuzawa 2001; Pepperberg 2002; Rendell & blush, it might appear obvious that human minds are Whitehead 2001; Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 1998; Smith qualitatively different from those of every other et al. 2003; Tomasello et al. 2003a). Pepperberg (2005, animal on the planet. Ever since Darwin, however, p. 469) aptly sums up the comparative consensus as the dominant tendency in comparative cognitive follows: “for over 35 years, researchers have been psychology has been to emphasize the continuity demonstrating through tests both in the field and in the lab- between human and nonhuman minds and to downplay oratory that the capacities of nonhuman animals to solve the differences as “one of degree and not of kind” complex problems form a continuum with those of (Darwin 1871). Particularly in the last quarter century, humans.” # 2008 Cambridge University Press 0140-525X/08 $40.00 109 Penn et al.: Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds Of course, many scholars continue to claim that there is Tomasello and Rakoczy (2003, p. 121) argue that the something qualitatively different about at least some ability to participate in cultural activities with shared goals human faculties, particularly those associated with language and intentions is uniquely human, but claim that the cogni- and a representational theory of mind (see, e.g., Bermudez tive skills of a human child born on a desert island and 2003; Carruthers 2002; Donald 2001; Mithen 1996; somehow magically kept alive by itself until adulthood Premack 2007; Suddendorf & Corballis 2007a). Nearly “would not differ very much – perhaps a little, but not everyone agrees that there is something uniquely human very much” from the cognitive skills of other great apes about our ability to represent and reason about our own (see also Tomasello et al. 2003a; Tomasello et al. 2005). and others’ mental states (e.g., Tomasello et al. 2005). Notwithstanding the broad comparative consensus And most linguists and psycho-linguists argue that there is arrayed against us, the hypothesis we will be proposing a fundamental discontinuity between human and nonhu- in the present paper is that Darwin was mistaken: The pro- man forms of communication (e.g., Chomsky 1980; found biological continuity between human and nonhu- Jackendoff 2002; Pinker 1994). But the trend among com- man animals masks an equally profound functional parative researchers is to construe the uniquely human discontinuity between the human and nonhuman mind.1 aspect of these faculties in increasingly narrow terms. Indeed, we will argue that the functional discontinuity Hauser et al. (2002a), for example, continue to claim that between human and nonhuman minds pervades nearly grammatically structured languages are unique to the every domain of cognition – from reasoning about human species, but suggest that the only component of spatial relations to deceiving conspecifics – and runs the human language faculty that is, in fact, uniquely much deeper than even the spectacular scaffolding pro- human is the computational mechanism of recursion. The vided by language or culture alone can explain. rest of our “conceptual-intentional” system, they argue, At the same time, we know from Darwin’s more well- differs from that of nonhuman animals only in “quantity grounded principles that there are no unbridgeable gaps rather than kind” (Hauser et al. 2002a, p. 1573). Similarly, in evolution. Therefore, one of the most important challenges confronting cognitive scientists of all stripes, in our view, is to explain how the manifest functional discontinuity between extant human and nonhuman minds could have evolved in a biologically plausible DEREK C. PENN received a Masters Degree from Boston manner. University in Philosophy and Literary Semiotics in 1987. The first – and probably most important – step in He spent the next 15 years on the trading floors of various answering this question is to clearly identify the simi- Wall Street investment firms and in Silicon Valley as a software entrepreneur. In 2002 he retired from the larities and the dissimilarities between human and nonhu- business world to pursue his life-long interest in compara- man cognition from a purely functional point of view. We tive psychology. He is currently affiliated with the Cogni- therefore spend the bulk of the paper reexamining the evi- tive Evolution Group, University of Louisiana, and the dence for “human-like” cognitive abilities among nonhu- University of California, Los Angeles and is working on man animals at a functional level, before speculating as a trade book with Daniel J. Povinelli based on the hypoth- to how these processes might be implemented. We cover eses proposed in the present article. a wide variety of domains, species, and experimental pro- tocols – ranging from spatial relations and mental state KEITH J. HOLYOAK is a Distinguished Professor of Psy- reasoning in the lab to dominance relations and transitive chology at the University of California, Los Angeles. The inferences in the wild. Across all these disparate cases, author of more than 180 research articles, his books include Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought a consistent pattern emerges: Although there is a profound (co-authored with Paul Thagard, MIT Press, 1995) and similarity between human and nonhuman animals’ abil- The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning ities to learn about and act on the perceptual relations (co-edited with Robert Morrison, Cambridge University between events, properties, and objects in the world, Press, 2005). A past recipient of a Guggenheim Fellow- only humans appear capable of reinterpreting the ship, Holyoak is a Fellow of the American Association higher-order relation between these perceptual relations for the Advancement of Science, the Association for in a structurally systematic and inferentially productive Psychological Science, the Cognitive Science Society, fashion. In particular, only humans form general cat- and the Society for Experimental Psychology. egories based on structural rather than perceptual criteria, find analogies between perceptually disparate relations, DANIEL J. POVINELLI is a Professor of Biology at the University of Louisiana. He is the recipient of an Ameri- draw inferences based on the hierarchical or logical can Psychological Association Award for an Early Career relation between relations, cognize the abstract functional Contribution to Psychology, an National Science Foun- role played by constituents in a relation as distinct
Recommended publications
  • A Rational Analysis of the Selection Task As Optimal Data Selection
    Psychological Review Copyright 1994 by the American Psychological Association. Inc. 1994. Vol. 101. No. 4, 608-631 0033-295X/94/S3.00 A Rational Analysis of the Selection Task as Optimal Data Selection Mike Oaksford and Nick Chater Human reasoning in hypothesis-testing tasks like Wason's (1966, 1968) selection task has been de- picted as prone to systematic biases. However, performance on this task has been assessed against a now outmoded falsificationist philosophy of science. Therefore, the experimental data is reassessed in the light of a Bayesian model of optimal data selection in inductive hypothesis testing. The model provides a rational analysis (Anderson, 1990) of the selection task that fits well with people's perfor- mance on both abstract and thematic versions of the task. The model suggests that reasoning in these tasks may be rational rather than subject to systematic bias. Over the past 30 years, results in the psychology of reasoning 1990; Evans, 1993; Stich, 1990). In particular, Anderson (1990) have raised doubts about human rationality. The assumption of argued that we must distinguish normative from adaptive ratio- human rationality has a long history. Aristotle took the capacity nality. An organism's behavior is rational if it is optimally for rational thought to be the defining characteristic of human adapted to its environment, even if reasoning according to logi- beings, the capacity that separated us from the animals. Des- cal rules had no causal role in producing the behavior. Such cartes regarded the ability to use language and to reason as the optimality assumptions have become widespread in contempo- hallmarks of the mental that separated it from the merely phys- rary social and behavioral science, from economics (Simon, ical.
    [Show full text]
  • Stenning.Pdf
    Logical and psychological relations between the `False Belief Task' and counterfactual reasoninga Keith Stenning Universitiy of Edinburgh DIPLEAP Workshop 26 - 28 November, 2010. Vienna, Austria aThis work is a joint project with Michiel van Lambalgen of the University of Amsterdam Counterfactuals in logic and psychology • there is much psychological interest in children's counterfactual rea- soning • children reason differently with hypotheticals and counterfactuals • a first logical response: possible worlds semantics|a classical logical analysis • but the tasks are `discourse understanding'|not adversarial inference Counterfactuals, nonmonotonic logics, and false-belief • an alternative logical response is to use non-monotonic logics for rea- soning to interpretations to explore children's discourse reasoning • the relation between counterfactuals and false-belief reasoning is a further active psychological issue • [Peterson and Riggs, 1999] proposed that problems with counterfac- tual reasoning were what made false-belief reasoning hard, and [Riggs et al., 1998] presented data to support the claim • [Stenning and van Lambalgen, 2008] proposed a nonmonotonic logical analysis of false-belief reasoning which related it to reasoning with counterfactuals • other data, notably [Perner et al., 2004], casts doubt on this alignment Nonmonotonic logic|the basic model • A ^ ab ! B read as "If A, and nothing is abnormal, then B" • information that is at present unknown (φ) may turn out to constitute an abnormality (φ ! ab) • if there is no such
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Dialogue As a Teaching and Research Method for Co- Creativity?
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Socratic dialogue as a teaching and research method for co- creativity? Citation for published version: Stenning, K, Schmoelz, A, Wren, H, Stouraitis, E, Scaltsas, T, Alexopoulos, K & Aichhorn, A 2016, 'Socratic dialogue as a teaching and research method for co-creativity?', Digital Culture and Education, vol. 8, no. 2, pp. 154-168. Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Digital Culture and Education General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 05. Oct. 2021 DIGITAL CULTURE & EDUCATION, 8(2) 2016, ISSN 1836-8301 Digital Culture & Education (DCE) Publication details, including instructions for authors http://www.digitalcultureandeducation.com/ Socratic dialogue as a teaching and research method for co-creativity? Keith Stenningb Alexander Schmoelza Heather Wren Elias Stouraitisc Theodore Scaltsasb Constantine Alexopoulosb Amelie Aichhorn a University of Vienna b University of Edinburgh c Ellinogermaniki Agogi Online Publication Date: 1st July 2016 To cite this Article: Stenning, K., Schmoelz, A., Wren, H., Stouraitis, E., Alexopoulos, C., & Aichhorn, A.
    [Show full text]
  • Joanna J. Bryson
    Joanna J. Bryson Department of Computer Science Resident in NJ 08536 [email protected] University of Bath United States of America http://www.cs.bath.ac.uk/∼jjb Bath BA2 7AY +1 (609) 285-3596 United Kingdom Education PH.D. IN COMPUTER SCIENCE June 2001 THE MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY Dissertation Title: Intelligence by Design: Principles of Modularity and Coordination for Engineering Complex Adaptive Agents. Courses Include: Principles of Computing Systems, Embodiment and Cognition, Computer Architecture, Artificial Intelligence, Theory of Computation. 1 M.PHIL. IN PSYCHOLOGY January 2000 THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH Dissertation Title: The Study of Sequential and Hierarchical Organization of Behavior via Arti- ficial Mechanisms of Action Selection. Research conducted 1996–1998; viva postponed for convenience; passed on first attempt. Tony Prescott, external. M.SC. IN ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE November 1992 THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH Dissertation Title: The Subsumption Strategy Development of a Music Modelling System Courses Include: Knowledge Representation and Inference, Intelligent Sensing and Control, Neural Networks, Software for Parallel Architectures, Expert Systems B.A. IN BEHAVIORAL SCIENCE June 1986 THE COLLEGE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO Courses Include: Human Information Processing, Perception, Human Interaction, Developmental Neuropsychology, Ethology Employment DEPARTMENT OF COMPUTER SCIENCE University of Bath, England Bath is a small, research-oriented university. Founded in 1966, now consistently ranked in the top ten British Universities by British newspapers. Founding leader for Intelligent Systems, one of four research groups in the department. Organiser for mailing lists and seminar series: Artificial Models of Natural Intelligence (amoni), Bath Evolutionary Social Sciences, Bath AI; also active participant in neuroscience and robotics communities.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science
    COGNITIVE SCIENCE HUMAN REASONING AND AN COGNITIVE SCIENCE D COGNITIVE HUMAN REASONING HUMAN REASONING Keith Stenning and Michiel van Lambalgen In Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science, Keith HUMAN Stenning and Michiel van Lambalgen—a cognitive scientist and a logician—argue for the indispensability Keith Stenning is Professor of Human “Once in a while there is a body of work that reconceptualizes a topic of research. of modern mathematical logic to the study of human Communication in the School of Informatics at This book reports and reviews such a body of work. The result is a framing and REASONING reasoning. Logic and cognition were once closely the University of Edinburgh. He is author of Seeing hypotheses about reasoning that, in my judgment, fundamentally reconstructs the SC connected, they write, but were “divorced” in the past psychology of inferential reasoning.... This book will be regarded as the major AND century; the psychology of deduction went from being Reason and coauthor of Introduction to Cognition IEN turning point in the field’s development.” central to the cognitive revolution to being the subject of and Communication (MIT Press, 2006). C COGNITIVE widespread skepticism about whether human reasoning James Greeno, LRDC, University of Pittsburgh E really happens outside the academy. Stenning and van Lambalgen argue that logic and reasoning have V Michiel van Lambalgen is Professor of Logic and S been separated because of a series of unwarranted AN ScIENCE TENNING “This deep and stimulating book, by a leading psychologist and a leading logician, assumptions about logic. Cognitive Science at the University of Amsterdam L is about the choice of logical formalisms for representing actual reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Diagrams 2018 Graduate Symposium Proceedings
    Proceedings of Graduate Symposium Editor: Andrew Blake University of Brighton, United Kingdom [email protected] Preface The Diagrams Graduate Symposium (GS) provides Master and Doctoral students with an opportunity to present their work and get feedback from established researchers in the field. It is also a supportive environment for students to network and make contact with potential future colleagues or employers. The GS was an integral part of the Diagrams 2018 programme. As in previous years, lively discussions led to suggestions about the students’ on-going research, and allowed experienced participants to hear fresh ideas and view some of the new trends in the field. This year’s GS proceedings constitute eleven student papers. These are short papers that describe the students’ research. Each paper was reviewed by two distinguished scholars whom provided constructive and detailed feedback to the students. Further to the reviewer’s feedback, students were assigned mentors for the duration of the conference. An important part of the mentor’s role was to provide constructive feedback and advice in response to their student’s presentation. Students, therefore, received valuable and construction feedback for both their paper and presentation. The success of this year’s GS arose for a number of important reasons. The diversity of the students assured, in part, the quality of their research. For example, students represented nine different universities from five different countries across three continents. Diagrams 2018 also received valuable funding from the National Science Foundation (NSF) facilitating graduates from the USA to make the long journey to Edinburgh. The conference organising committee worked hard to ensure the smooth running of each day’s events.
    [Show full text]
  • Statement on the Research Excellence Framework Proposals
    Statement on the Research Excellence Framework proposals The latest proposal by the higher education funding councils is If implemented, these proposals risk undermining support for for 25% of the new Research Excellence Framework (REF) to basic research across all disciplines and may well lead to an be assessed according to 'economic and social impact'. As academic brain drain to countries such as the United States academics, researchers and higher education professionals we that continue to value fundamental research. believe that it is counterproductive to make funding for the best research conditional on its perceived economic and social Universities must continue to be spaces in which the spirit of benefits. adventure thrives and where researchers enjoy academic freedom to push back the boundaries of knowledge in their The REF proposals are founded on a lack of understanding of disciplines. how knowledge advances. It is often difficult to predict which research will create the greatest practical impact. History We, therefore, call on the UK funding councils to shows us that in many instances it is curiosity-driven research withdraw the current REF proposals and to work with that has led to major scientific and cultural advances. academics and researchers on creating a funding regime which supports and fosters basic research in our universities and colleges rather than discourages it. Signed: Name Institution Relevant titles/positions Sir Tim Hunt Cancer Research UK FRS, Nobel Laureate 2001 Professor John Dainton University of Liverpool Fellow of the Royal Society Fellow of the Institute of Physics Fellow of the Royal Society for the encouragement of Arts, Manufactures and Commerce (RSA) Name Institution Relevant titles/positions Professor Venki Ramakrishnan University of Cambridge FRS, Nobel Prize in Chemistry Professor Brian Josephson University of Cambridge Nobel Laureate in Physics Professor Harry Kroto The Florida State University FRS Professor Donald W Braben UCL Sir John Walker Medical Research Council and University of FRS, F.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining the Discontinuity Between Human and Nonhuman Minds
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2008) 31, 109–178 Printed in the United States of America doi: 10.1017/S0140525X08003543 Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds Derek C. Penn Department of Psychology, University of California–Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095; Cognitive Evolution Group, University of Louisiana, Lafayette, LA 70504 [email protected] http://reasoninglab.psych.ucla.edu/ http://www.cognitiveevolutiongroup.org/ Keith J. Holyoak Department of Psychology, University of California–Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095 [email protected] http://reasoninglab.psych.ucla.edu/ Daniel J. Povinelli Cognitive Evolution Group, University of Louisiana, Lafayette, LA 70504 [email protected] http://www.cognitiveevolutiongroup.org/ Abstract: Over the last quarter century, the dominant tendency in comparative cognitive psychology has been to emphasize the similarities between human and nonhuman minds and to downplay the differences as “one of degree and not of kind” (Darwin 1871). In the present target article, we argue that Darwin was mistaken: the profound biological continuity between human and nonhuman animals masks an equally profound discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. To wit, there is a significant discontinuity in the degree to which human and nonhuman animals are able to approximate the higher-order, systematic, relational capabilities of a physical symbol system (PSS) (Newell 1980). We show that this symbolic-relational discontinuity pervades nearly every domain of cognition and runs much deeper than even the spectacular scaffolding provided by language or culture alone can explain. We propose a representational-level specification as to where human and nonhuman animals’ abilities to approximate a PSS are similar and where they differ.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 6, Number 7 (Optimised for Screen Readers)
    Volume 6, Number 7 July 2012 www.thereasoner.org ISSN 1757-0522 Contents Editorial Features News What’s Hot in . Events Courses and Programmes Jobs and Studentships Editorial Over the last decades, the relations between psychology, logic and philosophy on the topic of reasoning have been somewhat strained. Once the Piagetian idea that classical, traditional logic provided a good descriptive model of human reasoning was thought to have foundered on Wason’s critique in the 1960s, psychologists were increasingly convinced that logic had nothing to offer for their investigations. Logicians, in turn, were developing increasingly sophisticated and varied logical systems, but paying little attention to how (and whether) these systems were in fact connected to human reasoning au naturel. Philosophers, at the other end, held on to the idea that philos- ophy is about what ought to be the case, not about what is the case, and thus for the most part viewed the results in the psy- chology of reasoning as philosophically irrelevant. The absence of contact between these different disciplines is still essentially the current situation, but with a few notable and very exciting exceptions. The work of Keith Stenning in partic- ular boldly breaks down the borders between these disciplines, and thereby offers a much more encompassing and nuanced ac- count of human reasoning than what can be found elsewhere. Keith is an honorary professor at the University of Edinburgh, where for years (1990–2000) he led the Human Communication Research Center. He is the author of countless articles and two books: Seeing Reason (OUP, 2002) and, with Michiel van Lambalgen, Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science (MIT Press, 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Dialogue As a Teaching and Research Method for Co-Creativity?
    DIGITAL CULTURE & EDUCATION, 8(2) 2016, ISSN 1836-8301 Digital Culture & Education (DCE) Publication details, including instructions for authors http://www.digitalcultureandeducation.com/ Socratic dialogue as a teaching and research method for co-creativity? Keith Stenningb Alexander Schmoelza Heather Wren Elias Stouraitisc Theodore Scaltsasb Constantine Alexopoulosb Amelie Aichhorn a University of Vienna b University of Edinburgh c Ellinogermaniki Agogi Online Publication Date: 1st July 2016 To cite this Article: Stenning, K., Schmoelz, A., Wren, H., Stouraitis, E., Scaltsas, T., Alexopoulos, C., & Aichhorn, A. (2016). Socratic dialogue as a teaching and research method for co-creativity?. Digital Culture & Education, 8(2), 154-68. URL: http://www.digitalcultureandeducation.com/cms/wp-content/uploads/2016/07/stenning.et.al.pdf PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE SOCRATIC DIALOGUE AS A TEACHING AND RESEARCH METHOD FOR CO-CREATIVITY? Keith Stenning, Alexander Schmoelz, Heather Wren, Elias Stouraitis, Theodore Scaltsas, Konstantine Alexopoulos & Amelie Aichhorn Abstract: We sketch a theory of creativity which centres on the framing of activity by repetitive thinking and action, and sees creativity as divergences from these routines which is thereby framed against them. Without a repetitive frame creativity is impossible. Mere repetition is not creative, even if new. Creativity disrupts a frame, purposefully. Socratic Dialogue is an ancient technique of engaging a student in a dialogue by asking non-leading questions, aimed at revealing to the student how much knowledge he or she already has on some topic: Socrates' demonstration to the slave-boy (and the audience) that the boy already knows geometry (without any schooling) is the founding example. We aim to illustrate that internalising the Socratic kind of reflective self-questioning and co-questioning is intimately related to the view of creativity as the reframing of routine.
    [Show full text]