Appendix § 39

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Appendix § 39 § 39 Relation to other algebras 139 is an extension of the product mo of ml , m 2• Let B n E SB be the sequence defined in example C). By definition, n ~;;;;n<oo B n = /1, B n +l C B n , and lim mo (Bn ) > O. On the other hand, lim mo (Bn ) = lim m (Bn ) = 0 since 1t~OO n"""""-TOO n~oo n r;;;; n < 00 B n = /1 and m is a a-measure on Q{. Contradiction. Replacing a by any infinite cardinal m everywhere in the definition of a-product, we obtain the analogous notion of Boolean m-product of an indexed set {SBthE T of non-degenerate Boolean m-algebras. Since no representation theorem analogous to 29.1 is true for Boolean m-algebras, the theory of general Boolean m-products is more complicated than in the case m = a. One can prove that m-products exist always, it is also possible to introduce a not ion analogous to the maximal a-productl. Appendix § 39. Relation to other algebras Boolean algebras are a special case of abstract algebras (with a finite number of finite operations). Many notions introduced in Chapter I belong to the general theory of abstract algebras. We quote here such notions as homomorphism, isomorphism, subalgebra, generator, free algebra etc. Boolean m-algebras investigated in Chapter II can be also interpreted as a special case of abstract algebras but with some infinite operations, viz. with the complementation -A, the infinite join U tETA t and the infinite meet n tE TAt where T is a fixed set of cardinal m. Thus such notions as m-subalgebra, m-homomorphism (between two m-algebras), m-generator, free Boolean m-algebra etc. belongs also to the general theory of abstract algebras. Many remarks in Chapters land II and also some theorems belong to the theory of abstract algebras. We mention here, for instance, theorems 12.1 and 23.3 which are a particular case of a general theorem on abstract algebras. The notions of field product and m-product, and of Boolean product and maximal a-product are particular cases of a general notion of product of abstract algebras 2 • Also some other general algebraic notions not examined in Chapters I and II can be applied to the theory of Boolean algebras. As an example we quote here the notion of inverse and direct systems 3 • It follows immediately from the set ofaxioms assumed in § 1 that Boolean algebras are distributive lattices. More exactly, the notion of Boolean algebra coincides with the notion of distributive complemented lattice 4• Some theorems proved here for Boolean algebras can be 1 See SIKORSKI [191 2 See SlKORSKl [19]. 3 See HAlMO [IJ and WALLACE [1]. 4 For other characterizations of Boolean algebras among lattices. see BALA­ CHANDRAN [IJ. BIRKHOFFand WARD [IJ. DlLWORTH [2J. MlCHIURA [IJ. NACHBlN[I]. 140 Appendix generalized to distributive lattices. In particular, the fundamental representation theorem 8.2 can be considered as a particular case of a representation theorem for distributive latticesl . As we have observed in § 17, the theory of Boolean algebras coincides (if only finite joins and meets are taken into consideration) with apart of the theory of algebraic rings. The term "ideal" is taken from this theory. In fact, it is easy to verify that a set S of elements of a Boolean algebra Q( is an ideal in the sense defined in § 3 if and only if it is an ideal of the Boolean ring Ql in the sense assumed in the general theory of algebraic rings. The forming of factor algebras described in § 10 is a particular case of forming algebraic factor rings. It is also a particular case of forming factor algebras modulo a congruence relation in thc general theory of abstract algebras. It is worth noticing that the two-valued homomorphisms method used in the proof of the fundamental representation theorem 2 8.2 is a particular case of a general method of investigation of more complicated algebras by means of homomorphisms into certain special simple algebras with the same operations. An example of the use of this method is given by the notion of the space dual to a given Banach space. This space is the set of an linear continuous functionals, i.e. homomorphisms (of the theory of Banach spaces) into the simplest Banach space, viz. the field of scalars (real or complex). Another example of this method is given by the theory of normed rings in Functional Analysis. Here the dual space Ql* of a given normed ring Ql is the set of an continuous multiplicative linear functionals, i.e. homomorphisms X into the simplest normed ring, viz. the ring of scalars. If A E Ql is fixed, then the formula (X E Q(*) defines a continuous mapping from Ql* to scalars. Under some additional hypothesis, the mapping h defined by the formula (1) h(A) = <PA is one-to-one. In this case Ql can be represented as a ring of continuous functions on the dual space Q(*. The last example has an analogue in the theory of Boolean algebras. Every Boolean algebra Ql is not only an algebraic ring but also a linear ring over the two-element algebraic field 9\ (see § 17, p. 47). According to the remarks on p. 16-17 and the definition in the proof of 8.2, the Stone space X of a given Boolean algebra Ql can be interpreted as the set of an two-valued homomorphisms of Ql into 9\, i.e. the set of all multiplicative 1 Proved by BIRKHOFF [IJ and STONE [9J. See also RIEGER [2J. 2 In the proof of 8.2 we used the notion of maximal filter instead of two-valued homomorphisms but these notions are equivalent (see p. 16-17). § 39 Relation to other algebras 141 linear functionals with values in the field ~ of sealars. The dass of an continuous mappings from the Stone space X into the two-element Hausdorff space ~ can be indentified with the dass of all both open and dosed subsets of Q( sinee every mapping of this type is uniquely deter­ mined by the (both open and dosed) set of points where it assumes the unit as its value. Thus the isomorphism h in the proof of the fundamental representation theorem 8.2 can be considered as a particularcase of (1). Consequently the Stone space of Q( is sometimes called dual space 0/ Q( 1. The analogy between the representation theory of normed rings and Boolean algebras is so deep that it is possible to develop a general theory of maximal ideals which gives, as partieular cases, the both representation theorems 2. The notion of Boolean a-algebras is a partieular case of the notion of cardinal algebras 3• Cardinal algebras are abstract algebras with an infinite operation whieh is a common generalization of the Boolean join of an enumerable sequenee of elements and of the sum of an enumerable sequence of cardinal numbers. The axioms eharacterizing this operation are such that their consequences form a large part of the additive arithmetic of cardinal numbers. However they are also satisfied by Boolean a-algebras, types of isomorphisms for Boolean a-algebras, the set of non-negative integers or reals (with + 00), the set of an non-negative functions on a set, and other systems. Theorems on cardinal algebras are also theorems on Boolean algebras but they were not quoted in this book. It is worth notieing that some of these theorems on Boolean algebras are generalizations of some wen known fundamental theorems on cardinals. For instanee, the fundamental Cantor-Bernstein theorem on cardinals is a particular case of the following theorem on Boolean a-algebras Q(, Q3: if Q3 is isomorphie to Q( IA (A E Q() and Q( is isomorphie to Q3 IB (B E Q3), then Q( and Q3 are isomorphie 4 . To obtain the Cantor-Bernstein theorem it suffices to assurne that Q{ and Q3 are fields of an subsets of some sets X, Y with cardinals n1> n 2 respecti vel y. By the same method we infer that the Bernstein theorem 1 See HALMOS [4]. 2 SLOWIKOWSKI and ZAWADOWSKI [1]. 3 The notion and the theory of cardinal algebras are due to TARSKI [8J. See also JONSSON and TARSKI [2]. 4 See SIKORSKI [lJ and TARSKI [8J. The hypothesis thatm and mare a-complete is essential. See KINOSHITA [lJ and HANF [1]. 142 Appendix § 40 is a partieular case of the following theorem valid for every Boolean a-algebra Q{: if A, B E Q{, Q{ lAis isomorphie to Q{ 1-A, and 211 B is isomorphie to Q{ 1-B, then Q{ IA and Q{ IBare isomorphiel . Many papers are devoted to study Boolean algebras with some additional operations and to various generalizations of Boolean algebras and rings2• § 40. Applications to Mathematical Logic. Classical calculi The most important applications of the theory of Boolean algebras are those to Mathematical Logic. That is not surprising because the notion of Boolean algebras was created as the result of Boole's investigation of the algebraic structure of the "laws of thought"3. In the first part of its development, the theory of Boolean algebras was also called the Algebra 01 Logic. Consider first the case of the (two-valued) proposition al ca1culus. Denote the logical connective "or", "and", "not", "if ... , then ... " by U, n, -, -)0 respectively. The set of all formulas of the propositional ca1culus becomes a Boolean algebra after identifieation of equivalent formulas (see an analogous remark in § 1 D)).
Recommended publications
  • Alfred Tarski and a Watershed Meeting in Logic: Cornell, 1957 Solomon Feferman1
    Alfred Tarski and a watershed meeting in logic: Cornell, 1957 Solomon Feferman1 For Jan Wolenski, on the occasion of his 60th birthday2 In the summer of 1957 at Cornell University the first of a cavalcade of large-scale meetings partially or completely devoted to logic took place--the five-week long Summer Institute for Symbolic Logic. That meeting turned out to be a watershed event in the development of logic: it was unique in bringing together for such an extended period researchers at every level in all parts of the subject, and the synergetic connections established there would thenceforth change the face of mathematical logic both qualitatively and quantitatively. Prior to the Cornell meeting there had been nothing remotely like it for logicians. Previously, with the growing importance in the twentieth century of their subject both in mathematics and philosophy, it had been natural for many of the broadly representative meetings of mathematicians and of philosophers to include lectures by logicians or even have special sections devoted to logic. Only with the establishment of the Association for Symbolic Logic in 1936 did logicians begin to meet regularly by themselves, but until the 1950s these occasions were usually relatively short in duration, never more than a day or two. Alfred Tarski was one of the principal organizers of the Cornell institute and of some of the major meetings to follow on its heels. Before the outbreak of World War II, outside of Poland Tarski had primarily been involved in several Unity of Science Congresses, including the first, in Paris in 1935, and the fifth, at Harvard in September, 1939.
    [Show full text]
  • 31 Aug 2013 Cylindric and Polyadic Algebras, New Perspectives
    Cylindric and polyadic algebras, new perspectives Tarek Sayed Ahmed September 22, 2018 Abstract We generalize the notions of Monk’s system of varieties definable by a schema to integrate finite dimensions. We give a general method in this new framework that allows one to lift a plethora of results on neat embeddings to the infinite dimensional case. Several examples are given. We prove that that given α ≥ ω, r ∈ ω and k ≥ 1, there is r an algebra B ∈ NrαKα+k ∼ SNrαKα+k such that ΠrAr/F ∈ Kα for any r ∈ ω, where K is either the class of cylindric algebras or quasi- polyadic equality algebras (QEA). We discuss its analogue for diagonal free algebras like Pinter’s algebras and quasi-polyadic algebras. In another direction, we use Andr´eka’s methods of splitting to show that RQEAα (representable QEAαs) cannot be axiomatized by a finite schema over its substitution free reduct discarding substitution opera- tions indexed by transpositions, and is not finitely axiomatizable over its diagonal free reduct. We also give a general definition encompassing the two notions of Monk’s and Halmos’ schema, in infinite dimensions, which we call a gen- arXiv:1309.0681v1 [math.LO] 31 Aug 2013 eralized system of varieties definable by schema, and give many concrete examples. In this context we show that the free MV polyadic algebras, and free algebras in various countable reducts of Heyting polyadic al- gebras, have an interpolation property, deducing that the former class have the super-amalgamation property. We also show that Ferenczi’s cylindric-polyadic algebras have the super-amalgamation property.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Categorical Logic 1963–1977
    THE HISTORY OF CATEGORICAL LOGIC 1963{1977 Jean-Pierre Marquis and Gonzalo E. Reyes Categorical logic, as its name indicates, is logic in the setting of category the- ory. But this description does not say much. Most readers would probably find more instructive to learn that categorical logic is algebraic logic, pure and simple. It is logic in an algebraic dressing. Just as algebraic logic encodes propositional logic in its different guises (classical, intuitionistic, etc.) by their Lindenbaum- Tarski algebras (Boolean algebras, Heyting algebras and so on), categorical logic encodes first-order and higher-order logics (classical, intuitionistic, etc.) by cate- gories with additional properties and structure (Boolean categories, Heyting cate- gories and so on). Thus, from the purely technical point of view, categorical logic constitutes a generalization of the algebraic encoding of propositional logic to first- order, higher-order and other logics. Furthermore, we shall present and discuss arguments (given by the main actors) to show that this encoding constitutes the correct generalization of the well-known algebraic encoding of propositional logics by the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebras. The proper algebraic structures are not only categories, but also morphisms between categories, mainly functors and more specially adjoint functors. A key example is provided by the striking fact that quantifiers, which were the stumbling block to the proper algebraic generalization of propositional logic, can be seen to be adjoint functors and thus entirely within the categorical framework. As is usually the case when algebraic techniques are imported and developed within a field, e.g. geometry and topology, vast generalizations and unification become possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Logic and Logical Geometry
    Algebraic logic and logical geometry B. Plotkin, E. Aladova, E. Plotkin February 26, 2015 2 Contents I Preliminaries 5 1 Basics of Universal Algebra and Category Theory 7 1.1 Universal Algebra . 7 1.1.1 Sets . 7 1.1.2 One-sorted algebras . 9 Definitions and examples . 9 Homomorphisms of algebras . 12 1.1.3 Boolean algebras and lattices . 14 Definition of a Boolean algebra. 14 Boolean rings. 16 Lattices. 17 Ideals and filters. 18 1.1.4 Multi-sorted algebras . 20 Basic definitions . 20 Examples . 22 1.1.5 Free algebras . 23 One-sorted case . 23 Multi-sorted case . 27 1.1.6 Classes of algebras . 28 1.2 Category Theory . 33 1.2.1 Categories . 33 Definition of a category. Examples . 33 Morphisms. Dual categories . 34 Functors. Examples . 35 Natural transformations of functors . 37 1.2.2 Products and coproducts . 39 Inverse and direct limits . 41 1.2.3 Constants in algebras . 43 2 Basics of Universal Algebraic Geometry 47 2.1 Classical Algebraic Geometry . 48 2.1.1 Galois correspondence . 48 3 4 CONTENTS 2.1.2 Zariski topology . 52 2.1.3 The coordinate ring of an algebraic set . 53 2.1.4 Categories of algebraic sets and coordinate rings 54 2.2 Universal Algebraic Geometry . 55 2.2.1 Equations and affine spaces . 56 2.2.2 Galois correspondence in the universal case . 60 2.2.3 Zarisky topology in arbitrary variety Θ . 62 2.2.4 Coordinate algebras . 65 2.2.5 Categories of coordinate algebras and alge- braic sets . 69 2.2.6 Geometrically equivalent algebras .
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix § 39
    § 39. Relation to other algebras 191 Appendix § 39. Relation to other algebras Boolean algebras are a special case of universal algebras (with a finite number of finite operations). Many notions introduced in Chapter I belong to the general theory of universal algebras. We quote here such notions as homomorphism, isomorphism, subalgebra, generator, free algebra etc. Boolean m-algebras investigated in Chapter II can also be interpreted as a special case of universal algebras but with some infinite operations, viz. the complementation -A, the infinite join U tETAt and the infinite meet ntETA t where T is a fixed set of cardinality m. Thus such notions as m-subalgebra, m-homomorphism (between two m-algebras), m-generator, free Boolean m-algebra etc. also belong to the general theory of universal algebras. Many remarks in Chapter I and II and also some theorems belong to the theory of universal algebras. We mention here, for instance, theorems 12.1 and 23.3 which are particular cases of a general theorem on universal algebras. The notions of field product and m-product, and of Boolean product and maximal m-product, and maximal representable m-product are particular cases of a general notion of product of universal algebras1. Also some other general algebraic notions not examined in Chapters I and II can be applied to the theory of Boolean algebras. As an example we quote here the notion of inverse and direct systems 2 and the notion of projectivity and injectivity 3 from the general theory of categories. It follows immediately from the set of axioms assumed in § 1 that Boolean algebras are distributive lattices.
    [Show full text]
  • Cylindric and Polyadic Algebras
    CYLINDRIC AND POLYADIC ALGEBRAS BERNARD A. GALLER 1. Introduction. In recent years there have appeared two alge- braizations of the first-order predicate calculus; i.e., the polyadic algebras of Halmos [l; 2], and the cylindric algebras of Tarski [3; 4]. While polyadic algebras are the algebraic version of the pure first- order calculus, cylindric algebras yield an algebraization of the first- order calculus with equality. Since the pure calculus does not contain any identifiable predicate, one cannot expect to find the algebraic analogue of an equality predicate in a general polyadic algebra. It is reasonable, however, to consider "adjoining" an equality predicate, in some sense, to a polyadic algebra, and ask if one then obtains a cylindric algebra. This is the procedure followed here. An e-algebra is defined as a polyadic algebra with an equality predicate. We show that every e-algebra is in a natural way a cylindric algebra. Con- versely, it is shown that in the presence of an infinite supply of vari- ables and a local finiteness condition, cylindric algebras are in a natural way e-algebras, and the correspondence obtained in this way between e-algebras and cylindric algebras is one-to-one. 2. Polyadic algebras. A quantifier (or, more explicitly, an existential quantifier) on a Boolean algebra A is a mapping 3: A^A such that (1) 30 = 0, (2) pS 3p, and (3) 3(p/\ 3q) = 3pA 3q for all p, qCA. A polyadic algebra is a quadruple (A, I, S, 3), where A is a Boolean algebra, I an arbitrary set whose elements are called variables, S is a mapping from transformations of I into itself to Boolean endo- morphisms on A (the transformations need not be one-to-one nor onto), and 3 is a mapping from subsets of / to quantifiers on A, satisfying the following conditions: (Pi) 3(0)p=p for all pCA (0 shall denote the empty set throughout).
    [Show full text]
  • The Algebra of Logic Tradition
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CONICET Digital The Algebra of Logic Tradition Stanley Burris & Javier Legris This is a preliminary version of the entry “The Algebra of Logic Tradition” (substantive revision) from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ISSN: 1095-5054, http://plato.stanford.edu/): Information of the published final version: Burris, Stanley and Legris, Javier, "The Algebra of Logic Tradition", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/algebra-logic-tradition/>. The algebra of logic, as an explicit algebraic system showing the underlying mathematical structure of logic, was introduced by George Boole (1815-1864) in his book The Mathematical Analysis of Logic (1847). The methodology initiated by Boole was successfully continued in the 19th century in the work of William Stanley Jevons (1835-1882), Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914), Ernst Schröder (1841-1902), among many others, thereby establishing a tradition in (mathematical) logic. From Boole’s first book until the influence after WWI of the monumental work Principia Mathematica (1910–1913) by Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947) and Bertrand Russell (1872 – 1970), versions of the algebra of logic were the most developed form of mathematical above all through Schröder's three volumes Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (1890–1905). Furthermore, this tradition motivated the investigations of Leopold Löwenheim (1878-1957) that eventually gave rise to model theory. In addition, in 1941, Alfred Tarski (1901-1983) in his paper “On the calculus of relations” returned to Peirce's relation algebra as presented in Schröder's Algebra der Logik.
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure Theoretic Approach to Logical Quantification
    RENDICONTI del SEMINARIO MATEMATICO della UNIVERSITÀ DI PADOVA DAVID P. ELLERMAN GIAN-CARLO ROTA A measure theoretic approach to logical quantification Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova, tome 59 (1978), p. 227-246 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=RSMUP_1978__59__227_0> © Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova, 1978, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova » (http://rendiconti.math.unipd.it/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit conte- nir la présente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ A Measure Theoretic Approach to Logical Quantification. DAVID P. ELLERMAN (*) - GIAN-CARLO ROTA (**) 1. Introduction. It is an old philosophical thesis that logic is, in some sense, a limiting case of probability theory. However, this thesis has not given rise to a mathematical treatment of quantification theory (i.e., first-order logic) by the methods of probability theory because of cer- tain measure-theoretic difhculties. The principal difficulty is that it is impossible to put a positive finitely-additive real-valved probability measure on an uncountable set X (i.e., on the power-set Boolean algebra of X). If there was such a measure p on a set X, then the existential quantification of a unary predicate on X could be obtained as the support of the expectation of the indicator or characteristic function of the predicate and the quantification of n-ary relations could be similarly treated by means of conditional expectation opera- tors.
    [Show full text]