Schukraft-Dissertation-2017

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Schukraft-Dissertation-2017 Copyright by Jason Donald Schukraft 2017 The Dissertation Committee for Jason Donald Schukraft Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Carving Intuition at Its Joints Committee: Cory Juhl, Supervisor Ernest David Sosa Joshua Dever Miriam Schoenfield Herman Cappelen Carving Intuition at Its Joints by Jason Donald Schukraft, B.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2017 Dedication To Katie Carving Intuition at Its Joints Jason Donald Schukraft, Ph.D. The University of Texas at Austin, 2017 Supervisor: Cory Juhl Metaphilosophy is the philosophical study of philosophy itself. Metaphilosophers attempt to articulate and evaluate the aim(s) of philosophy, the value(s) of philosophy, and the method(s) of philosophy. One striking feature of contemporary metaphilosophy is the attention it devotes to the investigation of philosophical intuitions. There is a tacit presumption in this literature, shared by both proponents and critics of appeals to intuition, that philosophical intuitions constitute something like a natural kind. Intuitions may not issue from a single faculty, and the intuitions themselves may concern a heterogeneous collection of propositions, but nonetheless—so this line of thinking goes— there is something unifying about philosophical intuitions that justifies treating them monolithically. This treatment, I argue, is a mistake. To determine the merit of philosophical appeals to intuition, we need some way to gauge the reliability or justificatory power of such appeals. But attempting to measure the reliability or justificatory power of intuitions immediately generates a dilemma. On the one hand, challenging the reliability or justificatory power of all intuitions leads to self-defeat, as any such challenge will necessarily rely on intuition at some point in the argument. On the other hand, restricting the challenge to a certain subset of intuitions risks a familiar sort of v generality problem: what makes these intuitions problematic and not their counterparts in other domains? In response to this dilemma, I argue that metaphilosophy would be best served abandoning intuition talk altogether. ‘Intuition’ picks out an overly broad and general category. When assessing the reliability or justificatory power of an evidence source, it is necessary to be fine-grained about the evidence source. We ought not ask whether intuition as a whole is reliable; rather, we should ask whether particular kinds of intuition are reliable, leaving open the possibility that some sorts of intuitions are more reliable than others. I explore three principled ways of sub-dividing intuitions in a way that pushes the metaphilosophical dialectic forward. We can individuate classes of intuition by (1) their context of employment, (2) the exoticism of their content, and (3) their psychological provenance. This tripartite division will make it easier to identify which appeals to intuition are problematic without risking wholesale skepticism. vi Table of Contents Chapter One: Introduction ................................................................................................... 1 Project Overview ......................................................................................................... 2 Chapter Two: Methodological Particularism and Descriptive Intuition Skepticism.. 11 Against Methodological Particularism .................................................................... 12 Against Descriptive Intuition Skepticism ............................................................... 28 Chapter Three: The Heterogeneity of Intuition .............................................................. 68 Ambiguities ................................................................................................................. 68 Varieties of Intuition ................................................................................................. 75 The Diversity of Intuition Contents ....................................................................... 82 The Particularity of Intuitions .................................................................................. 86 Objections ................................................................................................................... 89 Chapter Four: Metaphilosophical Arguments ............................................................... 101 Calibration ................................................................................................................. 101 Intuitional Sensitivity ............................................................................................... 109 Self-Defeat ................................................................................................................ 124 Innocence-by-Association ...................................................................................... 133 Chapter Five: Carving Intuitions More Finely ............................................................... 140 Causal Carving .......................................................................................................... 143 Context Carving ....................................................................................................... 162 Content Carving ....................................................................................................... 178 Conclusion ................................................................................................................ 194 Bibliography ........................................................................................................................ 196 vii Chapter One: Introduction “There are few things that we phrase properly; most things we phrase badly; but what we are trying to say is understood.” -Augustine, Confessions, XI.20.26 1. INTRODUCTION The thesis of this monograph is a plea: stop talking about intuitions.1 Stop utilizing the locution ‘it is intuitive that p.’ Stop phrasing sentences ‘intuitively, p.’ Above all, stop reporting ‘I have the intuition that p.’ The reason that we should stop talking about intuitions isn’t that intuitions cannot be calibrated against an independent standard, as Cummins 1998 and Weinberg et al. 2012 claim. The reason isn’t that appeals to intuition are without any respectable theoretical foundation, as Hintikka 1999 and Hales 2000 claim. The reason isn’t that appeals to intuition conflict with our commitment to naturalism, as Devitt 1994, Ladyman & Ross 2007, and Maclaurin & Dyke 2012 claim. Nor is the reason that appeals to intuitions are argumentative third-wheels, as Cappelen 2012, Molyneux 2014, and Deutsch 2015 claim. And the reason isn’t that intuitions are sensitive to non-evidential factors, as Machery et al. 2004; Swain, Alexander, & Weinberg 2008; Buckwalter & Stich 2014; and Costa et al. 2014 claim. The reason that we should stop talking about intuitions is that ‘intuition’ does not pick out a monolithic, unified kind. The category represents a diverse collection of distinct mental states.2 The heterogeneity of the category makes for a term that is vague and 1 This plea is directed at, and restricted to, professional philosophers. Intuition talk in other disciplines may be unproblematic. 2 Indeed, some types of intuition-talk don’t refer to mental states at all. 1 imprecise. Our philosophy would be much improved if we adopted a finer-grained taxonomy to reflect this heterogeneity. Or so I shall argue. 2. PROJECT OVERVIEW Metaphilosophy is the philosophical study of philosophy itself. Metaphilosophers attempt to articulate and evaluate the aim(s) of philosophy, the value(s) of philosophy, and the method(s) of philosophy. The specific objectives of metaphilosopy are many and varied. In this monograph, I concentrate on two central metaphilosophical tasks. I’ll call them RELIABILITY and JUSTIFICATION: RELIABILITY Evaluate the reliability of the purported evidence that figures in philosophical arguments JUSTIFICATION Evaluate the justificatory status of relying on the purported evidence that figures in philosophical arguments I don’t intend to undertake these tasks. I merely intend to clarify what would be required in order to undertake them. A few clarificatory remarks are in order. RELIABILITY and JUSTIFICATION presuppose some answer to the descriptive question ‘what sort of things figure in philosophical arguments?’. This is no easy question. Much of contemporary metaphilosophy assumes that intuitions are the sort of thing that either appear among the premises of philosophical arguments or support the premises of philosophical arguments, and I defend that assumption in chapter two. I include ‘purported’ in my formulation of the goals because if evidence is factive, its reliability is guaranteed. Finally, the two goals are interrelated. The reliability of the purported evidence that figures in philosophical arguments may underwrite (or, indeed, constitute, if reliabilism is true) the justification for relying on that evidence. 2 The reliability of some belief-forming process Φ is a measure of the truth- conduciveness of Φ. Truth-conduciveness can be decomposed into two subjunctive components: SENSITIVITY and SAFETY: SENSITIVITY If p were false, Φ would not output that p SAFETY If Φ were to output that p, p would not be false A perfectly reliable (and hence infallible) belief-forming process
Recommended publications
  • Nihilist Perdurantism: a New Ontology of Material Objects
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy Philosophy 2017 NIHILIST PERDURANTISM: A NEW ONTOLOGY OF MATERIAL OBJECTS Brian Matthew Carlson University of Kentucky, [email protected] Author ORCID Identifier: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9625-2266 Digital Object Identifier: https://doi.org/10.13023/ETD.2017.268 Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Carlson, Brian Matthew, "NIHILIST PERDURANTISM: A NEW ONTOLOGY OF MATERIAL OBJECTS" (2017). Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy. 17. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/17 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| Eco Nihilism the Philosophicalcb 1St Edition
    ECO NIHILISM THE PHILOSOPHICALCB 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Wendy Lynne Lee | 9780739176887 | | | | | Eco-Nihilism: The Philosophical Geopolitics of the Climate Change Apocalypse Brian G. Stud East Eur Thought. The pay Eco Nihilism The Philosophicalcb 1st edition not bad but NOT what it Because miseries vastly outnumber pleasures, happiness is impossible, the philosopher argues, and subsequently advocates suicide. We simply don't care. The Buddha's response was that he only teaches the cessation of suffering. Gardiner - - Ethics 3 Not long ago, a Eco Nihilism The Philosophicalcb 1st edition leader of the B. Davis writes, for example: [40]. Nihilism Nihilism is the belief that all values are baseless and that nothing can be known or communicated. Edit this record. If our lives are needless then the only directive we have is to figure out how to find happiness in our momentary blip of consciousness. It has been over a century now since Nietzsche explored nihilism and its implications for civilization. Normative ethics. The Sociological Imagination ; Bell, Daniel. Translated by Graham Parkes; with Setsuko Aihara. Facebook Twitter. Derridean deconstructionists argue that this approach rather frees texts, individuals or organizations from a restrictive truth, and that deconstruction opens up the possibility of other ways of being. This epistemological cul-de-sac, Rorty concludes, leads inevitably to nihilism. This article is about the philosophical viewpoint. Lyotard argues that, rather than Eco Nihilism The Philosophicalcb 1st edition on an objective truth or method to prove their claims, philosophers legitimize their truths by reference to a story about the world that can't be separated from the age and system the stories belong to—referred to by Lyotard as meta-narratives.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Sense in Favor of Mereological Nihilism? (PDF)
    Common Sense in Favor of Mereological Nihilism? Michael Hanson University of Minnesota, Duluth 2013 Montana State University International Undergraduate Philosophy Conference Montana State University, Bozeman September 6-7, 2013 Abstract: Mereological nihilism, a theory in compositional metaphysics, has long suffered the objection that in virtue of its sheer anti-intuitive nature, it ought not to be believed. This essay seeks to address this objection. To this end this essay will provide a brief account of the nihilist position, an example of the objection that is prototypical, and an original attempt to meet this objection by providing a reasonable example of “common sense” that contains intuitions directed at mereological nihilism. In contemporary metaphysics it is believed that common sense, or “folk” intuitions, speak unilaterally against the position of mereological nihilism, and equipped with this belief the critics of mereological nihilism have argued the point that in virtue of this supposed overwhelming anti- intuitive charge, the nihilist position of composition ought not to be taken seriously. In this essay I seek to erode the charge that “folk” belief speaks unilaterally against nihilism. To that end I will provide a brief summary of mereological nihilism, a typical example of the too anti-intuitive objection, and an original, reasonable, example of common sense lending itself to the nihilist position. To understand the nihilist position I find that the following example is most instructive. Consider a statue made of clay; how many objects would you say are present? There is of course the statue, but is there not also the quantity of clay which existed prior to being molded and would continue to exist if some vandal were to smash the statue? It seems like in the case of the statue there are two objects sharing the same space.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Traynor Phd Thesis
    MODAL ARGUMENTS, POSSIBLE EVIDENCE AND CONTINGENT METAPHYSICS Michael Thomas Traynor A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2017 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/15595 This item is protected by original copyright Modal Arguments, Possible Evidence and Contingent Metaphysics. Michael Thomas Traynor This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews Date of submission: 23/09/2016 1 Abstract. The present work explores various ways in which contingent evidence can impact metaphysics, while advocating that, just as a scientific realist allows for ampliative inferences to the unobservable, ampliative inferences from possible evidence can warrant possibility claims that lie beyond the reach of sensorial imagination. In slogan form: possible evidence is a guide to possibility. Drawing on Shoemaker’s (1969) argument for the possibility of time without change, I advocate the following principle: If there is a possible world at which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that p, then we should conclude that p is possibly true. This provides a route to contingentism in metaphysics, for, if one considers that there are worlds in which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that p, and worlds in which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that not-p, then my principle tells us that we should conclude that possibly-p and possibly not-p, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereological Idealism∗
    Mereological Idealism∗ Kenneth L. Pearce Valparaiso University November 24, 2015 As Democritus used to say, [composite objects] exist by convention, not by nature. Leibniz to De Volder, 20 June 17031 One of the central questions of mereology { the theory of parts and wholes { is what Peter van Inwagen has dubbed the `Special Composition Question': \in what circumstances do things add up to or compose something? When does unity arise out of plurality?" (van Inwagen 1990, 31). Van Inwagen distin- guishes between `moderate' answers to this question, which say that composi- tion occurs sometimes, and `extreme' answers which say that composition occurs always (mereological universalism) or never (mereological nihilism). Common- sense clearly takes a moderate approach, but philosophers have found serious difficulties with moderate answers to the Special Composition Question, and especially with those answers that seek to approximate commonsense. In this paper, I defend a classical solution to this problem: \it is the mind that maketh each thing to be one" (Berkeley[1744] 1948{1957, x356).2 Accord- ing to this view, which I call `mereological idealism,' it is when a plurality is unified in thought under a concept that a unified whole comes to exist. After explaining the view in more detail, I show how it escapes three standard argu- ments against commonsense answers to the Special Composition Question.3 ∗This is a pre-publication draft circulated by the author for comment. The final version is expected to appear in Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, ed. Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenneth L. Pearce (Oxford University Press). 1. Lodge 2013, 264-265, translation modified.
    [Show full text]
  • Schaffer's Priority Monism and the Problem of Junky
    SCHAFFER’S PRIORITY MONISM AND THE PROBLEM OF JUNKY POSSIBLE WORLDS A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Cole Singletary May, 2015 © Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously published materials Thesis written by Cole Singletary B.A., Valdosta State University, 2013 M.A., Kent State University, 2015 Approved by Deborah Smith, Masters Advisor Deborah Barnbaum, Department Chair, Department of Philosophy James L. Blank, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS............................................................................................................................iv INTRODUCTORY SECTION.....................................................................................................................1 CHAPTER 1: GROUNDING METAPHYSICS AND ACTUAL CONCRETE OBJECTS Section 1.1: The Quine-Carnap Debate............................ ...............................................................5 Section 1.2: Some Basics on Grounding…………………….........................................................11 Section 1.3: Priority Monism and Actual Concrete Objects...........................................................17 CHAPTER 2: SOME ARGUMENTS FOR PRIOTITY MONISM Section 2.1: Priority Monism, the Cosmos, and Parsimony...........................................................21 Section 2.2: An Argument from Internal Relatedness....................................................................24 Section 2.3:
    [Show full text]
  • Mereological Nihilism and the Special Arrangement Question
    Mereological Nihilism and the Special Arrangement Question Andrew Brenner Penultimate version of paper. Final version of paper published in Synthese, May 2015, Volume 192, Issue 5, pp 1295-1314 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Do Nihilists Need To Answer the Special Arrangement Ques- tion? 4 3 Can Nihilists Answer the Special Arrangement Question? 9 4 Can Nihilists Answer the Special Arrangement Question With- out Undermining Nihilism? 19 5 Conclusion 24 Abstract: Mereological nihilism is the thesis that composite objects { ob- jects with proper parts { do not exist. Nihilists generally paraphrase talk of composite objects F into talk of there being \xs arranged F-wise" (for ex- ample, while nihilists deny that there are tables, they concede that there are \xs arranged table-wise"). Recently several philosophers have argued that nihilism is defective insofar as nihilists are either unable to say what they mean by such phrases as \there are xs arranged F-wise," or that nihilists are unable to employ such phrases without incurring significant costs, perhaps even undermining one of the chief motivations for nihilism. In this paper I defend nihilism against these objections. A key theme of the paper is this: if nihilists need to employ such phrases as \there are xs arranged F-wise," non-nihilists will need to do so as well. Accordingly, any costs incurred by the nihilist when she employs such phrases will be shared by everyone else. 1 What's more, such phrases are intelligible when employed by the nihilist, as well as when they are employed by the non-nihilist, insofar as analyses of such phrases will not essentially involve mereological concepts incompatible with nihilism.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereological Nihilism and Puzzles About Material Objects
    MEREOLOGICAL NIHILISM AND PUZZLES ABOUT MATERIAL OBJECTS BY BRADLEY RETTLER Abstract: Mereological nihilism is the view that no objects have proper parts. Despite how counter-intuitive it is, it is taken quite seriously, largely because it solves a number of puzzles in the metaphysics of material objects – or so its proponents claim. In this article, I show that for every puzzle that mereological nihilism solves, there is a similar puzzle that (a) it doesn’t solve, and (b) every other solution to the original puzzle does solve. Since the solutions to the new puzzles apply just as well to the old puzzles, the old puzzles provide no motivation to be a mereological nihilist. 1. Introduction Mereological nihilism is the view that no objects have any proper parts.1 Most people think that at any given time, they’re surrounded by counterex- amples to mereological nihilism – tables, chairs, hats, themselves…. Mereological nihilism says that those things don’texist,ortheydon’thave any proper parts. But most people think it’s obvious that such things do exist, and it’s also obvious that they have proper parts. One might wonder, then, why anyone would accept mereological nihilism. A main motivation has been that mereological nihilism solves a number of puzzles in the metaphysics of material objects2;it’s been thought to be a solution to coincidence puzzles, the Sorites paradox, the problem of overdetermination, the problem of arbitrariness, the problem of Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (2018) 842–868 DOI: 10.1111/papq.12220 ©2018TheAuthor Pacific Philosophical Quarterly © 2018 University of Southern California and John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
    [Show full text]
  • Why a Gunk World Is Compatible with Nihilism About Objects
    Why a Gunk World is Compatible with Nihilism about Objects Baptiste Le Bihan Department of Philosophy, University of Rennes 1 Ted Sider argues that nihilism about objects is incompatible with the metaphysi- cal possibility of gunk and takes this point to show that nihilism is awed. I shall describe one kind of nihilism able to answer this objection. I believe that most of the things we usually encounter do not exist. at is, I take talk of macroscopic ob- jects and macroscopic properties to refer to sets of fundamental properties, which are invoked as a matter of linguistic convention. is view is a kind of nihilism: it rules out the existence of objects; that is, from an ontological point of view, there are no objects. But unlike the moderate nihilism of Mark Heller, Peter van Inwagen and Trenton Merricks that claims that most objects do not exist, I endorse a radical nihilism according to which there are no objects in the world, but only properties instantiated in spacetime. As I will show, radical nihilism is perfectly compatible with the metaphysical possibility of gunk. It is also compatible with the epistemic possibility that we actually live in a gunk world. e objection raised by Ted Sider only applies to moderate nihilism that admits some objects in its ontology. Keywords: ontology, metaphysics, gunk, nihilism, object, spacetime, space, time Õ. Between a Nihilist World and a Gunk World Ted Sider(ÕÉÉì) argues that nihilism about objects is incompatible with the metaphysical possibility of gunk and takes this point to show that nihilism is awed.Õ I believe him to be right.
    [Show full text]
  • Applications and Extensions of Counterpart Theory
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations Dissertations and Theses November 2017 Applications and Extensions of Counterpart Theory Bridgette Peterson University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_2 Part of the Metaphysics Commons Recommended Citation Peterson, Bridgette, "Applications and Extensions of Counterpart Theory" (2017). Doctoral Dissertations. 1117. https://doi.org/10.7275/10671975.0 https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_2/1117 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Dissertations and Theses at ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. APPLICATIONS AND EXTENSIONS OF COUNTERPART THEORY A Dissertation Presented by BRIDGETTE BAILIE PETERSON Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 2017 Philosophy © Copyright by Bridgette Bailie Peterson 2017 All Rights Reserved APPLICATIONS AND EXTENSIONS OF COUNTERPART THEORY A Dissertation Presented By BRIDGETTE BAILIE PETERSON Approved as to style and content by: Maya Eddon, Chair Phillip Bricker, Member Michael Tooley, Member Angelika Kratzer, Member Joseph Levine, Department Head Philosophy DEDICATION To John Friedrich ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS A couple of decades ago, I would have thought it absurd if someone told me that I would be finishing my PhD in philosophy. I did not really know what philosophy was, and I was far from going back to school to get a high school diploma, let alone an advanced degree. This journey has been long and tumultuous, and the only way that any success has been possible is through the support and assistance of a great number of kind and capable people.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereological Nihilism and Theoretical Unification
    Mereological Nihilism and Theoretical Unification Andrew Brenner Forthcoming in Analytic Philosophy. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Nihilism and Theoretical Unification (I) 2 3 Nihilism and Theoretical Unification (II) 9 4 Composition as Identity to the Rescue? 17 5 Conclusion 21 Abstract: Mereological nihilism (henceforth just \nihilism") is the thesis that composition never occurs. Nihilism has often been defended on the basis of its theoretical simplicity, including its ontological simplicity and its ideologi- cal simplicity (roughly, nihilism's ability to do without primitive mereological predicates). In this paper I defend nihilism on the basis of the theoretical uni- fication conferred by nihilism, which is, roughly, nihilism's capacity to allow us to take fewer phenomena as brute and inexplicable. This represents a respect in which nihilism enjoys greater theoretical simplicity than its rivals which has not yet been explored, and which is immune to many of the objec- tions which have been leveled against previous arguments for nihilism from nihilism's theoretical simplicity. Composition as identity might be thought to confer a similar degree of theoretical unification as nihilism. I end the paper by arguing that this is not the case. 1 1 Introduction Mereological nihilism (henceforth just \nihilism") says that composition never occurs. So, tables, chairs, dogs, tennis balls, and so on, don't exist, under the assumption that these things are composite objects if they exist. Recent debates over mereological nihilism have largely turned on the alleged relative theoretical simplicity of nihilism vs its rivals1 (see, e.g., Dorr 2002; Schaffer 2007; Horgan, Potrˇc2008: Ch.7; Bennett 2009; Sider 2013; Cowling 2013, 2014; Kriegel 2013; Woodard 2013; Tallant 2014; Hawley 2014; Korman 2015; Smid 2015).
    [Show full text]
  • A Dilemma for Buddhist Reductionism
    A DILEMMA FOR BUDDHIST REDUCTIONISM Javier Hidalgo Jepson School of Leadership Studies, University of Richmond [email protected] I. Introduction Buddhists accept the doctrine of non-self. Almost all Buddhists agree that selves or persons are unreal.1 Instead, the term “person” is merely a way of referring to a causal series of psychophysical elements. Nonetheless, Buddhists also claim that persons are real in a different sense. Persons are conventionally real. So, Buddhist philosophers deny the ultimate reality of persons and affirm their conventional existence. How is it possible for persons to exist and yet not exist? Buddhist Reductionism is an answer to this question. Buddhist Reductionism gives an analysis of what it means for persons to lack ultimate existence and retain conventional existence. Buddhist Reductionists claim that persons don’t belong in our final ontology. So, it is false that persons ultimately exist. But persons are conventionally real in the sense that positing the existence of persons is useful. If we accept that persons are real, this will help us to achieve desirable outcomes, such as the minimization of suffering. Further- more, Buddhist Reductionists extend their analysis to all composite entities, not just persons. They defend a kind of mereological nihilism according to which all partite entities are unreal. Buddhist Reductionists contend that the only real existents are particular bundles of tropes, such as color and shape. In recent years, Mark Siderits and other philosophers have developed important and powerful arguments in favor of Buddhist Reductionism.2 In this article, I will raise an objection to Buddhist Reductionism. My objection centers on the nature of reasons.
    [Show full text]