Chapter 6 Idealism and Empire

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter 6 Idealism and Empire Chapter 6 Idealism and Empire When the hysterical vision strikes The facade of an era it manifests Its insidious relations. 1 — Ern Malley OW far can philosophy diverge from common sense? This is a question, of course, for philosophy, and one that has pro- Hduced a range of divergent opinions.2 Some regard the deliverances of common sense as data that philosophy can explain, but not deny. Others dismiss common sense as so much Stone Age metaphysics, incorporating the confusions of the Cave Man in the street in much the same way that ordinary language includes antique science like ‘The sun rises in the east.’ Now, if departures from common sense are allowed, how far can you go? Surely there is a limit. David Armstrong’s first year lectures on Descartes included this joke: A philosophy lecturer noticed one of his students looking more and more worried as the course progressed. The student was absent for a while, then staggered in unkempt, dirty, obviously unslept. ‘Professor, Professor,’ he said, ‘You’ve got to help me. Do I really exist?’ The Professor looked around and said, ‘Who wants to know?’ 1 Ern Malley, Collected Poems (Sydney, 1993), p. 36. 2 K. Campbell, ‘Philosophy and common sense’, Philosophy 63 (1988): pp. 161–74; cf. P. James, ‘Questioning the evidence of commonsense’, Melbourne Journal of Politics 14 (1982/3): pp. 46–57; J. Kennett & M. Smith, ‘Philosophy and common sense: The case of weakness of will’, in M. Michael & J. O’Leary-Hawthorne, eds, Philosophy in Mind: The Place of Philosophy in the Study of Mind (Dordrecht, 1994), pp. 141–57. 112 Corrupting the Youth The point of Descartes’ dictum, ‘I think, therefore I am’ is that, if you really try, you can doubt the existence of everything outside your own mind at least in principle. But there is no denying the existence of yourself, at least if ‘yourself’ means only the thinking being that you directly experience. The most determined school of philosophy in pushing doubt to this theoretical limit is idealism. The best-known version of idealism is that of George Berkeley, the eighteenth-century Irish bishop who maintained that there were no physical objects outside the mind at all. Instead, he thought, God causes directly the play of (apparent) per- ceptions on our psyches. Hector Monro’s Sonneteer’s History of Phi- losophy, one of the shorter introductions to the subject, summarises Berkeley’s position as follows: ‘The scientific cosmos’, grumbled Berkeley, ‘Is, once you penetrate beneath the patter, Made up of something mystical called Matter. It’s not just that you see it through glass darkly, You cannot see the stuff at all. It’s starkly Devoid of scent and sound and colour, flatter And duller than a garden party’s chatter. We’re all bamboozled by the learned-clerkly Romantic balderdash. Reality Is surely what we touch and hear and see. If what our senses yield is in the mind, Then so’s Reality.’ At once maligned, Good Berkeley’s universe, because it’s mental Is labelled thin, ethereal, transcendental.3 Needless to say, it is not a widely held opinion. Indeed, it invites jokes about why anybody who holds it should be concerned to ex- press it: who does he think he is talking to? The significance of Berkeley lies actually more in his arguments than in his conclusions. The colonial poet Charles Harpur wrote: His logic puzzles so, it don’t convince. So wide his arguments, we half suspect them Of aberrations though we can’t detect them.4 3 D.H. Monro, The Sonneteer’s History of Philosophy (Melbourne, 1981), p. 20; also in Philosophy 55 (1980): pp. 363–75 (repr. with permission of Dugald and Gordon Monro); comments on the causes of such opinions in H. Caton, ‘Pascal’s syndrome: Positivism as a symptom of depression and mania’, Zygon 21 (1986): pp. 319–52. 4 Quoted in Between Two Worlds: ‘Loss of Faith’ and Late Nineteenth Century Australian Literature, ed. A. Clark, J. Fletcher & R. Marsden (Sydney, 1979), p. 18. 6. Idealism and Empire 113 This is quite wrong, as Berkeley has an exceptional ability to make gross mistakes clearly, and is therefore in regular use as target practice for philosophy undergraduates — as David Stove said, an undergradu- ate course without Berkeley is like a zoo without elephants.5 He is important not only for students: David Armstrong’s early works, in which he refined the rigorous style of argumentation that became his hallmark, are on Berkeley.6 The only sign of Berkeleian idealism being taken seriously in Aus- tralia was an event in 1936, when the Sydney Anglican Church wheeled out the Lord Archbishop of Armagh and Primate of All Ire- land, the Most Reverend C.F. D’Arcy, to give a talk at Sydney Uni- versity. The Archbishop said that Berkeley’s doctrine, although it had been attacked severely, had not, in his opinion, been overthrown. ‘The principles of his philosophy supplied a great spiritual need at the present time.’ 7 No doubt there was a spiritual need, especially with John Anderson firmly in the chair of philosophy, but Berkeleian ide- alism is a cure surely at once worse than the disease, and necessarily ineffective. The Primate’s suggestion that the point of idealism is to pervade the universe with a general tone of moral uplift, amenable to religion, is even more evident in the other variant of the theory, Absolute Ide- alism. This is a late Victorian construction with some resemblance to the wedding-cake architecture beloved of the period. It is possibly too alien a thought-world to understand at this distance, but the gen- eral idea is that, while the physical world may exist, its nature is es- sentially mental rather than (what we take to be) material. Everything is interconnected, and is a manifestation of the Absolute, which is something like God, but less crudely personal, and also less distant from oneself.8 Absolute Idealism in its heyday — around the 1890s — became the first and only philosophy to be accepted as orthodoxy in 5 D.M. Armstrong, Course submission for 1974. 6 D.M. Armstrong, Berkeley’s Theory of Vision (Melbourne, 1960); Berkeley’s Philosophical Writings, ed. with an introduction by D.M. Armstrong (New York, 1965); Berkeley, the Push and Australian painting in H. McQueen, Suburbs of the Sacred (Ringwood, 1988), pp. 29–31. 7 SMH 12/6/1936, p. 10; some parallels in Christian Science: R. Dessaix, A Mother’s Disgrace (Sydney, 1994), pp. 79–81. 8 J. Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London, 1957), chs 3–4; S. Candlish, ‘The status of idealism in Bradley’s metaphysics’, Idealistic Studies 11 (1981): pp. 242–53; S. Candlish, ‘Idealism and Bradley’s logic’, Idealistic Studies 12 (1982): pp. 251–9; S. Candlish, ‘Bradley, F.H.’, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 1 pp. 857–63; J. O’Leary-Hawthorne, ‘Anti- realism, before and after Moore’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 12 (1995): pp. 443–67. 114 Corrupting the Youth the whole learned world (Paris, Heidelberg, Edinburgh, Peking, Adelaide ...). Then it simply evaporated. John Anderson always re- garded idealism as the prime enemy, but by his time there were hardly any live idealists left to devour — in the philosophical world, at least, though as we saw in chapter 1, there were some in the New South Wales Parliament. The importance of idealism for Australia is that all of the first philosophers in Australian universities were adher- ents, including, for example, Australia’s only philosophical knights, Sir Francis Anderson at Sydney and Sir William Mitchell at Adelaide.9 In his memorable attack, ‘Idealism: A Victorian horror story’, David Stove writes, Nineteenth-century idealism, accordingly, provided an important hold- ing-station or decompression chamber, for that century’s vast flood of in- tellectual refugees from Christianity; or at any rate, for the more philoso- phically inclined among them. The situation of these people was truly pitiful. The burden of their biblical embarrassments had become intoler- able ... The problem was how to part with the absurdities of Christianity, while keeping cosmic consolation: no one dreamt of parting with the lat- ter as well (it should hardly be necessary to say), or at any rate no philoso- pher did.10 An idealist, he says, is one of a philosophical turn of mind, who can no longer stomach the raw barbarisms of popular religion, but ‘in whom, nevertheless, the religious determination to have the universe congenial is still sovereign.’ This was a period in which a wide variety of remedies were tried by the less philosophical, including the Wis- dom of the East, theosophy, spiritualism, and so on,11 as well as relig- 9 S. Grave, A History of Philosophy in Australia (St Lucia, 1984), ch. 2; J. Passmore, ‘Philosophy’, in The Pattern of Australian Culture, ed. A.L. McLeod (Melbourne, 1963), pp. 131–69; obituary of Mitchell in AJP 40 (1962): pp. 261–3; W.M. Davies, A Mind’s Own Place: The Life and Thought of Sir William Mitchell, (Lewiston, NY, 2003); account of Francis Anderson’s philosophy in G. Melleuish, Cultural Liberalism in Australia (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 87–95; W.M. O’Neil, ‘Francis Anderson’, in ADB, vol. 7 pp. 53– 5; obituary in AJPP 19 (1941): pp. 97–101; ‘Francis Anderson: Professor and citizen’, Hermes 27 (3) (Nov 1921); Francis Anderson’s papers in Sydney University Archives listed at www.usyd.edu.au/arms/archives/anderson.htm ; a late example of idealism in G. James, Philosophy: A Synopsis (Brisbane, 1957). 10 D.C. Stove, The Plato Cult and Other Philosophical Follies (Oxford, 1991), pp.
Recommended publications
  • Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1947–2016: a Retrospective Using Citation and Social Network Analyses
    Global Intellectual History ISSN: 2380-1883 (Print) 2380-1891 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rgih20 Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1947–2016: a retrospective using citation and social network analyses Martin Davies & Angelito Calma To cite this article: Martin Davies & Angelito Calma (2018): Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1947–2016: a retrospective using citation and social network analyses, Global Intellectual History To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/23801883.2018.1478233 Published online: 28 May 2018. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rgih20 GLOBAL INTELLECTUAL HISTORY https://doi.org/10.1080/23801883.2018.1478233 Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1947–2016: a retrospective using citation and social network analyses Martin Davies a and Angelito Calma b aGraduate School of Education, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia; bWilliams Centre for Learning Advancement, Faculty of Business and Economics, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia ABSTRACT KEYWORDS In anticipation of the journal’s centenary in 2027 this paper provides Citation analysis; bibliometric a citation network analysis of all available citation and publication analysis; social network data of the Australasian Journal of Philosophy (1923–2017). A total analysis; philosophy; of 2,353 academic articles containing 21,772 references were Australasian Journal of Philosophy; Kumu collated and analyzed. This includes 175 articles that contained author-submitted keywords, 415 publisher-tagged keywords and 519 articles that had abstracts. Results initially focused on finding the most published authors, most cited articles and most cited authors within the journal, followed by most discussed topics and emerging patterns using keywords and abstracts.
    [Show full text]
  • A Life of Thinking the Andersonian Tradition in Australian Philosophy a Chronological Bibliography
    own. One of these, of the University Archive collections of Anderson material (2006) owes to the unstinting co-operation of of Archives staff: Julia Mant, Nyree Morrison, Tim Robinson and Anne Picot. I have further added material from other sources: bibliographical A Life of Thinking notes (most especially, James Franklin’s 2003 Corrupting the The Andersonian Tradition in Australian Philosophy Youth), internet searches, and compilations of Andersonian material such as may be found in Heraclitus, the pre-Heraclitus a chronological bibliography Libertarian Broadsheet, the post-Heraclitus Sydney Realist, and Mark Weblin’s JA and The Northern Line. The attempt to chronologically line up Anderson’s own work against the work of James Packer others showing some greater or lesser interest in it, seems to me a necessary move to contextualise not only Anderson himself, but Australian philosophy and politics in the twentieth century and beyond—and perhaps, more broadly still, a realist tradition that Australia now exports to the world. Introductory Note What are the origins and substance of this “realist tradition”? Perhaps the best summary of it is to be found in Anderson’s own The first comprehensive Anderson bibliography was the one reading, currently represented in the books in Anderson’s library constructed for Studies in Empirical Philosophy (1962). It listed as bequeathed to the University of Sydney. I supply an edited but Anderson’s published philsophical work and a fair representation unabridged version of the list of these books that appears on the of his published social criticism. In 1984 Geraldine Suter published John Anderson SETIS website, to follow the bibliography proper.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwinian Fairytales
    David Stove Darwinian Fairytales Selfish Genes, Errors of Heredity, and Other Fables of Evolution To my wife Jess and our children Robert and Judith Darwinian Fairytales DAVID STOVE Avebury Aldershot • Brookfield USA • Hong Kong • Singapore • Sydney © Judith Stove 1995 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Published by Avebury Ashgate Publishing Ltd Gower House Croft Road Aldershot Hants GUI 13HR England Ashgate Publishing Company Old Post Road Brookfield Vermont 05036 USA British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Stove, David C. Darwinian Fairytales. - (Avebury Series in Philosophy) I. Title II. Series 116 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 95- 83037 ISBN 185972 306 3 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Ipswich Book Co. Ltd., Ipswich, Suffolk Contents Acknowledgements vi Preface vii Essay I : Darwinism's Dilemma 1 Essay II : Where Darwin First Went Wrong about Man 13 Essay III : 'But what about War, Pestilence, and All That?' 31 Essay IV : Population, Privilege, and Malthus'Retreat 39 Essay V : A Horse in the Bathroom or the Struggle for Life 53 Essay VI : Tax and the Selfish Girl or Does Altruism Need Inverted 79 Commas? Essay VII : Genetic Calvinism or Demons and Dawkins 118 Essay VIII: 'He Ain't Heavy, He's My Brother' or Altruism and 137 Shared Genes Essay IX : A New Religion 171 Essay X : Paley's Revenge or Purpose Regained 178 Essay XI : Errors of Heredity or The Irrelevance of Darwinism to 212 Human Life Acknowledgements I owe thanks to far more people than I can name, for their critical comments on draft-parts of this book.
    [Show full text]
  • Discrete and Continuous: a Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics
    Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 7 | Issue 2 July 2017 Discrete and Continuous: A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics James Franklin University of New South Wales Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the Other Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Franklin, J. "Discrete and Continuous: A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 7 Issue 2 (July 2017), pages 355-378. DOI: 10.5642/jhummath.201702.18 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol7/iss2/18 ©2017 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. Discrete and Continuous: A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics James Franklin1 School of Mathematics & Statistics, University of New South Wales, Sydney, AUSTRALIA [email protected] Synopsis The distinction between the discrete and the continuous lies at the heart of mathematics. Discrete mathematics (arithmetic, algebra, combinatorics, graph theory, cryptography, logic) has a set of concepts, techniques, and application ar- eas largely distinct from continuous mathematics (traditional geometry, calculus, most of functional analysis, differential equations, topology).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Phil. 4400 Notes #1: the Problem of Induction I. Basic Concepts
    Phil. 4400 Notes #1: The problem of induction I. Basic concepts: The problem of induction: • Philosophical problem concerning the justification of induction. • Due to David Hume (1748). Induction: A form of reasoning in which a) the premises say something about a certain group of objects (typically, observed objects) b) the conclusion generalizes from the premises: says the same thing about a wider class of objects, or about further objects of the same kind (typically, the unobserved objects of the same kind). • Examples: All observed ravens so far have been The sun has risen every day for the last 300 black. years. So (probably) all ravens are black. So (probably) the sun will rise tomorrow. Non-demonstrative (non-deductive) reasoning: • Reasoning that is not deductive. • A form of reasoning in which the premises are supposed to render the conclusion more probable (but not to entail the conclusion). Cogent vs. Valid & Confirm vs. Entail : ‘Cogent’ arguments have premises that confirm (render probable) their conclusions. ‘Valid’ arguments have premises that entail their conclusions. The importance of induction: • All scientific knowledge, and almost all knowledge depends on induction. • The problem had a great influence on Popper and other philosophers of science. Inductive skepticism: Philosophical thesis that induction provides no justification for ( no reason to believe) its conclusions. II. An argument for inductive skepticism 1. There are (at most) 3 kinds of knowledge/justified belief: a. Observations b. A priori knowledge c. Conclusions based on induction 2. All inductive reasoning presupposes the “Inductive Principle” (a.k.a. the “uniformity principle”): “The course of nature is uniform”, “The future will resemble the past”, “Unobserved objects will probably be similar to observed objects” 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Papers in History and Methodology of Analytic Philosophy
    Papers in History and Methodology of Analytic Philosophy Brian Weatherson March 5, 2014 Contents 1 What Good are Counterexamples? 1 2 Morality, Fiction and Possibility 20 3 David Lewis 46 4 Humean Supervenience 81 5 Lewis, Naturalness and Meaning 96 6 Centrality and Marginalisation 114 7 Keynes and Wittgenstein 128 8 Doing Philosophy With Words 144 9 In Defense of a Kripkean Dogma 152 Co-authored with Jonathan Ichikawa and Ishani Maitra Bibliography 161 What Good are Counterexamples? e following kind of scenario is familiar throughout analytic philosophy. A bold philosopher proposes that all Fs are Gs. Another philosopher proposes a particular case that is, intuitively, an F but not a G. If intuition is right, then the bold philosopher is mistaken. Alternatively, if the bold philosopher is right, then intuition is mistaken, and we have learned something from philosophy. Can this alternative ever be realised, and if so, is there a way to tell when it is? In this paper, I will argue that the answer to the rst question is yes, and that recognising the right answer to the second question should lead to a change in some of our philosophical practices. e problem is pressing because there is no agreement across the sub-disciplines of phi- losophy about what to do when theory and intuition clash. In epistemology, particularly in the theory of knowledge, and in parts of metaphysics, particularly in the theory of causation, it is almost universally assumed that intuition trumps theory. Shope’s e Analysis of Knowl- edge contains literally dozens of cases where an interesting account of knowledge was jettisoned because it clashed with intuition about a particular case.
    [Show full text]
  • Vagrancy and the Victorians : the Social Construction of the Vagrant In
    VAGRANCY AND THE VICTORIANS: THE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE VAGRANT IN MELBOURNE, 1880-1907 SUSANNE ELIZABETH DAVIES RID THESiS, HISTORY DEPARTMENT, UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE, 1990 (This thesis does not exceed 100,000 words,) In Memory of my Father CONTENTS Page List of Figures 4 List of Illustrations 6 List of Abbreviations 9 Acknowledgements 10 Abstract 12 Introduction 15 Chapter One: A World of Difference 42 Chapter Two: The Evolution of the Vagrancy Laws 115 Chapter Three: Policing the Victorian Vagrancy Law 145 Chapter Four: Trial and Error 216 Chapter Five: Punishing and Reforming 274 Chapter Six: A System in Crisis $43 Chapter Seven: New Solutions for an Old Problem 397 Conclusion 450 Appendix One: Statistical Method 455 Appendix Two: Statistics relating to the Arrest and Imprisonment of Vagrants in Victoria, 1888-1907. 461 Appendix Three: Statistics relating to Vagrancy Cases heard by the Melbourne Court of Petty Sessions, 1 May 1888 - 30 April 1901. 468 Bibliography 478 4 FIGURES Page Figure 3.1: Vagrancy Arrests in Victoria, 1880-1907 161 Figure 3.2: Most Common Types of Arrests in Victoria, 1880-1905 162 Figure 3.3: Vagrancy Arrests as a Percentage of Total Arrests in Victoria, 1880-1907 163 Figure 3.4: '1 in 10' Sample - Vagrancy Cases heard by the MCPS, 1888-1901 167 Figure 3.5: '1 In 10' Sample - NVLMS/ILMS Cases as a Percentage of Total Vagrancy Cases, MCPS, 1888-1901 170 Figure 3.6: '1 in 10' Sample - Sex of Defendants in Vagrancy Cases, MCPS, 1888-1901 173 Figure 3.7: '1 in 10' Sample - Sex of Defendants in NVLMS/ILMS
    [Show full text]
  • The Melbourne Spectrum
    Chapter 7 The Melbourne Spectrum T IS an old saying that philosophy begins with a sense of wonder. That is a source of philosophy, but there is another one, the sense Ithat ‘that’s all bullshit (and I can explain why)’. Different philoso- phers draw on these sources in differing proportions. An uncritical sense of wonder leads one out of philosophy altogether, into the land of the fairies, to start angels from under stones, find morals at every turn and hug the rainforest. A philosopher near the other extreme — or one, like David Stove, actually occupying the extreme — will at least still be doing philosophy, but it will consist entirely of criticism of others. In the Australian intellectual tradition, the wonder/criticism mix varies not only according to individuals but according to cities. At least, it has since 1927, when John Anderson arrived in Australia and Sydney and Melbourne set off on different paths. Various writers, mainly from Melbourne, have discoursed at some length on the con- trasts between the two cities in their styles of thought, and with all due allowance made for the hot air factor, there is undoubtedly some distinct difference to be identified. Where Sydney intellectuals, fol- lowing Anderson, tend to be critical, pessimistic, classical and opposed to ‘meliorist’ schemes to improve society, Melbourne’s unctuous bien pensants are eager to ‘serve society’, meaning, to instruct the great and powerful how they ought to go about achieving Progress and the perfection of mankind.1 Manning Clark — and it is characteristic of 1 J. Docker, Australian Cultural Elites: Intellectual Traditions in Sydney and Melbourne (Sydney, 1974); V.
    [Show full text]
  • Ji Richapd'sylvan WHAT IS WRONG with APPLIED ETHICS Richard
    197d /> << Ji p. I Richapd'Sylvan WHAT IS WRONG WITH APPLIED ETHICS Richard Sylvan There is much that is wrong with and in applied ethics. Specifically, there are three comprehensive counts where things are wrong with the commodity concerned, applied ethics, that is with applied ethics so economically viewed.1 Namely on the following three counts: • extraneous, with the supply, delivery, consumption, and the like of applied ethics, AE. The category prominently includes the delivery of applied ethics: what is done, taught and learnt, by whom, and how qualified (e.g. whether taught by professionals, professional ethicists or philosophers in particular). That has tended to presume that the commodity itself is more or less in order, though the presumption lacks good pedigree, delivery of defective goods being almost as ubiquitous as business enterprise. The present focus is not however upon the delivery, or other features of the production and consumption, packaging and marketing of the goods, but on features of the commodity itself, applied ethics itself. Thus • intraneous counts, concerning the commodity itself, where a further two things are wrong: •• the applied idea, and ••• what the application is presumed to be made to, established - or, should it be, establishment - ethics. Because an implicit premiss in organising the Philosophy and Applied Ethics Re-examined1 Conference seems to have been that the issues to be addressed are predominantly extraneous, and because most of the papers actually relevant to the Conference topic appear to focus on extraneous issues, the present exercise, by contrast, concentrates upon intraneous problems, especially the third: radical deficiencies in what is supposed to be applied, prevailing ethics, and some extensive repairs thereto.
    [Show full text]
  • Concepts and Objects
    5 Concepts and Objects Ray Brassier 1. The question ‘What is real?’ stands at the crossroads of metaphysics and epistemol- ogy. More exactly, it marks the juncture of metaphysics and epistemology with the seal of conceptual representation. 2. Metaphysics understood as the investigation into what there is intersects with epistemology understood as the enquiry into how we know what there is. This intersec- tion of knowing and being is articulated through a theory of conception that explains how thought gains traction on being. 3. That the articulation of thought and being is necessarily conceptual follows from the Critical injunction which rules out any recourse to the doctrine of a pre-es- tablished harmony between reality and ideality. Thought is not guaranteed access to being; being is not inherently thinkable. There is no cognitive ingress to the real save through the concept. Yet the real itself is not to be confused with the concepts through which we know it. The fundamental problem of philosophy is to understand how to reconcile these two claims. 4. We gain access to the structure of reality via a machinery of conception which extracts intelligible indices from a world that is not designed to be intelligible and is not originarily infused with meaning. Meaning is a function of conception and con- ception involves representation—though this is not to say that conceptual representa- tion can be construed in terms of word-world mappings. It falls to conceptual ratio- nality to forge the explanatory bridge from thought to being. 5. Thus the metaphysical exploration of the structure of being can only be carried out in tandem with an epistemological investigation into the nature of conception.
    [Show full text]
  • The University Archives – Record 2011
    THE UNIVERSITY ARCHIVES 2011 Façade left standing: Front Cover image: Sir Charles Nicholson’s home ‘The Grange’ in Totteridge, Hertfordshire, was destroyed by fire in 1899 along with Nicholson’s collections, including journals and correspondence. These would have been extensive and a valuable record of his life and work. Nonetheless, a small amount of Nicholson’s personal archives was donated to the University Archives in the late 1980s, having been located with other family members. P4/5/3. At right: NIcholson in his library prior to the fire. P4/5/2a CONTENTS 02 ARCHIVIST’S NOTES 16 DINTENFASS AND SPACE 03 PERSONAL ARCHIVES TODAY, MISSION STS-BIC 06 WHY DID DAVID ARMSTRONG 18 EdGEWORTH DAVID’S TRY— SET UP THE JOHN ANDERSON REAL OR IMAGINED RESEARCH ARCHIVE? 26 ARCHIVES NEWS 12 JOURNEYS THROUGH THE 28 ACCESSIONS, SEPTEMBER 2010– ARCHIVES: THE EXTENDED OLIVER SEPTEMBER 2011 FAMILY 14 SNAPSHOTS AND GOLD NUGGETS ISSN 0301-4729 2 ARCHIVIST’S NOTES TIM ROBINSON, UNIVERSITY ARCHIVIST The March 1984 issue of Record contains an article by Nyree Morrison, Reference Archivist, has written on the then University Archivist Ken Smith on personal the unexpected connection between the University archives. Ken was keen to promote awareness and and NASA’s Space Shuttle documented in the use of the ‘...personal records of individuals closely papers of Dr Leopold Dintenfass, former Director connected with...’ the University. The theme is of Haemorheology and Biorheology and a Senior repeated in this issue, with some changes reflecting Research Fellow from 1962-75. the intervening 27 years. Another long time user of the University Archives, The first article is by Anne Picot, Deputy University Dr David Branagan, has provided an insight to some Archivist, on the nature and challenges of personal of the better known University personalities of a ‘papers’ in the world of email and web 2.0.
    [Show full text]
  • Chaffey Brothers Irrigation Works in Australia
    Engineers Australia Engineering Heritage Victoria Nomination Engineering Heritage Australia Heritage Recognition Program CHAFFEY BROTHERS IRRIGATION WORKS IN AUSTRALIA February 2017 Front Cover Photograph Caption The triple expansion steam engine designed by George Chaffey and built by Tangye Brothers, Birmingham which provided the first stage of pumping from the Murray River to Kings Billabong until replaced by electric pumps. The engine has been restored and is cared for and run by a group of Mildura volunteers. The use of marine type triple expansion steam engines direct driving to multiple centrifugal pumps was extremely innovative when George Chaffey designed the engine in the late 1880s however the date of the order on Tangye Brothers is not known. Image: Heritage Victoria. Chaffey Brothers Irrigation Works in Australia Nomination for Heritage Recognition page 2 TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE Table of Contents 3 1 Introduction 5 2 Heritage Nomination Letter 7 3 Heritage Assessment 8 3.1 Basic Data 8 3.2 Historical Notes 9 3.3 Heritage Listings 9 4 Assessment of Significance 10 4.1 Historical significance 10 4.2 Historic Individuals or Association 10 4.3 Creative or Technical Achievement 10 4.4 Research Potential 10 4.5 Social 11 4.6 Rarity 11 4.7 Representativeness 12 4.8 Integrity/Intactness 12 4.9 Statement of Significance 12 4.10 Area of Significance 15 5 Interpretation Plan 16 5.1 General Approach 16 5.2 The Interpretation Panel 5.3 Possible Interpretation themes for Interpretation Panels 17 8 References 18 9 Acknowledgments, Authors
    [Show full text]