Ability to Pay Theory of Taxation: Advocated by Ely, 320, 322; George

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ability to Pay Theory of Taxation: Advocated by Ely, 320, 322; George Index Ability to pay theory of taxation: advocated by Anarchists, nineteenth-century individualist: Ely, 320, 322; George on, 322; defects of, their critique of George, 234-53; accuse 387-88 George of Malthusianism, 236-37; Aesthetic argument against George's proposal: condemn George's Ricardianism, 237; advanced by Harris, 193 attack George's views on capital and Aimes, H. H. S.: his study of Cuban slave interest, 240-44; condemn land-value economy, 76-77 taxation, 236, 238, 239, 245, 246; their Alba, estates of the Duchess of, 343 confusion concerning George's concept of Alcazar Alvarez, Fr. Juan: biographical data, rent, 237-38; their views summarized on his appreciative remarks on George, rent, Ricardianism, unearned increment, 326, 327, 333; his critique of George, and land value, 240; their views on 326-41; considers single tax simplistic, 335; copyrights and patents, 244-45; tabular claims inconsistencies in George, 335; summary of their views compared with alleges practical difficulties in George's George's 249; their critique evaluated, proposal, 330-31; his commentary on 23848 passim. See also Hanson, William; George's island illustration, 332; his Ingalls, Joshua K.; and Tucker, Benjamin mistakes concerning George's proposal, R. 328-29, 331, 332, 335 (claims that George Anarcho-Capitalism, 354. See also Heath, proposes land nationalization, 329; claims Spencer; and Rothbard, Murray N. that George proposes equal division of Andelson, Robert V.: justifies territorial land, 329; claims that George predicates sovereignty, on George's premises, 150-51; individual happiness on welfare of society, quoted on effect on land ownership of 331; claims that George advocated George's proposal, 334. abolition of soldiers, lawyers, and priests, Andrews, E. Benjamin: regards faults 334; claims that George would single out attributed to George by Harris as actually agriculture for taxation, 328; shares recommendations, 191 Cathrein's failure to perceive that Argyll, George J. D. Campbell, Duke of: agricultural sites do not yield the highest George replies to his criticism, 17 rent, 127; thinks the value of a site is based Arizona: hydroponic production of tomatoes on the labor expended on it, 329-30, 331, in, 385 332); accepts labor theory of ownership, Asquith, Herbert H., 357 329; his suggestions regarding underuse of Assessment, land: George on, 258; Walras land, 332; his suggestions for world peace, cited on agricultural, 286; would be 327; advocates hierarchical social order, simplified if improvements were exempted, 333; advocates moral and spiritual 358; in nineteen American cities, 318-19; in regeneration as only means of alleviating Australia, 258, 318, 358; in California social problems, 336; claims that stable Irrigation Districts, 319; in Canada, 319; in well-being is only to be found in heaven, Denmark, 319; in Hawaii, 322; in Hungary, 337; his critique evaluated, 17, 326-38 319; in Jamaica, 322; in Kiao-chau, 322; in passim New Zealand, 258:1 318; in three Pennsyl- American Economic Association, 15, 178, 183, vania cities (Pittsburgh, Scranton, and 261, 303 Harrisburg), 322; in South Africa, 319, American Social Science Association,. Saratoga 358; in Taiwan, 358; impracticable, Conferences of: (1886) 187; (1890) 269, according to Alcázar, 330, Atkinson, 257, 273-74 Ely, 318, 320, Knight, 357, Rothbard, 357, 399 400 INDEX Seligman, 285, and Walker, 320 Black Death, the: its effect upon wages and Atkinson, Edward: biographical data, 254; his rents, 84 appreciative remarks on George, 37n5; his Bdhm-Bawerk, Eugen von: George's failure to critique of George, 254-60; claims single tax understand, mentioned by Schumpeter, l6n would be insufficient, 254-55; claims prob- Bolivia: George's system unlikely to be applied lems of separate land assessment insuper- successfully in, 331 able, 257; claims land-value tax would be Bramwell, George W. Wilshere, Lord: attacks shifted, 255; claims land-value tax Progress and Poverty in pamphlet review, regressive, 258-59; confuses land-value tax 18; his attack answered by Hirsch, 17 with land tax, 257; admits mistake about Brazil, latifundia of, 343 single tax in France, 259; his critique ans- Britain: its era of hegemony marked by free wered by George, 17; his critique answered trade, 286 by Hirsch, 17; his critique evaluated, 255-59 British depression of mid-1970s, 202 passim Brokerage commission: George proposes Augusta, Ga.: Somers system used in, 318 leaving a percentage of rent to landowners Australia: land assessment in, 258, 318, 358; as, 36-37, 63, 70n25, 249, 258, 357, 359, land-value taxation in, 30, 346, 347, 351, 385-86 358; Hyndman on rent and wages in, 215; Brown, Harry G.: quoted on legitimacy of Marx on land and wages in, 211, 215 interest, 244; quoted by Geiger against Austrian school of economics: George's failure Ely's conflation of land and capital, 323; to appreciate, 386 cited for able argument contrary to that of Aveling, Edward, 389 Knight, 365; does not accept George's "all- devouring rent thesis," 381; quoted on Back, Kenneth: denies that land values cannot monopolistic element in landownership, be separated from improvement values, 18 383; a professed Malthusian, 385, 392n15; Baldwin Park, Calif.: cited to document quoted on emergency revenues, 388; quoted nonregressive nature of land-value taxation, as recommending compensation in 259 hardship cases to landowners, 389 Balfour, Arthur J.: attacks George's Brown, J. Bruce: quoted on assessment of land reasoning, in Industrial Remuneration value only, 258 Conference paper, 20 Butler, Nicholas Murray: cited in appreciation Barber, Anthony: inflates British money of George, 26n4 supply, 202 Byington, Stephen: his correspondence with Barker, Charles Albro: censures Miller's Tucker, 248 Progress and Robbery, 21; quoted on Laveleye's letter to George, 47; cited on California Irrigation Districts: separation of death of political Georgism, 339 land values from improvement values in, Bastiat, Fre'deic: criticized by Dixwell on free 319 trade, 167 Callaghan, James: his "Social Contract" Beaumont, Tex.: Somers system used in, 318 policy, 203 Beedy, Mary E.: notes possible flaws in Canada: separation of land values from Harris's critique of George, 191 improvement values in, 319 Benefits theory of taxation: fundamental to --Western: exemption of improvements in, application of George's social thought, 387; 24, 285, 288 in Neo-Georgism, 388-89 Capital: defined by Hirshleifer, 296, Bellamy, Edward: first in U.S. to argue that Davenport, 295-98, in many ways by division of labor imposes a social mortgage George, 227, 375; as stored-up labor, on production, 279 120-21; cannot by itself exploit labor, Bernard, George: defends George against 50-51; George sees no inherent conflict Kitson's charge of inconsistency, 22 between it and labor, 31; characterized by Beverly Hills, Calif.: cited to document Geiger as partly a social product, 29002; nonregressive nature of land-value taxation, distinguished from capital goods by Clark, 259 267; its employment by labor disputed by Index 401 Dixwell, 173; not an active factor of discusses first-occupancy theory of production according to Hanson and ownership, 307-9; accepts social-utility Ingalls, 241; conflated with land by Ely, theory of ownership, 305, 308, 309; 322-23, Huxley, 144, and Gronlund, 204-5; distinguishes between land and capital, distinguished from land by Carver, 308-9, 308-9, 323; criticizes in advance Ely's 310, 323; George's views on, attacked by argument conflating land and capital, 323; anarchists, 240-44, criticized by subsumes land-values under "findings", Rutherford, 226-28; George's distinction 305; outlines advantages of land-value between land and, attacked by Huxley, taxation, 310-11; advances novel argument 98-99, 101; Geiger cites Davenport as major for land-value taxation, 310; endorses land- critic of George's theory of, 293; its value taxation on grounds of social utility, exploitative role as seen by Laveleye, 49; 388; recommends inheritance, income, and the return to, growing much faster than sales taxes, but gives land-value taxes first land rent, according to Gronlund, 198; its priority, 310-I1; listed among writers on ownership gives more concentrated wealth wages-fund theory, 159; his critique and power than does landownership, evaluated, 306-9 passim, evaluation according to Oser, 377; the monopoly of, summarized, 311 based on land monopoly according to Catholic, Roman. See Roman Catholic Marx, 211 Catholic University: theologians of, help Capitalism: Progress and Poverty its "last reverse McGlynn excommunication, 338 ditch" according to Marx, 196; George's Cathrein, Fr. Victor: biographical data, 126; championship of, acclaimed by Nock, 367; his critique of George, 126-36; fails to its nature misconceived by George, perceive that agricultural sites do not yield according to Oser, 374-75, 376. Mandel the highest rent, 127; disputes George's quoted on landownership and, 220n47 and deduction from Ricardo's law of rent, n70; Marx's self-contradictory view of role 127-28; criticizes George's teaching on the of landownership in, 210; hindered by land decrease of wages and interest, 128; monopoly, according to Marx, 206, 210; misrepresents George's definition of labor, identified with monopoly by Tucker, 241; 133; criticizes labor theory of ownership, the main oppressor of labor, according to 129-34; accepts first-occupancy as the Ingalls, 237 original justification of ownership, 130-31, Capitalists: George upbraided by Crump for 135; criticizes George's argument against allegedly "preaching against," 19; Marx on first-occupancy theory of ownership, their active role in production, 198, 200, 130-31; his reasoning on landownership 210; not a closed class, according to Marx, echoed in Rerum Novarum of Leo XIII, 205 132; his complacent theological Carey, Henry C.: Harris an economic disciple justification of economic inequality, of, 187-88, 194, 195n30; his arguments 134-35; his critique evaluated, 127-35 against Ricardian rent theory refuted by passim Mill, Walker, and Marshall, 188 Chalmers, Thomas, 15, 109 Carver, Thomas Nixon: biographical data, Chautauqua Society, 313 303; his critique of George, 303-12; defines Cherbuliez, A.
Recommended publications
  • A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Honors Theses University Honors Program 5-2002 The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly Follow this and additional works at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/uhp_theses Recommended Citation Daly, Chris, "The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill" (2002). Honors Theses. Paper 131. This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the University Honors Program at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. r The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly May 8, 2002 r ABSTRACT The following study exanunes three works of John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion, and their subsequent effects on liberalism. Comparing the notion on individual freedom espoused in On Liberty to the notion of the social welfare in Utilitarianism, this analysis posits that it is impossible for a political philosophy to have two ultimate ends. Thus, Mill's liberalism is inherently flawed. As this philosophy was the foundation of Mill's progressive vision for humanity that he discusses in his Three Essays on Religion, this vision becomes paradoxical as well. Contending that the neo-liberalist global economic order is the contemporary parallel for Mill's religion of humanity, this work further demonstrates how these philosophical flaws have spread to infect the core of globalization in the 21 st century as well as their implications for future international relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S
    July 2012 Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S. Mill, and Sidgwick–– Daisuke Nakai∗ 1. Utilitarianism in the History of Economic Ideas Utilitarianism is a many-sided conception, in which we can discern various aspects: hedonistic, consequentialistic, aggregation or maximization-oriented, and so forth.1 While we see its impact in several academic fields, such as ethics, economics, and political philosophy, it is often dragged out as a problematic or negative idea. Aside from its essential and imperative nature, one reason might be in the fact that utilitarianism has been only vaguely understood, and has been given different roles, “on the one hand as a theory of personal morality, and on the other as a theory of public choice, or of the criteria applicable to public policy” (Sen and Williams 1982, 1-2). In this context, if we turn our eyes on economics, we can find intimate but subtle connections with utilitarian ideas. In 1938, Samuelson described the formulation of utility analysis in economic theory since Jevons, Menger, and Walras, and the controversies following upon it, as follows: First, there has been a steady tendency toward the removal of moral, utilitarian, welfare connotations from the concept. Secondly, there has been a progressive movement toward the rejection of hedonistic, introspective, psychological elements. These tendencies are evidenced by the names suggested to replace utility and satisfaction––ophélimité, desirability, wantability, etc. (Samuelson 1938) Thus, Samuelson felt the need of “squeezing out of the utility analysis its empirical implications”. In any case, it is somewhat unusual for economists to regard themselves as utilitarians, even if their theories are relying on utility analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Physiocrats Six Lectures on the French Économistes of the 18Th Century
    The Physiocrats Six Lectures on the French Économistes of the 18th Century Henry Higgs Batoche Books Kitchener 2001 First Edition: The Macmillan Company, 1897 This Edition: Batoche Books Limited 52 Eby Street South Kitchener, Ontario N2G 3L1 Canada email: [email protected] ISBN: 1-55273-064-6 Contents Preface ............................................................................................... 5 I: Rise of the School. .......................................................................... 6 II: The School and Its Doctrines. ..................................................... 17 III: The School and Its Doctrines (contd.) ....................................... 29 IV: Activities of the School. ............................................................. 43 V: Opponents of the School. ............................................................ 55 VI: Influence of the School. ............................................................. 66 Appendix .......................................................................................... 77 Authorities ....................................................................................... 80 Notes ................................................................................................ 82 Preface This little volume consists of lectures delivered before the London School of Economics in May and June of the present year. Impossible though it was found to give a truly adequate account of the Physiocrats in these six lectures, it has been thought that they may perhaps furnish
    [Show full text]
  • James Mill As Economist: Theory Dominated by Deductive Metho D
    School of Management & Languages Heriot-Watt University Edinburgh, EH14 4AS Tel: +44(0)131 451 3542 Fax: +44 (0)131 451 3079 Mail: [email protected] Web: www.sml.hw.ac.uk School of Management and Languages James Mill as Economist: Theory Dominated by Deductive Metho d Thomas Torrance Discussion Paper Series in Economics ISSN 1741-8240 DP2004-E06 Aug-05 JAMES MILL AS ECONOMIST: THEORY DOMINATED BY DEDUCTIVE METHOD1 Thomas S Torrance, Economics Department, School of Management and Languages, Heriot-Watt University, Edinburgh EH14 4AS June 2005 Introduction James Mill1 was born on the 6th April 1773 in North Water Bridge, a village on what is now the A94 trunk road and which is situated half way between the Angus town of Brechin to the south and the Kincardine town of Laurencekirk five miles to the north (the Royal Mail treats the latter as the postal town address of the village). North Water Bridge is also approximately six miles northwest of the Angus coastal town of Montrose. His father, also James, though born with the family name of Milne, was a shoemaker and small businessman. Both James senior and his wife Isabel Fenton believed in education as an effective means of self improvement and strongly supported the young James in his early studies, first at the local village school and then at Montrose Academy. In 1790, with the support of Sir John and Lady Jane Stuart, who were friends of the Mill family, Mill was encouraged to continue his education at the University of Edinburgh. Sir John was a Baron of the Exchequer in Scotland and owned an estate at the nearby village of Fettercairn, and from this period onwards he saw himself as 1 Early versions of this paper have been presented at the Scottish Economic Society Conference in Perth, March 2005, and at the European Society for the History of Economic Thought Conference, Stirling, June 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • Marx's Comments on James Mill's Book
    1844: Marx’s comments on James Mill's book MARX'S NOTEBOOK COMMENTS ON JAMES MILL, ÉLÉMENTS D'ÉCONOMIE POLITIQUE [From a translation of Mill's book, by J. T. Parisot, Paris, 1823] by KARL MARX Written in the first half of 1844 Full text of conspectus first published in Marx/Engels, Gesamtausgabe, Erste Abteilung, Band 3, Berlin, 1932. English translation Clemens Dutt for the Collected Works Transcribed for the Internet by [email protected] Marx kept a wide variety of notebooks throughout his life. He often used them to aid in his study of other authors. A common practice was to transcribe long sections from a particular book, and then comment on those sections at some length. During his time in Paris, Marx kept nine notebooks -- largely dedicated to his growing interest in economics. They date from the end of 1843 to January 1845. The "Paris Notebooks" deal with books by J. B. Say, Adam Smith, David Ricardo, McCulloch, James Mill, Destott de Tracy, Sismondi, Jeremy Bentham, Boisguillebert, Lauderdale, Schütz, List, Skarbek and Buret. Most of Marx’s accompanying commentary on these authors is very fragmentary; and, ideas are often restated far more clearly in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts (1844). The exception to this is the material addressing James Mill’s book, Elements of Political Economy (London, 1821). Marx used an 1823 French translation of the English author’s tome. The Mill part of the Paris Notebooks is quite lengthy -- it starts on page 25 of the fourth notebook and continues into the fifth. http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1844-mil/index.htm (1 of 22) [23/08/2000 18:56:15] 1844: Marx’s comments on James Mill's book Following a lengthy selection of Mill excerpts, Marx suddenly "veered off" and began developing a larger, tangential thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of J.S.Mill Revisited: Biographical and Political Explorations
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Business Papers and Journal Articles School of Business 2009 Review of J.S.Mill Revisited: Biographical and Political Explorations Mark Donoghue University of Notre Dame Australia, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/bus_article Part of the Business Commons This book review in a scholarly journal was originally published as: Donoghue, M. (2009). Review of J.S.Mill Revisited: Biographical and Political Explorations. History of Economics Review, (49), 93-98. This book review in a scholarly journal is posted on ResearchOnline@ND at https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/ bus_article/40. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Richard Reeves. John Stuart Mill: Victorian Firebrand. London: Atlantic Books. 2007. Pp. viii + 616. ISBN 978 1 84354 643 6. £30.00 Mark Donoghue* John Stuart Mill: Victorian Firebrand opens in St James Park, on a warm summer’s morning, with the teenage Mill striding to his office in Leadenhall Street in the financial heart of the City of London. Suddenly, Mill’s attention is caught by a small bundle abandoned beneath an oak tree. Curious, Mill kneels down beside it and unwraps the layers of soiled blankets only to discover a dead, newborn baby. This grisly experience remained etched in Mill’s mind for the duration of his life and was perhaps formative in shaping his views on the twin rights of life and liberty. Britain then stood poised in the vanguard of economic industrialisation and opportunity, yet the lot of the working classes often remained quite harsh.
    [Show full text]
  • A Turning Point in the Concept of Justice: from Adam Smith to John Stuart Mill Un Punto De Inflexión En El Concepto De Justicia: De Adam Smith a John Stuart Mill
    A turning point in the concept of justice: from Adam Smith to John Stuart Mill Un punto de inflexión en el concepto de Justicia: de Adam Smith a John Stuart Mill ESTRELLA TRINCADO AZNAR Universidad Complutense de Madrid [email protected] Abstract: Classical economists, John Stuart Mill included, based their theories on Adam Smith’s system. At some point, they labelled it as a "utilitarian" theory. However, Smith was non-utilitarian, perhaps even anti-utilitarian. One of the most amazing differences between classical economics versus Smithian theory consists of their concept of justice. Classical economics were based on a utilitarian concept; Smith criticizes the concept of utilitarian justice. Utility being a subjective picture, classical economists find it more difficult to draw limits to state intervention than Smith does. This paper compares Smith’s and John Stuart Mill’s concept of justice when they make the case for land tenure. Mill admits that society cannot properly be said to owe anything to the poor. However, not arguing from 'abstract rights,' but from 'utility' understood in its largest sense, Mill defended the nationalization of land. Mill was unable to draw any limits to state intervention. Conversely, Smith defended that justice is not a utilitarian concept. In this case, limits to state intervention are more easily drawn. Keywords: John Stuart Mill, Adam Smith, state intervention, land tenure, justice. Resumen: Los economistas clásicos, incluidos John Stuart Mill, basaron sus teorías en el sistema de Adam Smith. En algún momento, lo calificaron como una teoría utilitarista. Sin embargo, Smith no era utilitarista, tal vez incluso anti- utilitarista.
    [Show full text]
  • Mill, Liberty and the Facts of Life
    UC Berkeley Working Papers Title Mill, Liberty And The Facts Of Life Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/26n9r19s Authors Stimson, Shannon C. Milgate, Murray Publication Date 2001 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California MILL, LIBERTY AND THE FACTS OF LIFE Shannon C. Stimson University of California, Berkeley and Murray Milgate Queens’ College, Cambridge Working Paper 2001-2 Working Papers published by the Institute of Governmental Studies provide quick dissemination of draft reports and papers, preliminary analysis, and papers with a limited audience. The objective is to assist authors in refining their ideas by circulating results and to stimulate discussion about public policy. Working Papers are reproduced unedited directly from the author’s page. MILL, LIBERTY AND THE FACTS OF LIFE Shannon C. Stimson University of California, Berkeley and Murray Milgate Queens’ College, Cambridge Working Paper 2001-2 Abstract: This paper examines John Stuart Mill's discussion of economic liberty and individual liberty, and his view of the relationship between the two. It explores how, and how effectively, Mill developed his arguments about the two liberties; reveals the lineages of thought from which they derived; and considers how his arguments were altered by political economists not long after his death. It is argued that the distinction Mill drew between the two liberties provided him with a framework of concepts which legitimised significant government intervention in economic matters without restricting individual liberty. Acknowledgements: The authors would like to thank, without in any way implicating, the following individuals for their helpful criticisms and suggestions on earlier drafts of this essay: Robert Adcock, Mark Bevir, Colin Bird, Alan Houston, Michael Rogin, Ian Shapiro.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Economics 446-01 History of Economic Thought Spring 2019
    Economics 446-01 History of Economic Thought Spring 2019, Tuesday and Thursday 12:30-1:50PM, Blow 333 Professor Clyde Haulman Office: Tyler 430 Tele: 1-2365 email: [email protected] Office Hours: TTh 11:00-12:20 and by appointment COURSE OBJECTIVES “...the ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they are right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is commonly understood.” In reality, even practical people “... are usually the slaves of some defunct economists.” With these words, John Maynard Keynes provides a rational for this course. Economic ideas have indeed played a critical role in shaping the world we know and they have day to day impacts on the lives of people everywhere. Understanding the origins of these ideas and how they have developed and transformed into the foundations of the current state of economic analysis is the purpose of this course. Studying the primary works of the some of the ‘giants’ of economics (as well as the works of some lesser giants), we will consider how economic ideas, analysis, and method have both changed and remained the same over time. We will focus on four major ‘schools’ of economic thought -- Classical, Marxian, Neo-Classical, and Keynesian. Classical political economy emerged in the late eighteenth century as an important component of Enlightenment thinking. In part, it developed in response to government intervention in the economy, and its proponents provided theories and policies for the emerging market revolution. The Classical school is represented by the work of Adam Smith, Thomas Malthus, David Ricardo and John Stuart Mill.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neo-Capitalist Assault — the Historical Background in the XVIII
    The Jus Semper Global Alliance Living Wages North and South The Neo-Capitalist Assault Essay Two of Part I (The Economics of Reference) April 2001 GLOBAL ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT – A TLWNSI ISSUE ESSAY SERIES The Historical Summary The Liberal Paradigm in Formation Background in the XVIII and the Idea of the Common Good. and XIX Centuries The initiation of liberalism The Pursuit of Individual Self-Interest By Alvaro J. de Regil a as the Best Way to Bring Prosperity to All Levels of Society Adam Smith and the Pursuit of the From time to time TJSGA will issue essays on Common Good topics relevant to The Living Wages North and South Initiative (TLWNSI). This paper is the The Classical School and the Principle second in the series “The Neo-Capitalist Assault” of the Common Good –a collection in development about Neoliberalism by its Executive Director. A Refreshment of Mercantilism In a narrative and analytic style, the essay John Stuart Mill, Social Justice, and describes the historical roots of modern economic His Social Liberalism thought with European Liberalism and its laissez faire ideology as a reaction to the era of Classic Economic Theory, Applied monopolistic Mercantilism. The objective in the essay is to describe the development of liberal The Struggle for Social Justice Begins economic thought and establish the great differences between its philosophical postulates A Parallel in Views. A Gap Between and its actual application. While a true spirit of Theory and Practice freedom and the pursuit of the common good imbued economic liberalism, the actual application of the Industrial Revolution was of paedists, “The Physiocrats”, who liked to regard laissez faire for the owners of money and of dire themselves as “The Economists”, were the first to exploitation for labour.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism: Classical, Reformist and Neo-Liberalism1 “Liberalism Is a Belief That Society Can Safely Be Founded on ... Self-Di
    Liberalism: Classical, Reformist and Neo-Liberalism1 “Liberalism is a belief that society can safely be founded on ... self-directing power of personality, that it is only on this foundation that a true community can be built, and that so established its foundations are so deep and so wide that there is no limit that we can place to the extent of the building.” – Hobhouse “[Liberalism is] an idea committed to freedom as a method and policy in government, as an organising principle in society, and a way of life for the individual and community.” – Encyclopaedia Britannica “Liberalism is a tentative attitude towards social problems which stresses the role of reason and human ingenuity.... Liberalism looks ahead with flexible approach; seeking to make future better for more people, as conservatism looks back aiming mainly to preserve the attainment of past.” – Grimes The elements of liberalism as a way of life and an outlook can be traced back to the classical Greece and Rome. The ideas of the Sophists, Protagoras and Gorgias, Democritus the atomist and Pericles in the ancient Greece and Solon, Cicero, Justinian, Constantine, Livy and Tacitus of the Roman age contain a multitude of liberal elements. Even the Christianity in its early stage also contained some liberal-individualistic elements. However, as a political current and an intellectual tradition, an identifiable strand in thought and practice, liberalism is no older than the 17 th century. Earlier the term ‘liberal’ used to denote the classical virtue of humanity, generosity and open-mindedness. During the Scottish Enlightenment the term was considered as a derivative of ‘liberality’.
    [Show full text]
  • Land Reform and Popular Political Economy in Victorian Britain
    Donald Winch Land Reform and Popular Political Economy in Victorian Britain Paper for a conference on ‘Worlds of Political Economy’ held at Churchill College, Cambridge, 6-7 September, 2002 I ‘In my lectures upon Political Economy about the country, I have found in almost every centre a certain little knot of men of the lower-middle or upper-working class, men of grit and character, largely self-educated, keen citizens, mostly nonconformists in religion, to whom Land Nationalisation, taxation of unearned increment, or other radical reforms of land tenure, are doctrines resting upon a plain moral sanction. These free-trading Radical dissenters regard common ownership and equal access to the land as a “natural right”, essential to individual freedom.’ J. A. Hobson’s description of the opinions of the kind of men he encountered in his university extension classes in the English provinces in the 1880s and 90s accords with everything we know about the revival of the movement for land reform during this period. For this was when Henry George’s Progress and Poverty (1879) was selling 100,000 copies, when George was addressing large audiences, and when Land Restoration Leagues, based on his ‘single tax’ proposals, were being formed throughout Britain. In 1897 Hobson thought that George had ‘exercised a more directly powerful formative and educative influence over English radicalism of the last fifteen years than any other man’.1 He acknowledged that George, through personal magnetism and with the aid of a drastically over-simplified economic message, was tapping into a ‘real, deep-grounded passion or conviction’, a ‘genuine need or aspiration’.
    [Show full text]