CAC0010.1177/0010836717719735Cooperation and ConflictGuzzini research-article7197352017

Rejoinder article

Cooperation and Conflict 2017, Vol. 52(3) 423­–445 Militarizing politics, © The Author(s) 2017 Reprints and permissions: essentializing identities: sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav https://doi.org/10.1177/0010836717719735DOI: 10.1177/0010836717719735 Interpretivist process tracing journals.sagepub.com/home/cac and the power of

Stefano Guzzini

Abstract This reply to the Symposium on Stefano Guzzini (ed.) The return of geopolitics in Europe?, answers the criticisms by John Agnew, Jeffrey Checkel, Dan Deudney and Jennifer Mitzen. It justifies (1) its specific definition and critique of geopolitics as a theory – and not just a foreign policy strategy; (2) its proposed interpretivist process tracing; (3) the role of mechanisms in constructivist theorizing and foreign policy theory; and (4) its usage of non-Humean causality in the analysis of multiple parallel processes and their interaction. At the same time, it develops the logic of the book’s main mechanism of foreign policy identity crisis reduction.

Keywords Causality, constructivism, foreign policy analysis, geopolitics, identity, social/causal mechanisms

The return of geopolitics in Europe? (Guzzini, 2012c) engages a series of research agen- das: the analysis of European security in the 1990s, the content and role of geopolitical theory, the usage of social mechanisms and process tracing in interpretivism and the theo- rization of micro-dynamics in constructivist theories of (IR). It did not start that way (Guzzini, 2003). The more the research advanced, the more these differ- ent agendas connected. To a considerable extent, this is due to the discussion within the research group. Although the six framework and theory chapters addressed in this Forum were written by myself, they have been informed by an ongoing conversation. Far from simply providing case studies on different countries, the other authors in the book are all theorists in their own right with quite diverse sensitivities (Astrov and Morozova, 2012; Behnke, 2012; Bilgin, 2012; Brighi and Petito, 2012; Drulák, 2012; Kuus, 2012). Their empirical analyses were no mere application, but spurred reflections that fed back into the

Corresponding author: Stefano Guzzini, Danish Institute for International Studies, Østbanegade 117, 2100 Copenhagen Ø, Denmark. Email: [email protected] 424 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3) general framework; inversely, the discussion around the framework also affected the dif- ferent paths of their own research (see e.g. Behnke, 2013; Bilgin, 2017; Kuus, 2014). The present Forum bears witness to the book’s approach to thinking empirics, meth- odology and theory at the same time. John Agnew (in Agnew et al., 2017), although generally sympathetic, sees crucial factors missing. Daniel Deudney (in Agnew et al., 2017) takes me to task over the very understanding and tradition of geopolitics. Jeffrey Checkel (in Agnew et al., 2017) assesses the methodological proposal of interpretivist process tracing with the teaser of excessive inductivism. Jennifer Mitzen (in Agnew et al., 2017) would have preferred more theoretical engagement with anxiety, identity and security in constructivism before making the methodological jumps. My reply roughly follows the logic of the book. I will start with Deudney, who got lost, perhaps not ‘on Earth’, but somewhere in Chapter 2. Since he alone misunderstands the research design and choices of the book, most of his remarks are unfortunately irrel- evant. Yet, they allow me to situate the logic of the book before addressing Agnew’s, Checkel’s and Mitzen’s incisive comments on theory and methodology.

Which geopolitics? Deudney (in Agnew et al., 2017: 10) claims that the omissions, absences and silences profoundly shape ‘in negative ways the insights this book advances about the nature of foreign policy crises, the role of “geopolitical” claims in the politics of this crisis’. In one stroke, he reduces foreign policy identity crises to simple foreign policy crises and, hence, eliminates the major focus of the book. As he sees it, I omit the pedigree of con- temporary geopolitical thought – from Colin Gray’s strategic culture to his own work – that shows how geopolitical and liberal, democratic and republican thought can be combined. I do not deal with the central role of technology in geopolitical thought, nei- ther at its height (Mackinder) nor in its role at the end of the Cold War with the nuclear fear heightened by Chernobyl. Finally, all turns towards Russia again, when I miss how justified Russia’s foreign policy (now suddenly) ‘identity crisis’ is in the wake of the gentlemen’s agreement undermined by a cheating West.1 Instead, I concentrate on Ratzel, the pre-Nazi soil and land (Lebensraum) theorist. The critique follows an established scheme. People criticize geopolitics, either because they do not know it, or because they have put on ideological blinders. Geopolitics is the victimized pet enemy of the righteous but ignorant liberal idealist. If only Deudney had read the chapter carefully, not to speak of the other chapters that establish the puzzle and framework of analysis, he would have noticed that the purpose of this chapter had to be entirely different than assessing a geopolitical explanation of the end of the Cold War or the crisis in Ukraine. He may have been intrigued by me making a controversial defence of Ratzel from easy charges of proto-fascist expansionism, and noticed that I do not omit but actually use Gray’s strategic culture, yet as a way to show the difference with the proposed framework (Guzzini, 2012a: 51–52). This said, his neglect of the main purpose of the study and even of the argument of the chapter in case makes it necessary for me to clarify the issue. The first chapter (Guzzini, 2012f) establishes the background to the puzzle and sets the stage for the definition in Chapter 2. To (geopolitical) realists, the revival of Guzzini 425 geopolitical thought in Europe was not unexpected, since the end of the Cold War was accompanied by the Balkan wars - an argument along Mearsheimer’s ‘Back to the Future’ (1990). To political geographers, the revival was also foreseeable. If ‘geopolitical lan- guage can be recognized by the occurrence of words referring to boundaries and the conflict between territorially bounded interests’ (Dijkink, 1996: 5), then the territorial reshuffling at the end of the Cold War had to increase geopolitical talk in Europe almost by definition. In my view, the realist line begs the question, whereas the political geog- raphers help to identify the puzzle more clearly. There are, in fact, two realist arguments. One is to say that ideas only reflect the sur- rounding political and material conditions. Since the end of the Cold War was accompa- nied by local territorial wars in Europe, geopolitical theories would become prominent (again) compared to the relatively stable Cold War (in Europe). Such an argument begs the question, though. The end of the Cold War was an epochal and unexpected change in the global security order. It is hardly self-evident to consider the end of global bipolarity, in whose name massive wars had been fought, of lesser material importance for the devel- opment of ideas than a civil war confined to some parts of the Balkans. A second realist argument implies that any conflict is a point for realism, applied here: any territorial con- flict is a point for geopolitics. Witness Deudney’s discussion about the territorial conflict/ geopolitics in East Ukraine. Yet, this move ‘conflates description and explanation’ (Wendt, 1995: 76), political strategy and theory, the level of action and the level of observation. Diplomatic solutions are no point for liberal theories, and conflicts themselves prove nothing; all theories have and need explanations for both. Again, it begs the question. Political geographers have been more to the point. Yet, if geographic imagination expectedly revives in moments of territorial change, it is not clear why some countries that got new borders (unified Germany and the Czech Republic) saw no or only an ephemeral revival of geopolitics (for the German case, see also Sur, 1995). Similarly, why would such revival take the form of ‘neoclassical geopolitics’ (Bassin, 2004: 621) with explicit references back to classical geopolitics and its explanatory primacy given to human and physical geographic factors? This then is the puzzle of the book: why would the revival of the most materialist and determinist line of theories occur in times of a new peace that nobody had anticipated? Hence, the book is not about how geopolitical thought explains the end of the Cold War and its aftermath, but, in reverse, how the latter could revive geopolitical thought. In fact, what seems to have eluded Deudney’s reading is that geopolitical thought is not used primarily for the explanation of events, but as an empirical object of analysis. Ideas are real; they can be studied. Here, identifying the object in ‘neoclassical geopolitics’ with its strong determinacy, and not some watered-down ‘geography matters’, is doubly important: it is least expected in times of peaceful change, and it alone can be expected to have (self-fulfilling) performative effects where our way of seeing and conceiving the world not only passively registers, but also interacts with the social world. But then, why defend Ratzel? This controversial move responds to the usual line of defence by geopolitical writers: being victims of guilt by association. If only, so the story goes, one would cut off the German branch, neither necessary nor typical, the geopoliti- cal tradition would appear less tainted, its discussion more even-handed. Ratzel stands for the quintessential difference: seeing the state as a (growing) organism (1896a, 1896b). 426 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

Without that biological analogy and the Social Darwinism it may inspire, geopolitics can have a respectable place in the history of ideas. This critique may be partially correct for Haushofer (1924, 1934), despite his conflict with the Nazi focus on race instead of space and the eventual strategy of attacking Russia, which Haushofer opposed (Bassin, 1987). However, for Ratzel, allegedly the main cul- prit, it applies much less. He warns about taking racial distinctions seriously, which are but ‘deceptive garments’ (täuschende Gewänder), misleading the ‘superficial observer’ (Ratzel, 1882: 469). For him, humankind is fundamentally unitary in its anthropology – as well as in its destiny, which would see the increasing fusion of peoples into a common mankind (Ratzel, 1882: 177). Just as much as his education in zoology made him think about biology, it made him wary of it (Hunter, 1986). Indeed, at some point he openly cautioned against the use of a biological analogy (Ratzel, 1897: 12–13). Inversely, the loose usage of organicism and of Social Darwinism (‘survival of the fittest’) does not distinguish the German from other classical geopolitical positions (Jean, 1995: 17–19). Organicism can be witnessed even in Mackinder’s famous speech (Mackinder, 1904: 422). Social Darwinism had two important non-German inspira- tions. On the one hand, it reached the Anglo-American world through the organicism of Herbert Spencer, who coined the term ‘survival of the fittest’, and whose volumes sold a staggering 368,755 copies between 1860 and 1903 in the USA (Hofstadter, 1944: 34). On the other hand, it is fundamental in the idea of laissez-faire economics, that is, a libertarian-conservative vision of progress, where the system itself, in its ‘natural’ selection most effective when left alone, would ensure that those unfit eventually be left out or perish, in capitalism’s ‘perennial gale of creative destruction’, as Schumpeter (1975 [1942]: 84) later put it. This derivation from liberal economics explains why E.H. Carr (1946: 46–50), one of the few early IR writers to critically engage Social Darwinism, places it oddly (or wryly) within the utopian, not the realist tradition (for a critical assessment of classical liberalism’s relationship to imperialism and scientific racism, see Hall and Hobson, 2010). Therefore, Chapter 2 turns around and defines the classical geopolitical tradition by central core attributes alone. I develop four (Guzzini, 2012e: 27–28). Firstly, geopolitics stresses the interconnectedness of the world that produces a ‘Ganzheit’ (totality), that, for one present-day geopolitical writer, presents ‘the ultimate object and justification’ of geopolitical theory today (Parker, 1985: 2). Here, the organism metaphor functions as a proxy for the holism of classical geopolitics, but it can have other functional equivalents, as in system theory (besides Parker, see e.g. Cohen, 1991, 2003). Secondly, it insists on the finiteness of the world in which no conflict can be exported, no easy compensations achieved. Thirdly, it mobilizes neo-Malthusianism that provides the pessimistic determi- nacy: in a finite world with limited resources, seeking expansionism is the default posi- tion of any state, and its realization is necessary whenever an opportunity arises. This is, finally, connected to the Social Darwinism of an existential struggle for national/cultural or racial primacy. Even granted that the classical geopolitical tradition is connected to Social Darwinism, is it fair to charge the neoclassical turn with classical environmental determinism, here understood as the explanatory primacy of geographic factors? It is not fair for those scholars, mainly in political geography, who analyse geography in its perceptions and Guzzini 427 institutional context (Lacoste, 1978) or, as done in critical geopolitics, focus on the poli- tics of geography rather than the other way round. It may be unfair for those who use it as a framework of analysis, a ‘geopolitical method’ that refuses determinacy, although not when this slides into a ‘geostrategy’ to predict/the conditions of border disputes (see the slide in the conclusion of Foucher, 1988). Such slides are my main justification. They are systematic. For, in their purpose of offering persuasive arguments and practical advice, geopolitical arguments confront a dilemma (Guzzini, 2012e: 36–41). If geopolitics merely means that we need to take physical and human geographic factors seriously, we all agree. This is neither distinct nor determinate: it cannot show how much geography matters, let alone how much it matters ‘in itself’, as geopolitical theory has it. If, then, it wishes to justify its distinctiveness, and legitimates recourse to its theory, it systematically glides into treating geography as the primary determinant – yet not providing a theoretical justification for it, since it rejects the charge of ‘environmental determinism’. In other words, geopolitical theory is either indistinct, indeterminate and correct but trivial, or distinct and determinate but wrong. This irresolvable dilemma explains what Carlo Jean (1995: 8, 20), a geopolitical thinker himself, calls the unavoidable geopolitical temptation of scientism and determinism (which he indeed does not avoid himself, as I show in the book). It is important to understand this dilemma to appreciate what distinguishes realism from geopolitical theory (Guzzini, 2012e: 28–35). Whereas geopolitical theory is part of the realist family, not all realists do geopolitical theory.2 There is a more diplomatic understanding of realism. Such understanding can be informed by the indeterminacy of rational human behaviour (Aron, 1962), a sense of practical prudence against the self- fulfilling character of the worst case (Wolfers, 1962) and self-restraint ‘to deal with the most fundamental problem of politics, which is not the control of wickedness but the limitation of righteousness’ (Kissinger, 1954: 1029). The overlap occurs when realists argue instead in terms of worst-case scenarios, most famously exemplified by the US Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld’s (2002) plea to defend against the ‘unknown unknowns’, which, incidentally, is the one thing we apparently do know (and, hence, uncertainty is rationally domesticated into ultimate risk). Here, a fundamental determi- nacy creeps in, which mobilizes a ‘strategic’ version of realism, what I call ‘realism’s military gaze’. For the effect of invoking geopolitical terminology is a militarization of politics. It reverses Clausewitz’s famous dictum. Rather than making war the prolongation of poli- tics with other means, it makes politics the mere prolongation of war with other means. Such a pernicious reversal was a constant risk during the Cold War (Aron, 1976); a revival of geopolitics would return to it. It also has a second effect, namely the homog- enization and essentialization of geographies, including collective identities, spatially and culturally defined. Talk is not cheap. For these reasons, the empirical object of analysis, neoclassical geopolitics, is defined as…

…a policy-oriented analysis, generally conservative and with nationalist overtones, that gives explanatory primacy, but not exclusivity, to certain physical and human geographic factors (whether the analyst is open about this or not), and gives precedence to a strategic view, realism 428 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

with a military and nationalist gaze, for analysing the ‘objective necessities’ within which states compete for power and rank. (Guzzini, 2012e: 43)

The question was then to find out whether and why it was revived in several European countries in the 1990s and hypothesize some of its effects. The case studies of ‘smaller European languages’ (Deudney), which found a revival in four out six countries, ana- lysed geopolitical thought in terms of this narrower definition. If referred to in this revival, Deudney, Gray or Huntington would be part of the analysis.

The framework of analysis Agnew and Mitzen bring a series of qualifications to the framework of analysis. Although both may sometimes push me from a vantage point that could have been another book, I think they are generally justified in doing so for the sake of the wider intellectual discus- sion to which this book belongs. Let me start with a short summary before locating their criticisms. The book’s general framework of analysis is inspired by constructivist foreign policy analysis. This pertains to at least three ideas. Firstly, social action and interaction is signifi- cantly, but not exclusively, constituted by social practices of recognition (Guzzini, 2012d: 265–266).3 Secondly, security imaginaries (Weldes, 1999) and their embedded identity dis- courses are a privileged place for understanding foreign policy traditions and strategic options (see also Mälksoo, 2012b). Such understandings are the condition of possibility for behaviour, but do not directly determine behaviour (Hopf, 2002: Chapter 1). Thirdly, the social world is characterized by reflexivity, something that Hacking (1999) calls ‘looping’ or ‘interaction’ effects, and that are crucial for understanding self-fulfilling effects. The central unit of analysis of the book is Jutta Weldes’s (1999) security imaginary (for more details of the following, see Guzzini, 2012a: 52–55). It is conceptualized in the book as a country’s foreign policy tradition, a repository that carries lessons of history, repertoires and scripts (or plots) out of which representations of the self (biographies) and of the world of IR are created. The security imaginary circumscribes a specific social field, in which social reality (always combining matter and ideas) interacts with our understandings. Social reality does not come with a single meaning-tag attached; discur- sive formations evolve through social practices enabled or constrained by social reality. A security imaginary is not homogeneous. A foreign policy tradition is not about a single shared opinion. It is a system of references that frames and authorizes certain posi- tions as legitimate parts of the debate. The security imaginary shares a common sense that provides the understandings upon which foreign policy experts can then disagree. This is part of ‘the concession to a social universe that one makes by accepting to become acceptable’ (Bourdieu, 2001: 114). A security imaginary includes multiple identity discourses. Those identity discourses usually include perceptions on how others perceive the self. It is no stable state, but itself the snapshot in an ongoing process of identification with an ever-precarious fixing (Campbell, 1992: 11 and passim). The prevalence of one particular identity plot in the discursive formation and the potential continuity of the latter are the result of dynamic processes, not of stasis. Guzzini 429

Since such identity discourses are in a constant re-articulation, a crisis is not to be understood as just any externally induced change of a discourse ‘at rest’. A crisis refers to those moments in which debates cannot update or combine repertoires to fix tensions, either internally or externally induced, or, when doing so, end up questioning the imagi- nary’s tacit assumptions, its common sense. In the historical context of the study, that is, the end of the Cold War and its immediate aftermath, the book focuses on the expectation of such crises to be happening when repertoires have to be mobilized for creating a new, or responding to a newly questioned or newly acquired, self-understanding or external role recognition in world affairs. The country studies in the volume reflect these cases. All six countries were prompted to rethink their role in international affairs, partly because they were countries in new borders, or indeed new countries, or because their international role was so closely tied to the Cold War dynamics that its absence produced a conceptual vacuum. Hence, we had countries where political geographers would expect the emergence of a geopolitical debate and potentially the revival of geopolitical thought. Yet, in two of those countries, namely the unifying Germany and the now split Czech Republic, no revival happened. Finally, identity crises do not automatically trigger a new understanding that privi- leges a recourse to geopolitical thought. Even if geopolitical thought can be alluring for fixing identity, it does not necessarily happen (it is functional, but not necessary). For this to happen, the book discusses a series of ideational, institutional and rhetorical factors that could facilitate that effect, such as the ideational path dependence of a materialist political culture in a country, the political economy of expertise production, including the importance of military elites or the lacking financial or status independence of academia and media, and the role of nationalism in political debates. Agnew’s critique sets in here. He appreciates the definition of neoclassical geopolitics to be open enough to account for the more geocultural than strictly territorial versions prevalent for some decades. He supports the focus on identity discourses, and that under- standing their crises is embedded in a wider analysis. Yet, he sees some factors and some effects of a geopolitical revival missing. For one, he thinks that a country’s previous historical standing in the world is an important factor for understanding the revival. Secondly, he would see these crises as driven by not only the end of the Cold War, but also by certain effects of globalization more generally. Finally, he thinks that neoclassical geopolitics not only depoliticizes by remilitarizing public debate as in the reversal of Clausewitz, but also by systematically projecting ‘the causes of our discontent beyond state borders. … Action from over the horizon dictates our fate. Foreigners are to blame’ (in Agnew et al., 2017: 8).4 The first two critiques are informed by Agnew’s (2003) well-argued reference to larger historical developments for understanding the role and effect of geopolitical thought, including the history of national rank in the world political hierarchy. This fac- tor, which he sees as salient for the Russian case, is one that the book discusses in terms of ‘the ideology of great or dissatisfied power’ (Guzzini, 2012a: 61–64). Rather than being a separate factor, we included it within the security imaginary itself, where it would be part of identity discourses. A second deep point of his has to do with process. If the book is right in its insistence on imaginaries as processes, then any historical starting date for the analysis will always 430 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3) have something arbitrary. Historical processes that led to the revival did not start in 1989 (or 1991 for Russia). This point is very consequential, since it is not just that structural factors of the global political economy were neglected in the analysis, although they are, but that by opening up to these macro-processes, the setup in terms of a process from A to B is to be rethought. I agree with the thrust of the critique and will take this up when the process analysis is introduced in the last section and in the conclusion. A third and crucial point raised by Agnew is the role of nationalism in constituting geopolitical thought and in triggering its revival. The nation is a victim to be defended against all ills, which originate elsewhere (even if that ‘elsewhere’ ends up being ‘here’; see, for instance, Combes, 2017). A prominent role of nationalism does not contradict the book’s theoretical setup, since state identity discourses are by definition tied to ideas of the nation (see also Berenskoetter, 2014). The book explicitly dealt with the role of nationalism when it qualified the definition of neoclassical geopolitics for not being necessarily tied to conservative circles and thought – just as Social Darwinism could be found across the political spectrum, including with liberals and socialists (Hawkins, 1997). Indeed, geopolitics appears as the foreign policy ideology of nationalism. Yet, Agnew is surely right that this connection to nationalism could have warranted more thought, because it is theoretically tricky and because it could provide a better grip for understanding the distinctive content of individual geopolitical traditions (as critically noted by Klinke, 2013; Sidaway, 2014). Mitzen’s critique probes deeply into the causal logic of the framework of analysis. She argues that ontological insecurity is a cause that can have multiple effects (multi- finality). Concretely, there are also creative agency-empowering ways in which such insecurity may be resolved. In addition, the other way round, there are resolutions to ontological anxiety that have a similar agency-narrowing effect, but are not connected to geopolitical thought (equifinality). By reducing the outcome to a binary (rise or not of geopolitics), the framework impoverishes the theoretical understanding of anxiety and its resolution. This critique is informed by her own research agenda on ontological secu- rity (Mitzen, 2006), to which I also refer in the book. I will start by showing that there is more flexibility to my process tracing than she acknowledges, before using her pointers to open the more fundamental issues on identity theory and causality. There are different ways to conceptualize identity. In the book, identity is a discursive phenomenon; that is, it is not analysed in terms of scaling up from individual to collec- tive identity (with all the problems entailed). Rather, the identity of a country exists through its recognition by other actors in a diplomatic and public discourse that attributes often anthropomorphic expectations to collective actors for making sense of their behav- iour. Identity is constituted in this ongoing communication and recognition. It is in the practices of actors, and it exists only as long as it is enacted through these practices. Jutta Weldes (1999: 215–231) shows how this works, for instance, when she discusses how identity discourses and credibility were connected in the US decision-making dur- ing the Cuban Missile Crisis. Or, to use a recent statement in an interview with , ‘credibility for a state plays the role of character for a human being’ (interview in Goldberg, 2016; for a similar take by a Brazilian scholar-diplomat, see Lafer, 2004). Hence, ‘identity’ refers to those attributions of personality in discourses among political actors, their observers (media and academia) or the public at large within which the Guzzini 431 subject-position of the country in world politics is negotiated. This negotiation takes place in domestic and external fields of recognition (identity as self-understanding and external role recognition, respectively). Based on social theories of recognition, it is assumed that countries generally seek to achieve a consistent subject-position (even if that is one of an unpredictable actor) such as to allow for a credible self-understanding and external role.5 For the argument of the book, an identity crisis is not understood as just any distur- bance of a foreign policy tradition, but only those for which the existing repertoires and plots find no solution. This is tricky, of course. On the one hand, any tradition is in poten- tial crisis and, hence, a resting self is always transitory. Moreover, as the analysis in the book shows for Russia and Turkey, and to some extent Italy, some foreign policy tradi- tions are in almost constant crisis, since alleged solutions taken from past repertoires unravel almost as soon as they take grip. Indeed, precisely for being an easy but indeter- minate fix, geopolitical thought only perpetuates those identity crises (Guzzini, 2012b: 233–236, 239–242). Yet, it is fair to say, and can be empirically shown, during some times more than others, the self-narratives in foreign policy discourses are unchallenged and/or are in harmony with the way internal or external publics (or fields of recognition) recognize them. This starting point of identity in discursive formations is hence related to, but different from ontological security theory (OST), as used by Mitzen. Concomitantly, the central issue of an identity crisis and its resolution – that is, the first social mechanism of the analysis, ‘foreign policy identity crisis reduction’ – is somewhat analogous, but not the same as the reaction to existential anxieties, even if such anxieties can also include issues of identity. A first difference is that dissonance reduction does not primarily respond to a human need as it does in OST, as in an emotional response to anxiety (see also Steele, 2007). Instead, it derives from the response to the conventional expectations of both domestic and international audiences for a coherent ‘credible’ identity to make sense of a state’s action. They are part of a social field that makes such attributions. Similarly, as in the Kissinger quote above, such reduction is deemed necessary in order to be able to project a coherent purpose of a country. As compared with OST, this is decidedly a more discur- sive take on identity (see e.g. Epstein, 2011; Hansen, 2006; Huysmans, 1998), although with a more sociological twist, since it is embedded in social fields of recognition. That difference also shows in the understanding of Mitzen’s critique that anxiety can also encourage creative agency (see the excellent discussions in Berenskoetter, 2016; Rumelili, 2015a, 2015b) and not only narrowing agency, which she sees represented by the revival of geopolitical thought. Yet, as truly important as this argument is for OST, it differs in two ways from my approach. Firstly, the dissonance reduction in the book is empirically studied at the level of ideas themselves, not of foreign policy behaviour.6 Secondly, the approach does not share the potential status quo bias of OST. Indeed, Weldes’ analysis of the security imaginary insists on the possibility of re-articulating these repertoires. It is something we would expect to happen, in particular, in times of crises where public demand for ‘story-telling’ is elevated, that is, where agents come up with new ways to rearrange the plots for making sense of a world in change (Krebs, 2015). 432 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

It is, therefore, not primarily in terms of agency-narrowing that one should understand the revival of geopolitical thought. Although Huntington’s geopolitical as geocultural re-articulation of the Cold War in terms of a ‘clash of civilization’ relies on old tropes (see e.g. Dalby, 1990; Ó Tuathail and Agnew, 1992), it puts them creatively together to provide a very powerful vision in a moment of conceptual disarray.7 In other words, the response to anxiety in terms of OS is not the same as dissonance reduction in the book, both for the locus and conceptualization of identity and, consequently, for the actual mechanism that carries the weight of theorization. This still leaves open Mitzen’s probing question about the causal process. Mitzen raises the issue of multi-finality, namely that the identity crisis could have several out- comes, not only the binary about geopolitical revival. I agree. In fact, the first mechanism I develop in the book is not about geopolitical thought at all, but specifies possible solu- tions for an identity crisis. As I write:

Such a dissonance would then trigger more concrete responses, which include: (1) denial that there is any dissonance to start with; (2) negotiation, that is, attempts to dissuade the other from the faulty identity vision (i.e. there is a perceived dissonance, but this is based on a misunderstanding); and (3–4) the acceptance of a real dissonance, which then spurs either attempts to change the international culture in such a way as to enable one’s own identity to fit (imposition), or efforts to redefine the identity as a way of adapting to external expectations or projections (adaptation). I posit these responses as components of the overall analysis of this discursive mechanism. (Guzzini, 2012d: 267)

These four outcomes fit a deductive matrix, distinguishing on the one axis whether foreign policy discourses acknowledge the need for identity discourses to change, and then whether they see the change to be happening within themselves or abroad (see Agnew in Agnew et al., 2017).

Table 1. Multiple paths of foreign policy identity crisis reduction. Need for identity change acknowledged No Yes Locus of change Internal Denial Adaptation External Negotiation Imposition

There is no reason to believe that these are the only ways, however. For instance, Pinar Bilgin and Ayşe Zarakol develop other historical answers to identity crises. Bilgin (2008) adapts Homi Bhabha’s (1994: 85–92) take on ‘mimicry’ as something that includes both emulation and camouflage. She develops the puzzle that secularism in Turkey is associated with security and argues that Turkey’s Kemalist turn to secularism was meant to imitate a picture of the West for protecting the new country from an always possible external intervention. This is a form of adaptation that is an active appropriation that does not, however, end up ‘being the same’. Zarakol (2010) also finds a different reaction to international socialization pressures beyond adaptation or imposition. In her Guzzini 433 analysis of Turkey’s and Japan’s refusal to accept what appears to them as a form of self- denial, we would, in fact, have a way to understand endemic identity crises as depicted in the book; for dissonance is only temporarily reduced, oscillating between showing the ‘good’ internal side and calling the hypocrisy of the external expectation. In her work on stigma management, she opens up the categories of adaptation and imposition by show- ing strategies of outright rejection without a chance to impose, or ressentiment without real adaptation (Zarakol, 2011: 104–107). Their conceptualizations point to a neglected component in conceptualizing the pro- cesses of identity crisis reduction in the book. Not only are there always different identity discourses within a security imaginary, but such individual discourses are often intrinsi- cally heterogeneous. This can be understood in terms of liminal identities (Norton, 1988), like ‘strangers’, both foreign and at home (for IR, see e.g. Mälksoo, 2012a; Rumelili, 2003, 2012), or as ‘hybridity’ stressed by postcolonial approaches (for a congenial IR application, see e.g. Morozov, 2015). As this shows, there are surely more, but not infi- nite, ways to dissonance reduction. The book contributes to the theorization of the mech- anism; it is not its end. Hence, multi-finality is indeed crucial for my understanding of social/causal mechanisms. However, that may only displace Mitzen’s critique: the argument is now too loose to be explanatory at all, neglecting alternative or parallel causal lines. The issue turns towards the very status of the explanation and its underlying take on causation. Mitzen rightly identifies a shift in the analysis from the early framework chapter to the last one. Whereas the early setup looks rather for the causes of effects (the geopolitical revival), by the final chapter the book looks for the indeterminate effects of causal mechanisms within the process itself (and not between variables). Her charge is therefore justified to the extent that if the book had stayed with its initial empirical puzzle only and not pro- posed a theory development, a different strategy would have been warranted. The book can still make a point for the role of identity processes in the revival, but this role is more circumscribed, since I introduce multi-final outcomes for the first mechanism with an open link between this mechanism to geopolitical revival. Mitzen’s concern about what is actually explained turns into a question of what can be explained in interpretivist pro- cess tracing.

Social mechanisms, causality and constructivist theory Jeffrey Checkel too sees the need for more theorization. Although generally persuaded by the clarity and transparency of the way the mechanisms are established and interpre- tivist process tracing is conceptualized, he sees ‘constructivism at mid-life’ (crisis). For one, he ironically sees the book falling into the trap of the ‘tyranny of mechanisms’ where research programmes feed into an ever-growing list of non-cumulative mecha- nisms. This charge is ironic, since it echoes the critique of its methodological opposite, that is, quantitative correlational analysis: lots of little regularities, empirical and induc- tive, but no real theory. He does not see how these mechanisms could travel or be gener- alizable. No forest of theory for all the trees of mechanisms; at best, some meagre middle-range theory, as he teases. Secondly, he finds that the empirical study turns out to be of little difference to soft positivist approaches, in particular the ones that 434 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3) take historical sequence and time seriously. Finally, he wants to have more operational guidelines for the empirical analysis, good-practice community standards. I will concen- trate on the first two and leave, just as he suggests, the third one for future discussion, including about the nature of such standards (since pushing for some type of standards undermines the very specificity of interpretivist research; it is not innocent). Checkel sees the mechanisms as inductively derived. I think this take vitiates much of his argument. Just because the book does no deductive hypothesis testing, its empirical analysis is not purely inductive (which, as we know, is not possible anyway). Concentrating on the processes that go into identity formation and the self-fulfilling practices that con- stitute international cultural structures (Wendt, 1999: 184–189) are not just any kind of mechanisms; they are central for the micro–macro links in already established construc- tivist theorizing. Moreover, his comments seem to suggest that there are only two ways to theory, the grand theories, which tend to lose empirical detail, and empirical generalizations, induc- tively derived. By not using the first way, the book would be compelled to use the second – and from there the critique of inductivism, non-accumulation and problematic general- izability follows. That is too narrow a view on theorizing, however. In the book, the empirical–theoretical link is not in terms of empirical generalization to the universe of cases, but in terms of how the empirics affect the conceptual lenses with which we approach any empirical analysis. In this case, it specifies the mechanisms, their possible origins or multi-final results and their role in the understanding of the processes with which the underlying social theories of recognition can be used to analyse our world. Theory comes before the induction. Such a view on theorization also leads to a different understanding of generalization and accumulation. The accumulation does not take place in the aggregate of mechanisms that fill up our theoretical universe; it takes place in the refinement of the conceptual apparatus with which our theories engage the empirical universe (and where Mitzen justifiably pitched her critique). Those mechanisms do indeed travel, but not via gener- alization; they travel via a form of abstraction, similar to ideal types, which are embed- ded in a (here: constructivist) framework of analysis that will be applied to other cases or events (for a comparable argument within a thin soft rationalist framework, see Bengtsson and Hertting, 2014). By not seeing the crucial role of ontological or constitutive theorizing for the social sciences in general (Guzzini, 2013), and for constructivism in particular, and by reducing our theorizing to the classical inductive–deductive scheme of (more empiricist) positiv- ism, Checkel misses the dynamics of theorization in the book. Truth be told, the book takes much of this for granted when embarking on its constructivist analysis, and the embeddedness into underlying social theories is not thoroughly pursued. Still, when claiming to look for the micro-dynamics of constructivist theory from an interpretivist angle, no other type of theorizing would make sense. Similarly, Checkel’s teaser of ‘middle-range theory’ mobilizes a more positivist understanding of the term (mid-range empirical generalization), which is not all what the middle-range can offer. The book does constitutive theorizing by developing micro- dynamics of constructivism and empirical theorizing by specifying the work of mecha- nisms. Doing so, it may actually not be too far from Merton’s initial call for the Guzzini 435 middle-range, which was never meant just to be a kind of inductive generalization of limited ambition (see also Tilly, 2010). Merton’s strategy was dual. On the one hand, he asked for middle-range ‘abstraction’ to be done in terms of ‘mechanisms’, which is how he understood self-fulfilling prophecies (Merton, 1948: 200) and that could very well include macro-sociological phenomena, as in Max Weber’s Protestant Ethic. On the other hand, this was to be done in connection with the development of a ‘conceptual scheme that is adequate to consolidate groups of special theories’, which he calls ‘para- digms’ and that develop both the underlying assumptions and conceptual meanings (Merton, 1968: 51, 69–72). I would agree more with Checkel’s second remark that empirical analyses may not look all that different across the epistemological divide. I share his sense that there is something positive about this, precisely because meta-theoretical discussions can be misused for empty flag-waving and cosy camp-building, which Checkel has always rightly and consistently opposed. I would, however, reverse the implication that is usu- ally drawn (albeit perhaps not by Checkel). If it were true that the differences are not so big in empirical research, that different methodological understandings (about the types of theory, etc.) do not impede cross- epistemological communication, then surely our research and teaching would be happily integrating both sides of the divide. It seems, however, that not much has changed since Hayward Alker’s (2000) pointed invitation to do so (Hagmann and Biersteker, 2014). To push it a little further: rather than assuming that all empirical constructivist analyses are closet positivistic approaches, hence condoning the use of positivist criteria for their assessment, could it be that the positivists who take historical institutionalism and idea- tional approaches seriously are closet interpretivists? What if the differences were not large, because it is so hard to be a consistently positivist researcher when doing problem- driven, not method-driven analysis of the kind that opens the black box of historical processes and individual preference formation? What, for instance, if it turns out that the underlying understanding of causality cannot be a Humean constant conjunction? For this is precisely what the conceptualization of social mechanisms proposes in the book. It is inspired by understandings of causality that go beyond Humean constant con- junction (Guzzini, 2012d: 256–264). This is a point that has been pushed for quite a while by critical realists in IR (e.g. Kurki, 2008; Patomäki, 1996; Wight, 2006) and also by researchers interested in historical processes (e.g. Lebow, 2014; Suganami, 2008).8 The book’s take starts from Jon Elster’s definition of social mechanisms as ‘frequently occurring and easily recognizable causal patterns that are triggered under generally unknown conditions or with indeterminate consequences’ (Elster, 1998: 45, 2007: 36). In this wording, leaving open either origins or effects, social sciences cannot aspire to gen- eral laws (where both conditions and consequences are known) but offer more than pure contingency (where none would). As Hedström and Ylikovski (2010: 53) write, this excludes approaches that define ‘causality in terms of regularities (such as Hume’s con- stant conjunction theory or many probabilistic theories of causation)’. Yet, the latter was initially even proposed by George and Bennett (2005: 225–227), a take now revised (Bennett and Checkel, 2015: 6–7). It seems to me that the interpretivist implications of going beyond probability (which leaves the logic of constant conjunction unchanged, but qualifies its usage in the social 436 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3) world) and of taking non-linear temporality seriously (Abbott, 1988) are not sufficiently acknowledged, if at all (for more detailed discussion on determinacy, see Guzzini, 2016; Lebow, 2014: 92ff.). So does the introduction of a recent special issue invite scholars to focus on their ontology first, already distinguishing mechanisms for being either deduc- tively or inductively derived, and either determinist or probabilistic (Trampusch and Palier, 2016)? This prompts a punctual reminder by Renate Mayntz (2016) that these distinctions miss the more fundamental issues on causality opened by contemporary ontological debates on contingency and time. If, however, we start from such ontologies, then there is a way to think causality in terms of ‘causal reconstructions’ (Mayntz, 2002), which is characterized by its multi-finality with contingent links, its non-linear process and mechanism character, historicity (taking sequence seriously) and complexity (which is not just stochastic). It is an explanation but without regularity, and yet not just a description since it includes abstracted and transferable aspects (see also her excellent discussion in Mayntz, 2004).9 The book explores a version of process tracing that includes such open causality and that is interpretivist, historical and multi-layered. It is interpretivist for two rea- sons. Firstly, the starting moment of the process is not given by a mere external choc (the end of the Cold War), but by how such events are understood in foreign policy discourses. Secondly, by looking at self-fulfilling mechanisms, it includes a reflexive element in which such interpretations, in turn, affect world politics. It is historical, because it takes sequence and time seriously (Grzymala-Busse, 2011), which means that explanatory factors along the path cannot simply be aggregated to increase total variance. This is obviously a point that has been made for a long time by some histori- cal sociologists (Tilly, 1998, 2001) and historical institutionalism (Pierson, 2000) or comparative-historical analysis, when the latter is defined by a focus on macro-config- urational explanation, the pursuit of problem-driven case-based research and a method- ical commitment to temporally oriented analysis (see this recent conceptualization in Thelen and Mahoney, 2015). The process tracing is also multi-layered (for want of a better term), showing how autonomous processes evolve and interact with each other during the period an analyst has decided to study. Rather than assuming one single process line that various factors punctuate, ‘the focus is not … on the trajectory of a single process. It is on the temporal intersection of distinctive trajectories of different, but connected, long-term processes’ (Aminzade, 1992: 467). As Falleti and Lynch (2009: 1156–1158) show, such processes can be conceptualized within layers in an analysis that cuts a certain time period out of them for the sake of studying a theory-informed empirical puzzle.10 Configurational analysis (see also Jackson, 2006) is laid out into time, where some processes change at higher speed than others (from bottom to top in Figure 1). Figure 1 illustrates two sequences with one mechanism each, connected (or not) by the rise of geopolitical thought. The first mechanism has a multi-final outcome, which, in turn, is dependent on the effects of the other relevant processes (political culture, political economy of expertise and political struggles/mobilization) for making the revival of geopolitical thought possible (for a summary of the book’s hypotheses and findings, see Guzzini, 2012d: 248–249). Geopolitical revival is not a functional neces- sity. The book unfortunately only has cases where identity crises and revivals are Guzzini 437

Figure 1. Social mechanisms in a time-layered interpretivist process model (reprinted with permission from Guzzini, 2012d: 273). connected. Yet, the case of Sweden could be one where the end of the Cold War produced an identity crisis, since the country’s neutral identity (Malmborg, 2001) made less sense, and yet no geopolitical revival ensued. The process tracing is not committed to a regular- ity, but to finding out how and whether the mechanism can be seen in the individual cases. The second mechanism, which is not developed in detail in the book, starts from a geopolitical revival and then applies it as a self-fulfilling mechanism, a ‘vicious circle of essentialization’, which affects the culture of anarchy (for the same type of mechanism, see ‘securitization’ in the Copenhagen School; see Guzzini, 2011). Just as the choice of these two mechanisms is not accidental, but central for constructivist theories, the choice of geopolitics as the focus is also not fortuitous. Neoclassical geopolitics provides a crucial link in the process. On the one hand, it responds to identity processes, being about state properties such as culture, territory, borders and the national imagination. On the other hand, its dual dynamics of essentializing identities and militarizing politics have an effect on the cultures of anarchy, constituted by the collective self-understandings and the definition of the relevant ‘roles’ in the international sphere of recognition. In this case, they would be encouraging a more Hobbesian culture of anarchy. Yet, the overall outcome can be influenced by the same type of self-fulfilling mecha- nism but with different content. There can obviously also be de-essentializing and demil- itarizing identity discourses. The post-national European Union (EU) is sometimes seen in this light, and desecuritizing strategies such as German Ostpolitik work that way, too. The revival of neoclassical geopolitics was the empirical puzzle that, for its central place in the two sequences (start or end), prompted a theory development. However, it would surely not claim to be the only set of ideational practices affecting cultures of anarchy. 438 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

Conclusion In my reading, Checkel’s critique is based on a limited understanding of the role of theories in the social sciences, and the place the two theoretically central mechanisms of the book have in and for constructivist theory. I did not answer his methodological critique, which would then have to start from that different take on theorizing and expla- nations. Similarly, besides acknowledging her points, I think that my discussion has shown that neither the mechanisms nor the underlying causality work in the way Mitzen assumes in her critique of missing multi-finality and theory. Theorizing foreign policy identity is not subsumed under OST (see also Browning and Joenniemi, 2017). If so, their theoretical relationship is, however, not sufficiently explored, which I take to be one important implication of Mitzen’s critique. That would include, for instance, the question of how these mechanisms relate to the social psychology of identity processes (for different takes, see Kinnvall, 2004, 2017; Lebow, 2016) and of nationalism, men- tioned in Agnew’s critique. That leaves Agnew’s main point. Precisely because I have developed the analysis in terms of multiple simultaneous processes, and precisely because I do analyse security imaginaries/foreign policy discourses within their institutional and political context (for such a critique of discursive approaches, see Laffey, 2000), his critique is meant to push me/us further by including an economic factor of the longue durée. The issue is how to include it. It could be yet another layer with the practices of the global political economy, which would affect the process under scrutiny. The book does not, in principle, exclude such an addition; yet so far, it theorizes the effects of capitalist practices within the other processual layers. Similar to Bourdieu, capitalist processes are a background process that affect all fields; their analysis is hence done within those fields and their interaction. This way to deal with them fits the short time-span focus of the book, but it does not cover the macro-historical shifts that Agnew may have in mind. I am grateful to this Forum for having pushed the book’s conceptualization of foreign policy identity crisis and its proposed interpretivist process tracing with social mecha- nisms further, not least by exposing its limits and omissions. Its political implications remain. The book traces how the end of the Cold War and the overall peace in Europe could lead to a militarization of international politics and essentialization of identities via foreign policy identity crises and the rise in geopolitical thinking. As paradoxical as it may sound, peace made militarization possible – well before 9/11. Such militarization and essentialization of foreign policy discourses has affected the interpretation of inter- national events since the 1990s, and has prepared the ground (among other factors) for securitizing societies and militarizing actual foreign policies, such as in NATO expan- sion and in the Crimea.

Acknowledgements This reply has profited from comments I received when presenting the book’s theses at lectures at Comenius University (Bratislava), the San Tiago Dantas Graduate School in International Relations (São Paulo), the Universities of the Basque Country (Bilbao), Coimbra, Cornell, LSE, Minnesota, Montréal (UdM), Pavia, Stockholm, UNA (Universidad Nacional Costa Rica), as well as the Collegio Carlo Alberto (Turin), the Swedish Institute of International Affairs (Stockholm) and in particular from a workshop dedicated to its theses at the Université Libre de Bruxelles and the Guzzini 439 discussion following my Dasturzada Dr Jal Pavry Memorial Lecture 2016 at Oxford University. My special thanks go to Pinar Bilgin, Barbara Delcourt, Andrew Hurrell, Ian Klinke, Frédéric Mérand, Kacper Szulecki, and Sid Tarrow. I also wish to express my gratitude to Riksbankens Jubileumsfond for financing a sabbatical at Cornell University during which this reply was researched and drafted.

Notes 1. I actually share Deudney’s critique of Western politics in Eastern Europe, having been an early critique of NATO expansion. However, that is not the issue here. 2. ‘Moreover, Guzzini’s excellent discussion of realism and geopolitics could have made for a much-needed stand-alone journal article’ (Klinke, 2013: 2). 3. Like Erik Ringmar (1996), I was here inspired by our former teacher, Alessandro Pizzorno (2007, 2008). Using recognition for theorizing action and society can be derived from a series of sociological traditions, as for instance from Alfred Schutz (1964) and George Herbert Mead (1934) to Berger and Luckmann (1966), from Ricœur (2004) or from different post- Hegelian traditions (Honneth, 1992, 2010; Taylor, 1989, 1992). I should also add that in my understanding, such social recognition is not power-free, but used in parallel to a theory of domination, in my case Bourdieu-inspired. 4. Agnew also charges the book with relying on ‘neat territorial experiences’, most probably because the security imaginary and much of the analysis is at the level of states. While it is correct that the setup encourages methodological nationalism, I think the charge is somewhat overstated. For the security imaginary, this depends on how the field is constituted. In some countries, particular foreign experts are part of or invited into the field (see for Huntington in the chapter on Estonia). In some countries, the field includes ‘authorized’ (usually US-based) experts (e.g. Zbignev Brzezsinski for Poland; Edward Luttwak for Italy). None of the other ideational, institutional or political factors are necessarily just neatly territorial and nothing excludes their experiences from being cross-national or international, even if they are picked up through a national passage point. 5. In this context, Zarakol (2017) raises the issue of how aspects of ontological security may have become included in the social recognition of sovereignty. 6. Therefore, the usage of dissonance is similar, but not the same as in Sucharov (2005) and Lupovici (2012), two studies that respectively deal with cognitive or ontological dissonance in Israeli identity and foreign policy. 7. The Clash of Civilizations? (Huntington, 1993) has been perhaps the single most cited article in IR: 1470 citations in the SSCI (accessed 11 December 2016). Huntingtonianism held (and still holds) a large place in the political imaginary and public discussions, amply documented by political geographers for the USA (see e.g. Bassin, 2007; Ó Tuathail, 1996: Chapter 7). It seems odd to imply that such tropes were not important in policy deliberation, public debate or academia in the USA in the 1990s (see also the analysis of Eurocentrism in Hobson, 2012). A Google Books Ngram viewer for ‘geopolitics’ (English) also shows a massive increase in the 1990s and then more or less stagnation for 2000 and after. I am grateful to Gabriel Cepaluni for this pointer. 8. See also the forthcoming special section on causality in JIRD, edited by Adam Humphreys and Hidemi Suganami (Betts and Pilath, 2016; Guzzini, 2016; Humphreys, 2016; Jackson, 2016; Kurki, 2016; Patomaki, 2016; Suganami, 2016). 9. This may explain why Elster’s approach and the conceptualization offered here are not proba- bilistic, deterministic or idiosyncratic, and hence elude existing typologies like Beach and Pedersen (for a recent take, see 2016). 10. One could see this process as a way to introduce time into a Bourdieusian analysis of several fields and their interaction. 440 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

References Abbott A (1988) Transcending general linear reality. Sociological Theory 6(2): 169–186. Agnew J (2003) Geopolitics: Re-visioning World Politics. London: Routledge. Agnew J, Checkel J, Deudney DH, et al. (2017) Symposium on Stefano Guzzini’s (ed.) The return of geopolitics in Europe? Social mechanisms and foreign policy identity crises. Cooperation and Conflict. Epub ahead of print 25 May. DOI: 10.1177/0010836717706985 Alker HR (2000) On learning from Wendt. Review of International Studies 26(1): 141–150. Aminzade R (1992) and time. Sociological Methods & Research 20(4): 456–480. Aron R (1962) Paix et guerre entre les nations. Paris: Calmann-Lévy. Aron R (1976) Penser la guerre, Clausewitz. II: L’âge planétaire. Paris: Gallimard. Astrov A and Morozova N (2012) Russia: Geopolitics from the heartland. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 192–216. Bassin M (1987) Race contra space: The conflict between German Geopolitik and National Socialism. Political Geography Quarterly 6(2): 115–134. Bassin M (2004) The two faces of contemporary geopolitics. Progress in Human Geography 28(5): 620–626. Bassin M (2007) Civilisations and their discontents: Political geography and geopolitics in the Huntington thesis. Geopolitics 12(3): 351–374. Beach D and Pedersen RB (2016) Process-Tracing Methods: Foundations and Guidelines. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press. Behnke A (2012) The theme that dare not speak its name: Geopolitik, geopolitics and German foreign policy since unification. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 101–126. Behnke A (2013) NATO’s Security Discourse after the Cold War. Abingdon: Routledge. Bengtsson B and Hertting N (2014) Generalization by mechanism: Thin rationality and ideal-type analysis in case study research. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44(6): 707–732. Bennett A and Checkel J (2015) Process tracing: From philosophical roots to best practices. In: Bennett A and Checkel J (eds) Process Tracing: From Metaphor to Analytical Tool. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–37. Berenskoetter F (2014) Parameters of a national biography. European Journal of International Relations 20(1): 262–288. Berenskoetter F (2016) Time, anxiety, agency. In: Paper presented at the CEEISA–ISA joint con- vention, Ljubljana, 23–25 June. Berger PL and Luckmann T (1966) The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books. Betts A and Pilath A (2016) The politics of causal claims: The case of environmental migra- tion. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 5 July. DOI: 10.1057/s41268-016-0003-y Bhabha HK (1994) The Location of Culture. London; New York: Routledge. Bilgin P (2008) The securityness of secularism? The case of Turkey. Security Dialogue 39(6): 593–614. Bilgin P (2012) Turkey’s ‘geopolitics dogma’. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 151–173. Bilgin P (2017) The International in Security, Security in the International. Abingdon: Routledge. Bourdieu P (2001) Language et pouvoir symbolique. Paris: Seuil. Guzzini 441

Brighi E and Petito F (2012) Geopolitics ‘in the land of the prince’: A passe-partout to (global) power politics? In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 127–150. Browning CS and Joenniemi P (2017) Ontological security, self-articulation and the securitization of identity. Cooperation and Conflict 52(1): 31–47. Campbell D (1992) Writing Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Carr EH (1946) The Twenty Years’ Crisis: An Introduction to the study of International Relations. London: Macmillan. Cohen SB (1991) Global geopolitical change in the post-Cold War era. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 81(4): 551–580. Cohen SB (2003) Geopolitical realities and United States foreign policy. Political Geography 22(1): 1–33. Combes M (2017) Encountering the stranger: Ontological security and the Boston Marathon bombing. Cooperation and Conflict 52(1): 126–143. Dalby S (1990) American security discourse: The persistence of geopolitics. Political Geography Quarterly 9(2): 171–188. Dijkink G (1996) National Identity and Geopolitical Visions: Maps of Pride and Pain. London; New York: Routledge. Drulák P (2012) Czech geopolitics: Struggling for survival. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 77–100. Elster J (1998) A plea for mechanisms. In: Hedström P and Swedberg R (eds) Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 45– 73. Elster J (2007) Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Epstein C (2011) Who speaks? Discourse, the subject and the study of identity in international politics. European Journal of International Relations 17(2): 327–350. Falleti TG and Lynch JF (2009) Context and causal mechanisms in political analysis. Comparative Political Studies 42(9): 1143–1166. Foucher M (1988) Fronts et frontières. Un tour du monde géopolitique. Paris: Fayard. George A and Bennett A (2005) Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Goldberg J (2016) World chaos and world order: Conversations With Henry Kissinger. The Atlantic. Available at: http://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2016/11/kissinger- order-and-chaos/506876/ (accessed 8 December 2016). Grzymala-Busse A (2011) Time will tell? Temporality and the analysis of causal mechanisms and processes. Comparative Political Studies 44(9): 1267–1297. Guzzini S (2003) ‘Self-fulfilling geopolitics?’, or: The social production of foreign policy exper- tise in Europe. DIIS Working Papers. Copenhagen: Danish Institute for International Studies. Guzzini S (2011) Securitization as a causal mechanism. Security Dialogue 42(4–5): 329–341. Guzzini S (2012a) The framework of analysis: Geopolitics meets foreign policy identity crises. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 45–74. Guzzini S (2012b) The mixed revival of geopolitics in Europe. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 219–250. Guzzini S (ed.) (2012c) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 442 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

Guzzini S (2012d) Social mechanisms as micro-dynamics in constructivist analysis. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 251–277. Guzzini S (2012e) Which geopolitics? In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 18–44. Guzzini S (2012f) Which puzzle? An expected return of geopolitical thought in Europe? In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 9–17. Guzzini S (2013) The ends of international relations theory: Stages of reflexivity and modes of theorizing. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 521–541. Guzzini S (2016) Power and cause. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 1 July. DOI: 10.1057/s41268-016-0002-z. Hacking I (1999) The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hagmann J and Biersteker TJ (2014) Beyond the published discipline: Toward a critical pedagogy of international studies. European Journal of International Relations 20(2): 291–315. Hall M and Hobson JM (2010) Liberal international theory: Eurocentric but not always imperial- ist? International Theory 2(2): 210–245. Hansen L (2006) Security as Practice: Discourse Analysis and the Bosnian War. London; New York: Routledge. Haushofer K (1924) Geopolitik des Pazifischen Ozeans. Studien über die Wechselbeziehungen zwischen Geographie und Geschichte. Berlin: Kurt Vowinckel Verlag. Haushofer K (1934) Weltpolitik von heute. Berlin: “Zeitgeschichte” Verlag und Vertriebs-GmbH. Hawkins M (1997) Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hedström P and Ylikovski P (2010) Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology 36: 49–67. Hobson JM (2012) The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hofstadter R (1944) Social Darwinism in American Thought. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Honneth A (1992) Kampf um Anerkennung. Zur moralischen Grammatik sozialer Konflikte. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Honneth A (2010) Das Ich im Wir. Studien zur Anerkennungstheorie. Berlin: Suhrkamp. Hopf T (2002) Social Construction of International Politics: Identities and Foreign Policies, Moscow, 1955 and 1999. Ithaca, NJ: Cornell University Press. Humphreys AR (2016) Causation, complexity, and the concert: The pragmatics of causal expla- nation in international relations. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 17 June. DOI: 10.1057/jird.2016.10. Hunter JH (1986) Commentary on “the social origins of environmental determinism”. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 76(2): 277–281. Huntington SP (1993) The clash of civilizations? Foreign Affairs 72(3): 22–42. Huysmans J (1998) Security! What do you mean? From concept to thick signifier. European Journal of International Relations 4(2): 226–255. Jackson PT (2006) Civilizing the Enemy: German Reconstruction and the Invention of the West. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press. Jackson PT (2016) Causal claims and causal explanation in international studies. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 20 May. DOI: 10.1057/jird.2016.13. Jean C (1995) Geopolitica. Roma; Bari: Editori Laterza. Guzzini 443

Kinnvall C (2004) Globalization and religious nationalism: Self, identity, and the search for onto- logical security. Political Psychology 25(5): 741–767. Kinnvall C (2017) Feeling ontologically (in)secure: States, traumas and the governing of gendered space. Cooperation and Conflict 52(1): 90–108. Kissinger HA (1954) The conservative dilemma: Reflections on the political thought of Metternich. American Political Science Review 48(4): 1017–1030. Klinke I (2013) The geopolitics of European (dis)union (review essay). Political Geography 37: 1–4. Krebs RR (2015) Tell me a story: FDR, narrative, and the making of the Second World War. Security Studies 24(1): 131–170. Kurki M (2008) Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kurki M (2016) Causality, support and the cult of the factish gods. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 29 April. DOI: 10.1057/ jird.2016.12. Kuus M (2012) Banal Huntingtonianism: Civilisational geopolitics in Estonia. In: Guzzini S (ed.) The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and Foreign Policy Identity Crises. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 174–191. Kuus M (2014) Geopolitics and Expertise: Knowledge and Authority in European Diplomacy. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. Lacoste Y (1978) La géographie, ça sert d’abord à faire la guerre. Paris: Maspéro. Lafer C (2004) A Identitade internacional do Brasil e a política externa brasileira: passado, pre- sente e futuro. 2nd ed. São Paulo: Perspectiva. Laffey M (2000) Locating identity: Performativity, foreign policy and state action. Review of International Studies 26(3): 429–444. Lebow RN (2014) Constructing Cause in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lebow RN (2016) National Identities and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lupovici A (2012) Ontological dissonance, clashing identities, and Israel’s unilateral steps towards the Palestinians. Review of International Studies 38(4): 809–833. Mackinder HJ (1904) The geographical pivot of history. The Geographical Journal 23(4): 421–437. Mälksoo M (2012a) The challenge of liminality for international relations theory. Review of International Studies 38(2): 481–494. Mälksoo M (2012b) The Politics of Becoming European: A Study of Polish and Baltic Post-Cold War Security Imaginaries. Abingdon: Routledge. Malmborg M (2001) Neutrality and State-Building in Sweden. Houndmills: Palgrave. Mayntz R (2002) Zur Theoriefähigkeit makro-sozialer Analysen. In: Mayntz R (ed.) Akteure – Mechanismen – Modelle. Zur Theoriefähigkeit makro-sozialer Analysen. Frankfurt; New York: Campus, pp. 7–43. Mayntz R (2004) Mechanisms in the analysis of social macro-phenomena. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34(2): 237–259. Mayntz R (2016) Process tracing, abstraction, and varieties of cognitive interest. New Political Economy 21(5): 484–488. Mead GH (1934) Mind, Self and Society: From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Mearsheimer J (1990) Back to the future: Instability in Europe after the cold war. International Security 15(1): 5–56. Merton RK (1948) The self-fulfilling prophecy. The Antioch Review 8(2): 193–210. 444 Cooperation and Conflict 52(3)

Merton RK (1968) On sociological theories of the middle range. In: Merton RK (ed.) Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: The Free Press, pp. 39–72. Mitzen J (2006) Ontological security in world politics: State identity and the . European Journal of International Relations 12(3): 341–370. Morozov V (2015) Russia’s Postcolonial Identity: A Subaltern in a Eurocentric World. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan. Norton A (1988) Reflections on Political Identity. Baltimore, MD: The Press. Ó Tuathail G (1996) Critical Geopolitics. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Ó Tuathail G and Agnew J (1992) Geopolitics and discourse: Practical geopolitical reasoning in American foreign policy. Political Geography 11(2): 190–204. Parker G (1985) Western Geopolitical Thought in the Twentieth Century. London; Sydney, NSW, Australia: Croom Helm. Patomäki H (1996) How to tell better stories about world politics. European Journal of International Relations 2(1): 105–133. Patomaki H (2016) Praxis, politics and the future: A dialectical critical realist account of world- historical causation. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 13 May. DOI: 10.1057/jird.2016.17. Pierson P (2000) Not just what, but when: Timing and sequence in political processes. Studies in American Political Development 14: 72–92. Pizzorno A (2007) Il velo della diversità. Studi su razionalità e riconoscimento. Milano: Feltrinelli. Pizzorno A (2008) Rationality and recognition. In: Della Porta D and Keating M (eds) Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences: A Pluralist Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 162–173. Ratzel F (1882) Anthropo-Geographie oder Grundzüge der Anwendung der Erdkunde auf die Geschichte. Stuttgart: Verlag von J. Engelhorn. Ratzel F (1896a) Der Staat als Organismus. Die Grenzboten 55: 614–623. Ratzel F (1896b) The territorial growth of states. Scottish Geographical Magazine 12(7): 351–361. Ratzel F (1897) Politische Geographie. München; Leipzig: Oldenbourg. Ricœur P (2004) Parcours de la reconnaissance: trois études. Paris: Éditions Stock. Ringmar E (1996) Identity, Interest and Action: A Cultural Explanation of Sweden’s Intervention in the Thirty Years War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rumelili B (2003) Liminality and perpetuation of conflicts: Turkish-Greek relations in the context of the community-building by the EU. European Journal of International Relations 9(2): 213–248. Rumelili B (2012) Liminal identities and processes of domestication and subversion in interna- tional relations. Review of International Studies 38(2): 495–508. Rumelili B (2015a) Identity and desecuritisation: The pitfalls of conflating ontological and physi- cal security. Journal of International Relations and Development 18(1): 52–74. Rumelili B (2015b) Ontological (in)security and peace anxieties: A framework for conflict reso- lution. In: Rumelili B (ed.) Conflict Resolution and Ontological Security: Peace Anxieties. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 10–29. Rumsfeld D (2002) Press conference at NATO headquarters, Brussels, 6 June. Available at: http:// www.nato.int/docu/speech/2002/s020606g.htm (accessed 26 November 2016). Schumpeter JA (1975 [1942]) Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Harper. Schutz A (1964) Collected Papers II: Studies in Social Theory. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Sidaway JD (2014) (Review of) The return of geopolitics in Europe? By Stefano Guzzini. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space. Available at: http://societyandspace.org/2014/01/06/the- return-of-geopolitics-in-europe-social-mechanisms-and-foreign-policy-identity-crises-by-ste- fano-guzzini-reviewed-by-james-sidaway/ (accessed 28 November 2016). Guzzini 445

Steele BJ (2007) Ontological Security in International Relations: Self-Identity and the IR State. London: Routledge. Sucharov M (2005) The International Self: Psychoanalysis and the Search for Israeli-Palestinian Peace. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Suganami H (2008) Narrative explanation and international relations: Back to basics. Millennium: Journal of International Studies 37(2): 327–356. Suganami H (2016) On the Hume/Bhaskar contrast in philosophical metatheory of international relations. Journal of International Relations and Development. Epub ahead of print 17 June. DOI: 10.1057/jird.2016.9. Sur É (1995) La référence à la Geopolitik ou la tentation du déterminisme spatial. Matériaux pour l’histoire de notre temps 37–38: 31–37. Taylor C (1989) Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor C (1992) Multiculturalism and the Politics of Recognition. Princeton, NJ: Press. Thelen K and Mahoney J (2015) Comparative-historical analysis in contemporary political sci- ence. In: Mahoney J and Thelen K (eds) Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–36. Tilly C (1998) Durable Inequality. Berkeley: University of California Press. Tilly C (2001) Mechanisms in political process. Annual Review of Political Science 4: 21–41. Tilly C (2010) Mechanisms of the middle range. In: Calhoun C (ed.) Robert K. Merton: Sociology of Science and Sociology as Science. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 54–62. Trampusch C and Palier B (2016) Between X and Y: How process tracing contributes to opening the black box of causality. New Political Economy 21(5): 437–454. Weldes J (1999) Constructing National Interests: The United States and the Cuban Missile Crisis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Wendt A (1995) Constructing international politics. International Security 20(1): 71–81. Wendt A (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wight C (2006) Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wolfers A (1962) Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International Politics. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press. Zarakol A (2010) Ontological (in)security and state denial of historical crimes: Turkey and Japan. International Relations 24(1): 3–23. Zarakol A (2011) After Defeat: How the East Learned to Live with the West. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zarakol A (2017) States and ontological security: A historical rethinking. Cooperation and Conflict 52(1): 48–68.

Author biography Stefano Guzzini is Senior Researcher at the Danish Institute for International Studies, Professor of Government at Uppsala University, and Professor of International Relations at PUC-Rio de Janeiro. He has published nine books, including Power, Realism and Constructivism (Routledge, 2013), winner of the 2014 ISA Theory Section Best Book Award. He currently serves as President of the Central and East European International Studies Association (CEEISA). For more, see: http://www.diis.dk/en/experts/stefano-guzzini