The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites Under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann (UC Santa Cruz)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites Under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann (UC Santa Cruz) The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann (UC Santa Cruz) . Amsterdam Colloquium 2019 1 Introduction This talk A generalization • Presents an analysis of the above cases in intensional Compositional DRT (CDRT, following Muskens (1996); Brasoveanu (2010)) based on the assumption that a pronoun can be co-referential Indefinite DPs under non-veridical operators such as negation do not usually introduce a discourseref- with a preceding DP only if the referent of the DP exists in the worlds of evaluation of the pronoun erent (dref) that is available for subsequent reference (Karttunen (1969)): – Uses analyses of modal subordination in terms of simultaneous reference to sets of possible (1) There is [no bathroom]υ in this house. worlds (propositions) and individuals #Itυ is in a weird place. (Stone (1999); Stone and Hardt (1999); Brasoveanu (2007, 2010)) – Extends them to disjunction, double negation and disagreement cases Some counterexamples 2 The account (2) a. Double negation: (Karttunen (1969); Krahmer and Muskens (1995)) The intuition behind the analysis υ1 It’s not true that there is [no bathroom] in this house. Itυ1 is just in a weird place. • Counterfactual drefs under negation: Speaker committed to their non-existence b. Disjunction: (Krahmer and Muskens (1995)) (cf. hypothetical drefs in Stone (1999); Stone and Hardt (1999)) υ2 Either there is [no bathroom] in this house, or itυ is in a weird place. 2 • Pronoun presupposes existence of a referent c. Modal subordination: (Roberts (1989)) υ3 There is [no bathroom] in this house. Itυ3 would be easier to find. • Use of a pronoun in veridical contexts is inconsistent with counterfactual dref antecedent d. Disagreement: • BUT: Pronoun can co-refer with counterfactual dref if A: There’s [no bathroom]υ4 in this house. – It is in a counterfactual context (Modal subordination) B: (What are you talking about?) Itυ4 is right over there. – The discourse segments of the antecedent and pronoun do not have to be consistent (disjunc- tion, disagreement) Krahmer and Muskens (1995) The account in a nutshell Note that standard Discourse Representation Theory (DRT, Kamp (1981); Kamp and Reyle (1993)) (and • Antecedents and pronouns are interpreted relative to their local intensional context other classic dynamic semantic frameworks) don’t account for the counterexamples • Relativizing individual drefs to sets of worlds where they refer (Stone (1999); Stone and Hardt • Negation is externally static, indefinites in its scope never introduce global drefs (1999)) – In DRT, it introduces a subordinated discourse representation structure (DRS) – Gives rise to accessibility condition, capturing that pronouns presuppose existence of a ref- – Only drefs introduced in the same DRS or a superordinate DRS are accessible erent and are infelicitous otherwise • Sentential operators introduce drefs for sets of worlds providing a local context for interpretation of their prejacent K & M introduce an account of double negation and disjunction cases, based on… – Relation between local and global context sets is constrained semantically by the interpreta- • Semantics for negation that symmetrically switches between the extension and anti-extension of tion of linguistic expressions an expression Karttunen (1973); Heim (1983) • Semantics for disjunction that analogizes it to conditionals, truth-conditionally and dynamically – And pragmatically by set of worlds compatible with a speaker’s commitments • Doesn’t extend to cases w/o overt negation or disjunction (disagreement, modal subordination) Stalnaker (1978, 2002); Gunlogson (2004) 1 December 18, 2019 The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann 2.1 Intensional CDRT ϕ, ϕ : υ1; υ2 υ1 = Marye (3) Mary has a car CDRT with propositional discourse referents Muskens (1996); Brasoveanu (2007, 2010) carϕfυ2g f g • Four basic types: haveϕ υ1; υ2 t (truth-values), e (entities), w (possible worlds), and s (variable assignments) Relative variable update • Variable assignments Individual drefs map to an individual for all worlds in which their referent exists, and to an indeterminate – Objects manipulated and updated in context value #e in all other worlds (cf Stone (1999); Stone and Hardt (1999)) – In classic static systems: Functions from variables to entities (4) i[ϕ : υ]j, where ϕ 2 Term ; υ 2 Term , holds iff the conjunction of the following holds: – Here: Basic type s (discourse states) s(wt) s(we) • Discourse referents (drefs) •i[υ]j 0 – Functions from assignments to referents •8ww:(ϕ(j)(w) ! υ (i)(w) =6 # – Individual drefs: type s(we) •8ww:(:ϕ(j)(w) ! υ(j)(w) = #) ∗ Functions from assignments is and worlds ww to individuals xe ∗ Drefs for individual concepts j is an update of i with υ in relation to ϕ, iff ∗ Variables: υ, υ1; υ2;::: • j is an update of i that differs at most wrt the value assigned to υ – Propositional drefs: type s(wt) • for each world w in ϕ(j), υ(j)(w) doesn’t map to # (but an individual) ∗ Drefs for sets of worlds • for each world w not in ϕ(j), υ(j)(w) maps to # ∗ Variables: ϕ, ϕ1; ϕ2;::: Negation • Sentence meanings Negation introduces a counterfactual set of worlds wrt which its prejacent is interpreted – Conceptualized in terms of their context-change potential – Binary relations between discourse states: Type s(st) (5) S: Mary doesn’t sleep. – Anaphoric potential: Updating variable assignments ϕ1; ϕ1 : υ, ϕ2 ⊆ – Truth-conditions: Imposing conditions on propositional drefs ϕDCS ϕ1 S :(not(Mary sleep)) υ = Marye ϕ1 = ϕ2 f g sleepϕ2 υ 2.2 Drefs in relation to their local context • New drefs: • Conditions: – Matrix ϕ1 – ϕ1 is entailed by the commitments of S DRSs and Relativizing individual drefs ϕDC – not: Embedded ϕ2 S • A DRS contains a list of new drefs (ϕ, ϕ : υ1; : : : ; υn) – Mary: υ – Mary: υ refers to marye – Where individual drefs are introduced relative to propositional ones – not: ϕ1 and ϕ2 are complements • and a series of conditions of type st, i.e. properties of the output state (C1;:::;Cn) – Verb: υ sleeps in ϕ2 2 December 18, 2019 The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann Accessibility condition on pronominal reference: The hypothetical bathroom • A dref is accessible for reference by a variable, iff the referent exists in the local context ofthe υ variable. (7) S: There is [no bathroom] 1 . (9). S: It would be (more) accessible. • Local context defined wrt the evaluation of DRS conditions: ϕ1; ϕ2; ϕ2 : υ1 ϕ3 ⊆ ⊆ ϕDCS ϕ1 ϕDCS ϕ3 (6) Predicates with their arguments as conditions (type st): f g f g 8 2 ϕ1 = ϕ2 wouldϕ3 underlineϕ4 carϕ υ2 := λis: w ϕ(i):car(υ2(i)(w))(w) f g f g bathroomϕ2 υ1 accessibleϕ4 υ2 – υ2 is a car in ϕ wrt the variable assignment i, iff – Each world w in ϕ(i) is s.t. • Modal subordination: (Stone (1999); Stone and Hardt (1999); Brasoveanu (2007, 2010)) ∗ υ2(i)(w) =6 # (i.e. a referent of υ2 wrt i exists in w) and ∗ υ2(i)(w) is a car in w – would is anaphoric to a proposition that is not taken to be true in ϕDCS , this can be the counterfactual ϕ2 • A dref is an accessible antecedent for a variable in the context of is, ϕs(wt) iff the dref refers to something other than # (i.e. an actual individual) in each world in ϕ, wrt i – The local set of worlds for the interpretation of its prejacent is provided compositionally f g • Now we have accessibleϕ2 υ2 , so we get υ1 = υ2 2.3 Drefs under negation The non-existent bathroom The optional bathroom υ1 (7) S: There is [no bathroom] . (8) # S: Itυ3=υ1 is in a weird place. υ1 (10) S: Either there is [no bathroom] ,or itυ =υ is in a weird place. ϕ1; ϕ2; ϕ2 : υ1 ϕ3; ϕ3 : υ2 3 1 ⊆ ⊆ ϕ1; ϕ2; ϕ3; ϕ4; ϕ4 : υ1; ϕ3 : υ2 ϕDCS ϕ1 ϕDCS ϕ3 ϕDC ⊆ ϕ1 ϕ1 = ϕ2 placeϕ fυ2g S 3 ϕ = ϕ [ ϕ bathroom fυ g weird fυ g 1 2 3 ϕ2 1 ϕ3 2 ϕ = ϕ f g 2 4 inϕ3 υ3; υ2 f g bathroomϕ4 υ1 place fυ g • New drefs: • Conditions: ϕ3 2 f g weirdϕ3 υ2 – Matrix ϕ1 – ϕ1 is entailed by the commitments of S (ϕDCS ) f g inϕ3 υ3; υ2 – Embedded ϕ2 – ϕ1 and ϕ2 are complements • Assertion compatible with speaker’s commitments – υ1 exists in ϕ2 – υ1 is a bathroom in ϕ2 • Disjunction introduces two local sets of worlds that don’t have to be compatible • υ exists in all and only the counterfactual ϕ -worlds 1 2 • First disjunct: Analogous to the above negative sentences • υ1 doesn’t exist in any worlds in ϕ1, the complement of ϕ2 – υ1 exists in all and only the ϕ4-worlds, and in none of the worlds in ϕ2 f g • υ3 is interpreted in the condition inϕ3 υ3; υ2 • Second disjunct: • For υ1 to be an antecedent for υ3, υ1 needs to exist in all ϕ3-worlds – For υ1 to be an antecedent for υ3, υ1 needs to exist in all ϕ3-worlds \ \ ? • ϕDCS contains only worlds that are in ϕ1 ϕ3 • Compatible with an output discourse state, s.t. υ1 exists in ϕ3, i.e. the one where ϕ2 ϕ3 = , and υ3 can be resolved as υ1 • So, there are ϕ1-worlds in ϕ3, i.e. worlds where υ1 doesn’t exist • υ3 can’t refer to υ1 3 December 18, 2019 The Anaphoric Potential of Indefinites under Negation and Disjunction Lisa Hofmann The contested bathroom 4 Conclusion • The paper presents an analysis results in a flat-update dynamic semantics that globally introduces υ1 (7) S: There is [no bathroom] . (11). B: Itυ1 is (right over) there. anti-veridical drefs along with the information about the sets of worlds in which they exist : ϕ1; ϕ2; ϕ2 υ1 ϕ3 • The analysis provides an understanding of when the surrounding context allows for an anaphoric ϕ ⊆ ϕ ⊆ DCS 1 ϕDCB ϕ3 relation between expressions introducing anaphora and potential antecedents ϕ1 = ϕ2 there fυ g ϕ3 2 • It constitutes a step forward from previous approaches to anaphoric accessibility in classical DRT bathroomϕ fυ1g 2 (Kamp and Reyle (1993)), as well as analyses of modal subordination (Stone (1999)) and the double negation and disjunction cases (Krahmer and Muskens (1995)), by extending the empirical coverage.
Recommended publications
  • Anaphoric Reference to Propositions
    ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Todd Nathaniel Snider December 2017 c 2017 Todd Nathaniel Snider ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS Todd Nathaniel Snider, Ph.D. Cornell University 2017 Just as pronouns like she and he make anaphoric reference to individuals, English words like that and so can be used to refer anaphorically to a proposition introduced in a discourse: That’s true; She told me so. Much has been written about individual anaphora, but less attention has been paid to propositional anaphora. This dissertation is a com- prehensive examination of propositional anaphora, which I argue behaves like anaphora in other domains, is conditioned by semantic factors, and is not conditioned by purely syntactic factors nor by the at-issue status of a proposition. I begin by introducing the concepts of anaphora and propositions, and then I discuss the various words of English which can have this function: this, that, it, which, so, as, and the null complement anaphor. I then compare anaphora to propositions with anaphora in other domains, including individual, temporal, and modal anaphora. I show that the same features which are characteristic of these other domains are exhibited by proposi- tional anaphora as well. I then present data on a wide variety of syntactic constructions—including sub- clausal, monoclausal, multiclausal, and multisentential constructions—noting which li- cense anaphoric reference to propositions. On the basis of this expanded empirical do- main, I argue that anaphoric reference to a proposition is licensed not by any syntactic category or movement but rather by the operators which take propositions as arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modal Future
    The Modal Future A theory of future-directed thought and talk Cambridge University Press Fabrizio Cariani Contents Preface page vii Conventions and abbreviations xi Introduction xii PART ONE BACKGROUND 1 1 The symmetric paradigm 3 1.1 The symmetric paradigm 3 1.2 Symmetric semantics 4 1.3 The symmetric paradigm contextualized 10 1.4 Temporal ontology and symmetric semantics 14 Appendix to chapter 1: the logic Kt 17 2 Symmetric semantics in an asymmetric world 19 2.1 Branching metaphysics 20 2.2 Branching models 21 2.3 Symmetric semantics on branching models 27 2.4 Ways of being an Ockhamist 32 2.5 Interpreting branching models 32 PART TWO THE ROAD TO SELECTION SEMANTICS 39 3 The modal challenge 41 3.1 What is a modal? 42 3.2 The argument from common morphology 44 3.3 The argument from present-directed uses 45 3.4 The argument from modal subordination 48 3.5 The argument from acquaintance inferences 52 iii iv Contents 3.6 Morals and distinctions 54 4 Modality without quantification 56 4.1 Quantificational theories 57 4.2 Universal analyses and retrospective evaluations 59 4.3 Prior’s bet objection 60 4.4 The zero credence problem 61 4.5 Scope with negation 64 4.6 Homogeneity 66 4.7 Neg-raising to the rescue? 69 5 Basic selection semantics 73 5.1 Selection semantics: a first look 74 5.2 Basic versions of selection semantics 78 5.3 Notions of validity: a primer 81 5.4 Logical features of selection semantics 82 5.5 Solving the zero credence problem 83 5.6 Modal subordination 85 5.7 Present-directed uses of will 86 5.8 Revisiting the acquaintance
    [Show full text]
  • Counterfactuals and Modality
    Linguistics and Philosophy https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-020-09313-8 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Counterfactuals and modality Gabriel Greenberg1 Accepted: 9 October 2020 © Springer Nature B.V. 2021 Abstract This essay calls attention to a set of linguistic interactions between counterfactual conditionals, on one hand, and possibility modals like could have and might have,on the other. These data present a challenge to the popular variably strict semantics for counterfactual conditionals. Instead, they support a version of the strict conditional semantics in which counterfactuals and possibility modals share a unified quantifica- tional domain. I’ll argue that pragmatic explanations of this evidence are not available to the variable analysis. And putative counterexamples to the unified strict analysis, on careful inspection, in fact support it. Ultimately, the semantics of conditionals and modals must be linked together more closely than has sometimes been recognized, and a unified strict semantics for conditionals and modals is the only way to fully achieve this. Keywords Counterfactuals · Conditionals · Modality · Discourse This essay calls attention to a set of linguistic interactions between counterfactual conditionals, on one hand, and possibility modals like could have and might have,on the other. These data present a challenge to the popular variably strict semantics for counterfactual conditionals. Instead, they support a version of the strict conditional semantics in which counterfactuals and possibility modals share a unified quantifica- tional domain. I’ll argue that pragmatic explanations of this evidence are not available to the variable analysis. And putative counterexamples to the unified strict analysis, on careful inspection, in fact support it. Ultimately, the semantics of conditionals and modals must be linked together more closely than has sometimes been recognized, and a unified strict semantics for conditionals and modals is the only way to fully achieve this.
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit Arguments, Paychecks and Variable-Free Semantics*
    Proceedings of SALT 21: 155-175, 2011 Implicit Arguments, Paychecks and Variable-Free Semantics* Walter A. Pedersen McGill University Abstract The present paper focuses on a particular class of implicit arguments – what have been termed anaphoric implicit arguments (AIAs) – and presents an account of AIAs in the variable-free (VF) framework introduced in Jacobson 1999, 2000. In particular, it is demonstrated how AIAs allow „paycheck‟ (E-type) readings, an observation that goes back to Dowty 1981; it is shown that these readings follow naturally in the VF framework. The VF account is then compared and contrasted with some alternatives, including Condoravdi & Gawron‟s (1996) proposal that AIAs pattern with definite descriptions. Keywords: implicit arguments, paycheck pronouns, E-type anaphora, variable-free semantics 1 Introduction The topic of the present study is anaphoric implicit arguments (AIAs), and their incorporation into the variable-free framework proposed in Jacobson 1999, 2000. Special attention is paid to the E-type readings of AIAs first observed in Dowty 1981, and it is demonstrated how such readings follow naturally in a variable-free framework. The paper is organized as follows: §2 discusses the data relating to implicit arguments, and in particular to AIAs; §3 reviews the variable-free framework laid out in Jacobson 1999, 2000; §4 shows how anaphoric implicit arguments can be introduced into this framework; §5 compares the variable-free proposal to various alternatives, including the proposal in Condoravdi & Gawron 1996 that AIAs pattern with definite descriptions rather than pronouns. 2 Implicit Arguments The term „implicit argument‟ is a broad one, and the phenomenon to be discussed here has gone under different names in the literature; this multiplicity of labels reflects both *Thank you to Brendan Gillon, Ed Stabler, Ed Keenan, Jessica Rett, Pauline Jacobson, Chris Barker, Barbara Partee, and the UCLA linguistics department for their helpful comments and suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bound Variable Hierarchy and Donkey Anaphora in Mandarin Chinese
    The Bound Variable Hierarchy and Donkey Anaphora in Mandarin Chinese Haihua Pan and Yan Jiang City University of Hong Kong / London University Cheng and Huang (1996) argue that both unselective binding and E-type pro- noun strategies are necessary for the interpretation of natural language sentences and claim that there exists a correspondence between two sentence types in Chinese and the two strategies, namely that the interpretation of the “wh … wh” construction (which they call “bare conditional”) employs the unselective binding strategy, while the ruguo ‘if’ and dou ‘all’ conditionals use the E-type pronoun strategy. They also suggest that there is a complementary distribution between bare conditionals and ruguo/dou conditionals in the sense that the lat- ter allows all the NP forms, e.g. (empty) pronouns and definite NPs, except for wh-phrases in their consequent clauses, and can even have a consequent clause with no anaphoric NP in it, while the former permits only the same wh-phrase appearing in both the antecedent clause and the consequent clause. Although we agree with Cheng and Huang on the necessity of the two strategies in natural language interpretation, we see apparent exceptions to the correspondence between sentence types and interpretation strategies and the complementary distribution between wh-phrases and other NPs in bare conditionals and ruguo/dou conditionals. We think that the claimed correspondence and comple- mentary distribution are the default or preferred patterns, or a special case of a more general picture, namely that (i) bare conditionals prefer the unselective binding strategy and the ruguo ‘if’ and dou ‘all’ conditionals, the E-type pronoun strategy; and (ii) wh-phrases are more suitable for being a bound variable, and pronouns are more suitable for being the E-type pronoun.
    [Show full text]
  • The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Technical Reports (CIS) Department of Computer & Information Science January 1997 The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense Matthew Stone University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/cis_reports Recommended Citation Matthew Stone, "The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense", . January 1997. University of Pennsylvania Department of Computer and Information Science Technical Report No. MS-CIS-97-09. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/cis_reports/177 For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense Abstract In modal subordination, a modal sentence is interpreted relative to a hypothetical scenario introduced in an earlier sentence. In this paper, I argue that this phenomenon reflects the fact that the interpretation of modals is an ANAPHORIC process, precisely analogous to the anaphoric interpretation of tense. Modal morphemes introduce alternative scenarios as entities into the discourse model; their interpretation depends on evoking scenarios for described, reference and speech points, and relating them to one another. Although this account formalizes anaphoric connections using dynamic semantics, it invokes a novel and direct encoding of scenarios as ordinary, static objects (competing analyses take modal referents to be inherently dynamic objects, unlike the referents of pronouns and tenses). The result is a simpler proposal with
    [Show full text]
  • Diagnosing Modality in Predictive Expressions
    June 18, 2013 Diagnosing Modality in Predictive Expressions Peter Klecha University of Chicago Abstract This short paper argues that predictive expressions (will, gonna) are modals. In section 1 I provide three empirical arguments for a treatment of predictive expressions as modals: i) they behave like modals in that they can occur in overt and covert conditionals in a way that non-modal operators cannot; ii) they have morphologi- cal variants which show displacement behaviors, i.e., nonveridicality; iii) like modals, they obviate the personal experience requirement on predicates of personal taste. In section 2 I specifically rebut arguments by Kissine (2008) that will is not a modal. In section 3 I conclude. In this paper I argue that what I call predictive expressions (PEs) in English, words like will and gonna, are modal operators rather than simple temporal operators. (1) a. Ryan will leave for California tomorrow. b. Ryan is gonna leave for California tomorrow. The distinction between temporal and modal corresponds to a question about what the nature of the future is, or at least, how language treats the nature of the future: as a linear continuation of time, no different from the past (what can be called the Linear Future Hypothesis, sometimes called Ockhamist), or as a range of possible paths, a potentially infinite set of open possibilities (what can be called the Open Future Hypothesis, sometimes called Peircian); see, e.g., Kaufmann et al. (2006) . On the former view, there is a single actual world, even if we can never have the knowledge needed to distinguish it from other worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidentiality and Mood: Grammatical Expressions of Epistemic Modality in Bulgarian
    Evidentiality and mood: Grammatical expressions of epistemic modality in Bulgarian DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements o the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Anastasia Smirnova, M.A. Graduate Program in Linguistics The Ohio State University 2011 Dissertation Committee: Brian Joseph, co-advisor Judith Tonhauser, co-advisor Craige Roberts Copyright by Anastasia Smirnova 2011 ABSTRACT This dissertation is a case study of two grammatical categories, evidentiality and mood. I argue that evidentiality and mood are grammatical expressions of epistemic modality and have an epistemic modal component as part of their meanings. While the empirical foundation for this work is data from Bulgarian, my analysis has a number of empirical and theoretical consequences for the previous work on evidentiality and mood in the formal semantics literature. Evidentiality is traditionally analyzed as a grammatical category that encodes information sources (Aikhenvald 2004). I show that the Bulgarian evidential has richer meaning: not only does it express information source, but also it has a temporal and a modal component. With respect to the information source, the Bulgarian evidential is compatible with a variety of evidential meanings, i.e. direct, inferential, and reportative, as long as the speaker has concrete perceivable evidence (as opposed to evidence based on a mental activity). With respect to epistemic commitment, the construction has different felicity conditions depending on the context: the speaker must be committed to the truth of the proposition in the scope of the evidential in a direct/inferential evidential context, but not in a reportative context.
    [Show full text]
  • Tense, Modals and Modal Subordination in Korean
    Copyright by Jinung Kim 2012 The Dissertation Committee for Jinung Kim Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Korean Evidentials in Discourse Committee: Nicholas Asher, Supervisor David Beaver Sun-Hee Lee Toshiyuki Ogihara Stephen Wechsler Korean Evidentials in Discourse by Jinung Kim, B.A., M.A., M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2012 Dedication To my family. Acknowledgements First and foremost, I would like to express my gratitude to my supervisor, Dr. Nicholas Asher for his invaluable advice, encouragement and patience. He has enlightened me through his wide knowledge and deep intuition from the preliminary to concluding level. This research has benefited from the many discussion meetings we have had and his commentary on my work. I would like to thank the other members of my committee, David Beaver, Stephen Wechsler, Sun- Hee Lee and Toshiyuki Ogihara. I am indebted to them for the effort that they took time to read and comment on the implication of my dissertation. I am especially grateful to David for helpful discussions and sincere support for completing my work. Without his advice and understanding, it would have been impossible for me to finish this study. This dissertation has benefited from many discussions with friends including Sang-hoon Park, Tony Wright, Eric McCready, Cheng-fu Chen, So-Hee Kim and Ji-hwan Kim. I thank Sang-hoon Park and Eric McCready for helpful comments on some of the work in this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • On Context Dependence III Modal Constructions
    On Context Dependence III Modal Constructions Anette Frank and Hans Kamp Rank Xerox Research Centre and University of Stuttgart This paper investigates a new representation format for dynamic discourse in DRT, where contextual dynamics is modeled in terms of update conditions. This new representation format is motivated by the study of context depen­ dence in modal constructions, in particular by serious problems besetting ear­ lier approaches to modality and modal subordination in DRT. We present an alternative DRT analysis that provides a unified analysis of relative modality and modal subordination, and which accounts for a wider range of data as regards modal subordination relative to negation and graded modal context.s. 1. Introduction One of the distinguishing features of DRT is its focus on representational aspects of meaning. Another important characteristic of the theory is the in­ sight that the meaning of sentences cannot be determined by truth conditional semantics proper. A pervasive feature of natural language semant.ics is that. it is essentially dependent on (material introduced within) the previous discourse context; DRT and FCS were t.he firstsema .ntic theories that made this specific kind of context dependence formally precise (Kamp(1981), IIeim(1982)). To account for anaphoric binding in donkey sentcnces (la), DRT and FSC a.ssign the conditional a 'dynamic' analysis , which is 'internal' inasmnch as it concerns the relation between the antecedent and the scope. It is 'exter­ nally static' in that the dynamically ' augmented ' contexts of the antecedent and consequent are ' invisible from the outside ', i.e., from the vantage point of the conditional as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • A Modest Proposal for the Meaning of Imperatives*
    Version of September 1, 2015. A modest proposal for the meaning of imperatives* Kai von Fintel Sabine Iatridou 1 Introduction In this paper, we attempt to make a modest contribution to the understanding of the meaning of imperatives. By “imperative” we mean a verb form that is typically used to convey directive force, and is not typically used in subordinate roles (distinct from infinitives and subjunctives; but see later). Now, one might think that there is an obvious answer to the question of what imperatives mean: imperatives are used to impose an obligation on the addressee to make the prejacent of the imperative true. A speaker who utters (1) Read this book! is trying to get the addressee to take on the obligation to make it true that the addressee reads this book. If the imperative is successful, the addressee now has the obligation to read this book. So, it’s unsurprising that “command” is often taken to be the basic function of the imperative verb. In fact, in many languages, even the (folk-)linguistic name of the form is based on a verb that means “command”: • Romance imperative from Latin imperare, “to command” • Greek prostaktiki from prostazo, “to command” • Turkish emir kipi, “command” (noun) • Slovenian velelnik from veleti, “to command” • Hebrew civuy, “to command” • Albanian urdherore from me urdheru, “to command” • Arabic fi’l ?amr, “to command” * This paper has taken far too long to write. We have talked about and taught this material many times and many places. It all started with a seminar on imperatives we taught at MIT in 2008.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Not' As Inherently Modal
    1 ‘Not’ as inherently modal Yasuhiro Sasahira University of Wisconsin-Madison 1 Some background: Negation vs. affirmation The standard theoretical assumption on the semantics of negation is that it is a truth-functional operator, a function from propositions to propositions defined as follows: (1) || ¬p|| = true if and only if ||p|| = false. Negation, as defined in (1), is a one-place propositional operator that takes a proposition p as its argument and yields another proposition that denotes the complement of what is denoted by p. However, simple as it may look, negative sentences in natural language do not always denote what is expected by the semantics defined in (1). As has long been noted and discussed, negative sentences are more discourse-linked than their affirmative counterparts, in the sense that a negative sentence is interpreted as if its affirmative counterpart is already in the discourse. 2 To see this, consider the following examples: 3 (2) a. My wife isn’t pregnant. b. My wife is pregnant. If (2a) is uttered in a context where the listener doesn’t know whether or not the speaker’s wife is pregnant, the listener’s likely response will be: “Oh, I didn’t 1 For helpful comments and discussion, I’d like to thank the audience of WIGL5. 2 See Horn (1989) for extensive discussion and a comprehensive overview of this topic. 3 These examples are cited from Givon (1978). LSO Working Papers in Linguistics 7: Proceedings of WIGL 2007, 145-159. © 2007 by Yasuhiro Sasahira. 145 Yasuhiro Sasahira know that she was supposed to be pregnant” or something along this line.
    [Show full text]