Parts of a Whole: Distributivity As a Bridge Between Aspect and Measurement”

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Parts of a Whole: Distributivity As a Bridge Between Aspect and Measurement” Algebraic Semantics - Linguistic Applications of Mereology Script to the lecture series Lucas Champollion University of Tübingen [email protected] Tübingen, Germany Apr >E-?=, ?=>? Preface Expressions like ’John and Mary’ or ’the water in my cup’ intuitively involve reference to col- lections of individuals or substances. The parthood relation between these collections and their components is not modeled in standard formal semantics of natural language (Montague >FDA; Heim and Kratzer >FFE), but it plays central stage in what is known as mereological or algebraic semantics (Link >FFE; Krifka >FFE; Landman ?===). In this mini-lecture series I will present in- troductions into algebraic semantics and selected applications involving plural, mass reference, measurement, aspect, and distributivity. I will discuss issues involving ontology and philosophy of language, and how these issues interact with semantic theory depending on how they are resolved. This script is subject to change. Comments welcome. Lucas Champollion, Tübingen, April >Cth, ?=>? ? Contents > Mereology: Concepts and axioms B >.> Introduction . B >.? Mereology . C >.?.> Parthood . C >.?.? Sums....................................... E >.@ Mereology and set theory . >= >.A Selected literature . >= ? Nouns: count, plural, mass >? ?.> Algebraic closure and the plural . >? ?.? Singular count nouns . >B ?.@ Mass nouns and atomicity . >C @ Homomorphisms and measurement >E @.> Introduction . >E @.? Trace functions and intervals . >F @.@ Measure functions and degrees . ?= @.A Unit functions . ?> @.B The measurement puzzle . ?? A Verbs and events ?B A.> Introduction . ?B A.? Thematic roles . ?C A.@ Lexical cumulativity . ?E A.A Aspectual composition . ?F @ B Distributivity and scope @? B.> Introduction . @? B.? Lexical and phrasal distributivity . @? B.?.> Reformulating the D operator . @A B.?.? The leakage problem . @B B.@ Atomic and nonatomic distributivity . @C A Lecture > Mereology: Concepts and axioms >.> Introduction • Mereology: the study of parthood in philosophy and mathematical logic • Mereology can be axiomatized in a way that gives rise to algebraic structures (sets with binary operations deVned on them) Figure >.>: An algebraic structure a ⊕ b ⊕ c a ⊕ b a ⊕ c b ⊕ c a b c • Algebraic semantics: the branch of formal semantics that uses algebraic structures and parthood relations to model various phenomena B >.? Mereology >.?.> Parthood • Basic motivation (Link >FFE): entailment relation between collections and their members (>) a. John and Mary sleep. ) John sleeps and Mary sleeps. b. The water in my cup evaporated. ) The water at the bottom of my cup evaporated. • Basic relation ≤ (parthood) – no consensus on what exactly it expresses • Table >.> gives a few interpretations of the relation ≤ in algebraic semanitcs Table >.>: Examples of unstructured parthood Whole Part some horses a subset of them a quantity of water a portion of it John, Mary and Bill John some jumping events a subset of them a running event from A to B its part from A halfway towards B a temporal interval its initial half a spatial interval its northern half • All these are instances of unstructured parthood (arbitrary slices). • Individuals, spatial and temporal intervals, events, and situations are each generally taken to be mereologies (Link >FFE; Krifka >FFE). • Various types of individuals: – Ordinary individuals: John, my cup, this page – Mass individuals: the water in my cup – Plural individuals: John and Mary, the boys, the letters on this page – Group individuals: the Senate, the Beatles, the boys as a group C Table >.?: Examples of structured parthood from Simons (>FED) Whole Part a (certain) man his head a (certain) tree its trunk a house its roof a mountain its summit a battle its opening shot an insect’s life its larval stage a novel its Vrst chapter • Link (>FE@) on reductionist considerations: they are “quite alien to the purpose of logically analyzing the inference structure of natural language . [o]ur guide in ontological matters has to be language itself” • But reductionism is still possible, just at a later stage. • Compare this with structured parthood (Simons >FED; Fine >FFF; Varzi ?=>=) in Table >.? (cognitively salient parts) • In algebraic semantics one usually models only unstructured parthood. • This contrasts with lexical semantics, which concerns itself with structured parthood (e.g. Cruse >FEC). • Mereology started as an alternative to set theory; instead of 2 and ⊆ there is only ≤. • In algebraic semantics, mereology and set theory coexist. • The most common axiom system is classical extensional mereology (CEM). • The order-theoretic axiomatization of CEM starts with ≤ as a partial order: (?) Axiom of reWexivity 8x[x ≤ x] (Everything is part of itself.) D (@) Axiom of transitivity 8x8y8z[x ≤ y ^ y ≤ z ! x ≤ z] (Any part of any part of a thing is itself part of that thing.) (A) Axiom of antisymmetry 8x8y[x ≤ y ^ y ≤ x ! x = y] (Two distinct things cannot both be part of each other.) • The proper-part relation restricts parthood to nonequal pairs: (B) DeVnition: Proper part x < y =def x ≤ y ^ x 6= y (A proper part of a thing is a part of it that is distinct from it.) • To talk about objects which share parts, we deVne overlap: (C) DeVnition: Overlap x ◦ y =def 9z[z ≤ x ^ z ≤ y] (Two things overlap if and only if they have a part in common.) >.?.? Sums • Pretheoretically, sums are that which you get when you put several parts together. • The classical deVnition of sum in (D) is due to Tarski (>F?F). There are others. (D) DeVnition: Sum sum(x; P ) =def 8y[P (y) ! y ≤ x] ^ 8z[z ≤ x ! 9z0[P (z0) ^ z ◦ z0]] (A sum of a set P is a thing that consists of everything in P and whose parts each overlap with something in P . “sum(x; P )” means “x is a sum of (the things in) P ”.) Exercise >.> Prove the following facts! (E) Fact 8x8y[x ≤ y ! x ◦ y] (Parthood is a special case of overlap.) E (F) Fact 8x[sum(x; fxg)] (A singleton set sums up to its only member.) The answers to this and all following exercises are in the Appendix. • In CEM, two things composed of the same parts are identical: (>=) Axiom of uniqueness of sums 8P [P 6= ? ! 9!z sum(z; P )] (Every nonempty set has a unique sum.) • Based on the sum relation, we can deVne some useful operations: (>>) DeVnition: Generalized sum For any nonempty set P , its sum L P is deVned as ιz sum(z; P ): (The sum of a set P is the thing which contains every element of P and whose parts each overlap with an element of P .) (>?) DeVnition: Binary sum x ⊕ y is deVned as Lfx; yg. (>@) DeVnition: Generalized pointwise sum L For any nonempty n-place relation Rn, its sum Rn is deVned as the tuple hz1; : : : ; zni such that each zi is equal to L fxij9x1; : : : ; xi−1; xi+1; : : : ; xn[R(x1; : : : ; xn)]g: (The sum of a relation R is the pointwise sum of its positions.) • Two applications of sum in linguistics are conjoined terms and deVnite descriptions. – For Sharvy (>FE=), the water = L water J K – For Link (>FE@), John and Mary = j ⊕ m J K • Another application: natural kinds as sums; e.g. the kind potato is L potato. • But this needs to be reVned for uninstantiated kinds such as dodo and phlogiston. One answer: kinds are individual concepts of sums (Chierchia >FFEb). See Carlson (>FDD) and Pearson (?==F) on kinds more generally. F >.@ Mereology and set theory • Models of CEM (or “mereologies”) are essentially isomorphic to complete Boolean algebras with the bottom element removed, or equivalently complete semilattices with their bottom element removed (Tarski >F@B; Pontow and Schubert ?==C). • CEM parthood is very similar to the subset relation (Table >.@). • Example: the powerset of a given set, with the empty set removed, and with the partial order given by the subset relation. Exercise >.? If the empty set was not removed, would we still have a mereology? Why (not)? Table >.@: Correspondences between CEM and set theory Property CEM Set theory > ReWexivity x ≤ x x ⊆ x ? Transitivity x ≤ y ^ y ≤ z ! x ≤ z x ⊆ y ^ y ⊆ z ! x ⊆ z @ Antisymmetry x ≤ y ^ y ≤ x ! x = y x ⊆ y ^ y ⊆ x ! x = y A InterdeVnability x ≤ y $ x ⊕ y = y x ⊆ y $ x [ y = y S B Unique sum/union P 6= ? ! 9!z sum(z; P ) 9!z z = P C Associativity x ⊕ (y ⊕ z) = (x ⊕ y) ⊕ z x [ (y [ z) = (x [ y) [ z D Commutativity x ⊕ y = y ⊕ x x [ y = y [ x E Idempotence x ⊕ x = x x [ x = x x < y ! F Unique separation x ⊆ y ! 9!z[z = y − x] 9!z[x ⊕ z = y ^ :x ◦ z] >.A Selected literature – Textbooks: * Mathematical foundations: Partee, ter Meulen, and Wall (>FF=) * Montague-style formal semantics: Heim and Kratzer (>FFE) * Algebraic semantics: Landman (>FF>) – Books on algebraic semantics: Link (>FFE); Landman (?===) >= – Seminal articles on algebraic semantics: Landman (>FFC); Krifka (>FFE) – Mereology surveys: Simons (>FED); Casati and Varzi (>FFF); Varzi (?=>=) – My dissertation: Champollion (?=>=) >> Lecture ? Nouns: count, plural, mass ?.> Algebraic closure and the plural • Link (>FE@) has proposed algebraic closure as underlying the meaning of the plural. (>) a. John is a boy. b. Bill is a boy. c. ) John and Bill are boys. • Algebraic closure closes any predicate (or set) P under sum formation: (?) DeVnition: Algebraic closure (Link >FE@) The algebraic closure ∗P of a set P is deVned as fx j 9P 0 ⊆ P [x = L P 0]g. (This is the set that contains any sum of things taken from P .) • Link translates the argument in (>) as follows: (@) boy(j) ^ boy(b) ) ∗boy(j ⊕ b) • This argument is valid. Proof: From boy(j) ^ boy(b) it follows that fj; bg ⊆ boy. Hence 9P 0 ⊆ boy[j ⊕ b = L P 0],
Recommended publications
  • Anaphoric Reference to Propositions
    ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Todd Nathaniel Snider December 2017 c 2017 Todd Nathaniel Snider ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS Todd Nathaniel Snider, Ph.D. Cornell University 2017 Just as pronouns like she and he make anaphoric reference to individuals, English words like that and so can be used to refer anaphorically to a proposition introduced in a discourse: That’s true; She told me so. Much has been written about individual anaphora, but less attention has been paid to propositional anaphora. This dissertation is a com- prehensive examination of propositional anaphora, which I argue behaves like anaphora in other domains, is conditioned by semantic factors, and is not conditioned by purely syntactic factors nor by the at-issue status of a proposition. I begin by introducing the concepts of anaphora and propositions, and then I discuss the various words of English which can have this function: this, that, it, which, so, as, and the null complement anaphor. I then compare anaphora to propositions with anaphora in other domains, including individual, temporal, and modal anaphora. I show that the same features which are characteristic of these other domains are exhibited by proposi- tional anaphora as well. I then present data on a wide variety of syntactic constructions—including sub- clausal, monoclausal, multiclausal, and multisentential constructions—noting which li- cense anaphoric reference to propositions. On the basis of this expanded empirical do- main, I argue that anaphoric reference to a proposition is licensed not by any syntactic category or movement but rather by the operators which take propositions as arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modal Future
    The Modal Future A theory of future-directed thought and talk Cambridge University Press Fabrizio Cariani Contents Preface page vii Conventions and abbreviations xi Introduction xii PART ONE BACKGROUND 1 1 The symmetric paradigm 3 1.1 The symmetric paradigm 3 1.2 Symmetric semantics 4 1.3 The symmetric paradigm contextualized 10 1.4 Temporal ontology and symmetric semantics 14 Appendix to chapter 1: the logic Kt 17 2 Symmetric semantics in an asymmetric world 19 2.1 Branching metaphysics 20 2.2 Branching models 21 2.3 Symmetric semantics on branching models 27 2.4 Ways of being an Ockhamist 32 2.5 Interpreting branching models 32 PART TWO THE ROAD TO SELECTION SEMANTICS 39 3 The modal challenge 41 3.1 What is a modal? 42 3.2 The argument from common morphology 44 3.3 The argument from present-directed uses 45 3.4 The argument from modal subordination 48 3.5 The argument from acquaintance inferences 52 iii iv Contents 3.6 Morals and distinctions 54 4 Modality without quantification 56 4.1 Quantificational theories 57 4.2 Universal analyses and retrospective evaluations 59 4.3 Prior’s bet objection 60 4.4 The zero credence problem 61 4.5 Scope with negation 64 4.6 Homogeneity 66 4.7 Neg-raising to the rescue? 69 5 Basic selection semantics 73 5.1 Selection semantics: a first look 74 5.2 Basic versions of selection semantics 78 5.3 Notions of validity: a primer 81 5.4 Logical features of selection semantics 82 5.5 Solving the zero credence problem 83 5.6 Modal subordination 85 5.7 Present-directed uses of will 86 5.8 Revisiting the acquaintance
    [Show full text]
  • Counterfactuals and Modality
    Linguistics and Philosophy https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-020-09313-8 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Counterfactuals and modality Gabriel Greenberg1 Accepted: 9 October 2020 © Springer Nature B.V. 2021 Abstract This essay calls attention to a set of linguistic interactions between counterfactual conditionals, on one hand, and possibility modals like could have and might have,on the other. These data present a challenge to the popular variably strict semantics for counterfactual conditionals. Instead, they support a version of the strict conditional semantics in which counterfactuals and possibility modals share a unified quantifica- tional domain. I’ll argue that pragmatic explanations of this evidence are not available to the variable analysis. And putative counterexamples to the unified strict analysis, on careful inspection, in fact support it. Ultimately, the semantics of conditionals and modals must be linked together more closely than has sometimes been recognized, and a unified strict semantics for conditionals and modals is the only way to fully achieve this. Keywords Counterfactuals · Conditionals · Modality · Discourse This essay calls attention to a set of linguistic interactions between counterfactual conditionals, on one hand, and possibility modals like could have and might have,on the other. These data present a challenge to the popular variably strict semantics for counterfactual conditionals. Instead, they support a version of the strict conditional semantics in which counterfactuals and possibility modals share a unified quantifica- tional domain. I’ll argue that pragmatic explanations of this evidence are not available to the variable analysis. And putative counterexamples to the unified strict analysis, on careful inspection, in fact support it. Ultimately, the semantics of conditionals and modals must be linked together more closely than has sometimes been recognized, and a unified strict semantics for conditionals and modals is the only way to fully achieve this.
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit Arguments, Paychecks and Variable-Free Semantics*
    Proceedings of SALT 21: 155-175, 2011 Implicit Arguments, Paychecks and Variable-Free Semantics* Walter A. Pedersen McGill University Abstract The present paper focuses on a particular class of implicit arguments – what have been termed anaphoric implicit arguments (AIAs) – and presents an account of AIAs in the variable-free (VF) framework introduced in Jacobson 1999, 2000. In particular, it is demonstrated how AIAs allow „paycheck‟ (E-type) readings, an observation that goes back to Dowty 1981; it is shown that these readings follow naturally in the VF framework. The VF account is then compared and contrasted with some alternatives, including Condoravdi & Gawron‟s (1996) proposal that AIAs pattern with definite descriptions. Keywords: implicit arguments, paycheck pronouns, E-type anaphora, variable-free semantics 1 Introduction The topic of the present study is anaphoric implicit arguments (AIAs), and their incorporation into the variable-free framework proposed in Jacobson 1999, 2000. Special attention is paid to the E-type readings of AIAs first observed in Dowty 1981, and it is demonstrated how such readings follow naturally in a variable-free framework. The paper is organized as follows: §2 discusses the data relating to implicit arguments, and in particular to AIAs; §3 reviews the variable-free framework laid out in Jacobson 1999, 2000; §4 shows how anaphoric implicit arguments can be introduced into this framework; §5 compares the variable-free proposal to various alternatives, including the proposal in Condoravdi & Gawron 1996 that AIAs pattern with definite descriptions rather than pronouns. 2 Implicit Arguments The term „implicit argument‟ is a broad one, and the phenomenon to be discussed here has gone under different names in the literature; this multiplicity of labels reflects both *Thank you to Brendan Gillon, Ed Stabler, Ed Keenan, Jessica Rett, Pauline Jacobson, Chris Barker, Barbara Partee, and the UCLA linguistics department for their helpful comments and suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bound Variable Hierarchy and Donkey Anaphora in Mandarin Chinese
    The Bound Variable Hierarchy and Donkey Anaphora in Mandarin Chinese Haihua Pan and Yan Jiang City University of Hong Kong / London University Cheng and Huang (1996) argue that both unselective binding and E-type pro- noun strategies are necessary for the interpretation of natural language sentences and claim that there exists a correspondence between two sentence types in Chinese and the two strategies, namely that the interpretation of the “wh … wh” construction (which they call “bare conditional”) employs the unselective binding strategy, while the ruguo ‘if’ and dou ‘all’ conditionals use the E-type pronoun strategy. They also suggest that there is a complementary distribution between bare conditionals and ruguo/dou conditionals in the sense that the lat- ter allows all the NP forms, e.g. (empty) pronouns and definite NPs, except for wh-phrases in their consequent clauses, and can even have a consequent clause with no anaphoric NP in it, while the former permits only the same wh-phrase appearing in both the antecedent clause and the consequent clause. Although we agree with Cheng and Huang on the necessity of the two strategies in natural language interpretation, we see apparent exceptions to the correspondence between sentence types and interpretation strategies and the complementary distribution between wh-phrases and other NPs in bare conditionals and ruguo/dou conditionals. We think that the claimed correspondence and comple- mentary distribution are the default or preferred patterns, or a special case of a more general picture, namely that (i) bare conditionals prefer the unselective binding strategy and the ruguo ‘if’ and dou ‘all’ conditionals, the E-type pronoun strategy; and (ii) wh-phrases are more suitable for being a bound variable, and pronouns are more suitable for being the E-type pronoun.
    [Show full text]
  • The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Technical Reports (CIS) Department of Computer & Information Science January 1997 The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense Matthew Stone University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/cis_reports Recommended Citation Matthew Stone, "The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense", . January 1997. University of Pennsylvania Department of Computer and Information Science Technical Report No. MS-CIS-97-09. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/cis_reports/177 For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense Abstract In modal subordination, a modal sentence is interpreted relative to a hypothetical scenario introduced in an earlier sentence. In this paper, I argue that this phenomenon reflects the fact that the interpretation of modals is an ANAPHORIC process, precisely analogous to the anaphoric interpretation of tense. Modal morphemes introduce alternative scenarios as entities into the discourse model; their interpretation depends on evoking scenarios for described, reference and speech points, and relating them to one another. Although this account formalizes anaphoric connections using dynamic semantics, it invokes a novel and direct encoding of scenarios as ordinary, static objects (competing analyses take modal referents to be inherently dynamic objects, unlike the referents of pronouns and tenses). The result is a simpler proposal with
    [Show full text]
  • Diagnosing Modality in Predictive Expressions
    June 18, 2013 Diagnosing Modality in Predictive Expressions Peter Klecha University of Chicago Abstract This short paper argues that predictive expressions (will, gonna) are modals. In section 1 I provide three empirical arguments for a treatment of predictive expressions as modals: i) they behave like modals in that they can occur in overt and covert conditionals in a way that non-modal operators cannot; ii) they have morphologi- cal variants which show displacement behaviors, i.e., nonveridicality; iii) like modals, they obviate the personal experience requirement on predicates of personal taste. In section 2 I specifically rebut arguments by Kissine (2008) that will is not a modal. In section 3 I conclude. In this paper I argue that what I call predictive expressions (PEs) in English, words like will and gonna, are modal operators rather than simple temporal operators. (1) a. Ryan will leave for California tomorrow. b. Ryan is gonna leave for California tomorrow. The distinction between temporal and modal corresponds to a question about what the nature of the future is, or at least, how language treats the nature of the future: as a linear continuation of time, no different from the past (what can be called the Linear Future Hypothesis, sometimes called Ockhamist), or as a range of possible paths, a potentially infinite set of open possibilities (what can be called the Open Future Hypothesis, sometimes called Peircian); see, e.g., Kaufmann et al. (2006) . On the former view, there is a single actual world, even if we can never have the knowledge needed to distinguish it from other worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidentiality and Mood: Grammatical Expressions of Epistemic Modality in Bulgarian
    Evidentiality and mood: Grammatical expressions of epistemic modality in Bulgarian DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements o the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Anastasia Smirnova, M.A. Graduate Program in Linguistics The Ohio State University 2011 Dissertation Committee: Brian Joseph, co-advisor Judith Tonhauser, co-advisor Craige Roberts Copyright by Anastasia Smirnova 2011 ABSTRACT This dissertation is a case study of two grammatical categories, evidentiality and mood. I argue that evidentiality and mood are grammatical expressions of epistemic modality and have an epistemic modal component as part of their meanings. While the empirical foundation for this work is data from Bulgarian, my analysis has a number of empirical and theoretical consequences for the previous work on evidentiality and mood in the formal semantics literature. Evidentiality is traditionally analyzed as a grammatical category that encodes information sources (Aikhenvald 2004). I show that the Bulgarian evidential has richer meaning: not only does it express information source, but also it has a temporal and a modal component. With respect to the information source, the Bulgarian evidential is compatible with a variety of evidential meanings, i.e. direct, inferential, and reportative, as long as the speaker has concrete perceivable evidence (as opposed to evidence based on a mental activity). With respect to epistemic commitment, the construction has different felicity conditions depending on the context: the speaker must be committed to the truth of the proposition in the scope of the evidential in a direct/inferential evidential context, but not in a reportative context.
    [Show full text]
  • Tense, Modals and Modal Subordination in Korean
    Copyright by Jinung Kim 2012 The Dissertation Committee for Jinung Kim Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Korean Evidentials in Discourse Committee: Nicholas Asher, Supervisor David Beaver Sun-Hee Lee Toshiyuki Ogihara Stephen Wechsler Korean Evidentials in Discourse by Jinung Kim, B.A., M.A., M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2012 Dedication To my family. Acknowledgements First and foremost, I would like to express my gratitude to my supervisor, Dr. Nicholas Asher for his invaluable advice, encouragement and patience. He has enlightened me through his wide knowledge and deep intuition from the preliminary to concluding level. This research has benefited from the many discussion meetings we have had and his commentary on my work. I would like to thank the other members of my committee, David Beaver, Stephen Wechsler, Sun- Hee Lee and Toshiyuki Ogihara. I am indebted to them for the effort that they took time to read and comment on the implication of my dissertation. I am especially grateful to David for helpful discussions and sincere support for completing my work. Without his advice and understanding, it would have been impossible for me to finish this study. This dissertation has benefited from many discussions with friends including Sang-hoon Park, Tony Wright, Eric McCready, Cheng-fu Chen, So-Hee Kim and Ji-hwan Kim. I thank Sang-hoon Park and Eric McCready for helpful comments on some of the work in this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • On Context Dependence III Modal Constructions
    On Context Dependence III Modal Constructions Anette Frank and Hans Kamp Rank Xerox Research Centre and University of Stuttgart This paper investigates a new representation format for dynamic discourse in DRT, where contextual dynamics is modeled in terms of update conditions. This new representation format is motivated by the study of context depen­ dence in modal constructions, in particular by serious problems besetting ear­ lier approaches to modality and modal subordination in DRT. We present an alternative DRT analysis that provides a unified analysis of relative modality and modal subordination, and which accounts for a wider range of data as regards modal subordination relative to negation and graded modal context.s. 1. Introduction One of the distinguishing features of DRT is its focus on representational aspects of meaning. Another important characteristic of the theory is the in­ sight that the meaning of sentences cannot be determined by truth conditional semantics proper. A pervasive feature of natural language semant.ics is that. it is essentially dependent on (material introduced within) the previous discourse context; DRT and FCS were t.he firstsema .ntic theories that made this specific kind of context dependence formally precise (Kamp(1981), IIeim(1982)). To account for anaphoric binding in donkey sentcnces (la), DRT and FSC a.ssign the conditional a 'dynamic' analysis , which is 'internal' inasmnch as it concerns the relation between the antecedent and the scope. It is 'exter­ nally static' in that the dynamically ' augmented ' contexts of the antecedent and consequent are ' invisible from the outside ', i.e., from the vantage point of the conditional as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • A Modest Proposal for the Meaning of Imperatives*
    Version of September 1, 2015. A modest proposal for the meaning of imperatives* Kai von Fintel Sabine Iatridou 1 Introduction In this paper, we attempt to make a modest contribution to the understanding of the meaning of imperatives. By “imperative” we mean a verb form that is typically used to convey directive force, and is not typically used in subordinate roles (distinct from infinitives and subjunctives; but see later). Now, one might think that there is an obvious answer to the question of what imperatives mean: imperatives are used to impose an obligation on the addressee to make the prejacent of the imperative true. A speaker who utters (1) Read this book! is trying to get the addressee to take on the obligation to make it true that the addressee reads this book. If the imperative is successful, the addressee now has the obligation to read this book. So, it’s unsurprising that “command” is often taken to be the basic function of the imperative verb. In fact, in many languages, even the (folk-)linguistic name of the form is based on a verb that means “command”: • Romance imperative from Latin imperare, “to command” • Greek prostaktiki from prostazo, “to command” • Turkish emir kipi, “command” (noun) • Slovenian velelnik from veleti, “to command” • Hebrew civuy, “to command” • Albanian urdherore from me urdheru, “to command” • Arabic fi’l ?amr, “to command” * This paper has taken far too long to write. We have talked about and taught this material many times and many places. It all started with a seminar on imperatives we taught at MIT in 2008.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Not' As Inherently Modal
    1 ‘Not’ as inherently modal Yasuhiro Sasahira University of Wisconsin-Madison 1 Some background: Negation vs. affirmation The standard theoretical assumption on the semantics of negation is that it is a truth-functional operator, a function from propositions to propositions defined as follows: (1) || ¬p|| = true if and only if ||p|| = false. Negation, as defined in (1), is a one-place propositional operator that takes a proposition p as its argument and yields another proposition that denotes the complement of what is denoted by p. However, simple as it may look, negative sentences in natural language do not always denote what is expected by the semantics defined in (1). As has long been noted and discussed, negative sentences are more discourse-linked than their affirmative counterparts, in the sense that a negative sentence is interpreted as if its affirmative counterpart is already in the discourse. 2 To see this, consider the following examples: 3 (2) a. My wife isn’t pregnant. b. My wife is pregnant. If (2a) is uttered in a context where the listener doesn’t know whether or not the speaker’s wife is pregnant, the listener’s likely response will be: “Oh, I didn’t 1 For helpful comments and discussion, I’d like to thank the audience of WIGL5. 2 See Horn (1989) for extensive discussion and a comprehensive overview of this topic. 3 These examples are cited from Givon (1978). LSO Working Papers in Linguistics 7: Proceedings of WIGL 2007, 145-159. © 2007 by Yasuhiro Sasahira. 145 Yasuhiro Sasahira know that she was supposed to be pregnant” or something along this line.
    [Show full text]