"Nothing" As "Not-Being": Some Literary Contexts That Bear on Plato and on Parmenides

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 8-1977 "Nothing" as "Not-Being": Some Literary Contexts that Bear on Plato and on Parmenides Alexander P.D. Mourelatos University of Texas at Austin, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Mourelatos, Alexander P.D., ""Nothing" as "Not-Being": Some Literary Contexts that Bear on Plato and on Parmenides" (1977). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 230. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/230 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. "Nothing" as "Not-Being": Some Literary Contexts That Bear on Plato and on Parmenides Alexander P. o. Mourelatos The university of Texas at Austin (August 1977) !O It has often been noticed that Plato, and before him Parmenides, 1 assimilates "what is not" C't"O µ� �v) to •nothing" CµY)5&v or o6o&v) Given that the central use of " nothing" has important ties with the exis- tential quantifier ("Nothing is here" = "It is not the case that there is anything here"), it has widely been assumed that contexts that document this assimilation also count as evidence that both within them and in cognate ontological contexts the relevant sense of 11being11 or "to be" is that of existence. That this assumption is not to be granted easily, has been 2 • compellingly argued by G. E. L. owen. His main concern was to show that the assumption is particularly mischievous in the interpretation of the Sophist, where he found it totally unwarranted. My own concern is to attack the assumption on a broader plane. "Nothing" in English has uses that do not depend on a tie with the existential quantifier. So too in cl or d l d xi 1 Greek: in� eh 'ou en can be g osse as •what does not e st , 1 but it can also be glossed as "not a something, " or in owen's fornmlation,•1what is not anything, what not-in-any way is': a subject with all the being knocked out 3 of it and so unidentifiable, no subject." In effect, the assimilation of "what is not• to •nothing" may--in certain contexts-- work in the opposite - -. 2 I di.rection: not from "nothing" to " non""'.being" in the sense of non-existence; rather from "non-being" as negative specification or negative determination To to •nothing" as the extreme of negativity or indeterminacy. convey the sense involved in this reverse assimilation I borrow owen's suggestive translation •not-being" for me �, a rendering which makes use of an in­ complete participle, rather than t.he complete gerund, of the verb "to be." In the main Section of this paper I examine a certain "characterizing" use of meden/ouden and medeis/oudeis in pre-Platonic non-philosophical contexts. The passages discussed and analyzed offer cle.ar and suggestive illustrations of the assimilation of "nothing" or "nobody" to •not-being." In the concluding Section I explore connections between that use and philo­ sophical concepts,with particular reference to Plato's doctrine of degrees of reality. I To make alternatives clear I begin with an exploration of the relevant English uses. The semanti c spectrums of "nothing" and of the personal form •nobody" are, of course, wider than logic books might suggest. Only two uses concern us, and these can be quickly formulated if we take the expres­ sions "nob()dy"and "nothing"as answers to two types of questions. (a) 1. Who is in the house now?--Nobody. 2. What is in the box?--Nothing. (b) 1. Who is the gentle�arl dver there?--Nobody. 2. What is that shape over there?--Nothing. The one-word cu:iswers in exchanges (a) are clearly equivalent to more per­ spicuous expanded paraphrases of the form •There is no ! in !!1" where K can 3 be replaced by an appropriate classifier or natural-kind expression and L can be replaced by a locative word or phrase. This is the use of "nobodytc or "nothing" that is closest to the negative existential quantified ex- pressions in formal logic, "'(3x)Ex For suggestive convenience, in spite of some infelicity--since (a)-type sentences are tensed, whereas the exis­ tential quantifier imports no time implications--! shall call (a) the "exis­ tential" use of "nobody" and •nothing." It is not as easy to give a single perspicuous paraphrase of the one­ word answers in type (b). The respondent may intend to dispute the inter­ rogator's presupposition that there actually is something, let alone a gentleman or a shape, in the region referred to. In that case, the question receives in effect a type (a) answer. A distinct type (b) is defined in the case in which the respondent does not dispute the interrogator's existential presupposition. He says, roughly: "I notice who you are referring to, but he's nobody,• or "I notice what you're referring to, but it's nothing." In that sort of case the respondent intends to convey one of two possible messages: (i) The object (person or thing) referred to is "of no account": it (he or she) lies outside the interlocutors• scope of interests, in what ­ ever way and however broadly these interests are defined by the inter­ locutors' current endeavor. thus the snobbish respondent might say "He's nobody" with reference to someone of inferior status;or "It's nothing" may be the reassuring response of a doctor to a patient concerning certain physical changes in the patient's body they have both observed1 or it might be the response of a laboratory assistant to a student with reference to a speck they can both see through 4 the mii romiop ec or of oAe limteAer at a l eitu re to aAothert rho iA uired ab o ut a p oi A ta d e b g t h e mpeanera A d r h ii hh e fir m tlimteAer mimm e d. Uhe other pommible memmaue im: (ii) U h e obje t ref err e d t o i m A et r e m e l g p o o rtro A o u tto r red ui e d .. .- -1 \ --11 L - ('r - m e iim eA o f t h e n i A di t pr ma fa i ieappearm t o b e . It im e teAmi elg deprired of he Ao mal haraiterimtiim of hat niA d t mo i t i A 'barel g' or 'hardlb e g'iall edta m f o r ex mple i A ex h Auem ( a)A d (b)t a 'ueAtlem A' or a 'mhape.' 'Ae i A mo e aptlg m e n of rhat it 'im Aot' rather th A of rhat 'it im. • IA the limitiAu iamet to bo r r oAe of the defiAitioAm iA oebmter'm hird Ner IAte AatioAal DiitioAa g t it im 'momethiAu hat im iharaiterized bg utter bmeAie of dete AatioA: erfeit iAdimtiAuuimhableAemm.' et me refer to (b) A either of itm o m b-tgpem am the •ihara teriziAu' ume of 'Ao odg' or 'Aoth Au.' hat Aderliem t p e (a)t the eximteAtial umet im a o Aiep tioA of AoA- eiA u am e pt Aemm: I mear h the houme Ad fiAd hat it im rai At: or I o eA the box Ad fiAd hat it im emptg. hat Aderliem t e (b)t he ihar- a i t e r i z i Au u m e t i m a ioAie pt ioA o f A o A - b e i A u to r p o p e r l g A o t - b e i A ua t m ( i ) ( of mt AdiAu (almomt iA that juridiial meAme iA rhi h mo eoAe mag hare •Ao mtA dA u' A a parti ular iourt Ad iame- or (ii) priratioA or a t t eA u a t i o A . umt am the eximteAtial ume of 'Aobodg' or 'AothiAu' iorre- m p o A d mt o h e e x i m t e A ta i l u m e of ' t o e t 1 1 t h e i h a r a t e r i z i A u m e m o r r em poA d t o i o p u l a t i r e' t o b e . 'h e p e r m o Ar h o i m ' A o b o d g 'A t h e m e A m eh a t h e ' d o e mA o t i o A t •1 i m i e t a i A l gA o f i i t i r eo r h o A - e x i m t e Ae t A t i t g cl i n e r i m e for the thiAu that im depreiated am a 'AothiAu.A Ae iuht ob jet at thim oiAt hat here im Ao Aeed o m o t a iop- ulatire oAmt u tioA iA he Aalgmim of he ihara teriziAu ume.
Recommended publications
  • Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman
    17 Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman The Alpha Course, a well‐known evangelical Christian programme, advertises itself with posters displaying the words THE MEANING OF LIFE IS_________, followed by the invitation ‘Fill in the blanks at alpha.org’. Followers of the course will discover that ‘Men and women were created to live in a relationship with God’, and that ‘without that relationship there will always be a hunger, an emptiness, a feeling that something is missing’.1 We all have that need because we are all sinners, we are told, and the truth which will fill the need is that Jesus Christ died to save us from our sins. Not all Christian or other religious views about the meaning of life are as simplistic as this, but they typically share the assumptions that the meaning of life is to be found in some belief whose truth we need to recognize, and that this is a belief about the purpose for which we exist. A further implication is that this purpose is the purpose intended by the God who created us, and that if we fail to identify and live in accordance with that purpose, our lives will lack meaning. The assumption is echoed in the question many humanists will have encountered: if you don’t believe in a God, what’s the point of it all? And many people who don’t share the answer still accept the legitimacy of the question – ‘What is the meaning of life?’ – and assume that what we need is a correct belief, religious or non‐religious, which will fill the blank in the sentence ‘The meaning of life is …’.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View
    R ené Descartes (1596-1650) is generally regarded as the “father of modern philosophy.” He stands as one of the most important figures in Western intellectual history. His work in mathematics and his writings on science proved to be foundational for further development in these fields. Our understanding of “scientific method” can be traced back to the work of Francis Bacon and to Descartes’ Discourse on Method. His groundbreaking approach to philosophy in his Meditations on First Philosophy determine the course of subsequent philosophy. The very problems with which much of modern philosophy has been primarily concerned arise only as a consequence of Descartes’thought. Descartes’ philosophy must be understood in the context of his times. The Medieval world was in the process of disintegration. The authoritarianism that had dominated the Medieval period was called into question by the rise of the Protestant revolt and advances in the development of science. Martin Luther’s emphasis that salvation was a matter of “faith” and not “works” undermined papal authority in asserting that each individual has a channel to God. The Copernican revolution undermined the authority of the Catholic Church in directly contradicting the established church doctrine of a geocentric universe. The rise of the sciences directly challenged the Church and seemed to put science and religion in opposition. A mathematician and scientist as well as a devout Catholic, Descartes was concerned primarily with establishing certain foundations for science and philosophy, and yet also with bridging the gap between the “new science” and religion. Descartes’ Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View 1) Descartes’ disbelief in authoritarianism: Descartes’ belief that all individuals possess the “natural light of reason,” the belief that each individual has the capacity for the discovery of truth, undermined Roman Catholic authoritarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absurd Author(S): Thomas Nagel Reviewed Work(S): Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Absurd Author(s): Thomas Nagel Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 68, No. 20, Sixty-Eighth Annual Meeting of the American Philosophical Association Eastern Division (Oct. 21, 1971), pp. 716-727 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024942 . Accessed: 19/08/2012 01:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org 7i6 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY The formerstands as valid only if we can findcriteria for assigning a differentlogical formto 'allegedly' than to 'compulsively'.In this case, the criteriaexist: 'compulsively'is a predicate, 'allegedly' a sentenceadverb. But in countless other cases, counterexamplesare not so easily dismissed.Such an example, bearing on the inference in question, is Otto closed the door partway ThereforeOtto closed the door It seems clear to me that betterdata are needed beforeprogress can be made in this area; we need much more refinedlinguistic classificationsof adverbial constructionsthan are presentlyavail- able, ifour evidenceconcerning validity is to be good enough to per- mit a richerlogical theory.In the meantime,Montague's account stands: thereis no reason to thinka morerefined theory, if it can be produced, should not be obtainable within the frameworkhe has given us.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absurdity of Life Without God (Craig)
    The Absurdity of Life Without God (Craig) 1. Life Without God is Meaningless: William Lane Craig argues that, if there is no God, then life itself lacks meaning, value, and purpose. The primary motive of this conclusion is the idea that, without God, there is no immortality. And, without immortality, then each and every one of us is doomed to die. Life is, as Craig notes, merely a brief transition out of oblivion and back into oblivion. Not only that, but the human race—indeed, the entire universe—is doomed to die. In 5 billion years, the Sun will engulf the Earth in a fiery death. Billions of years after that, the entire universe, as it expands and cools, will one day be nothing but a litter of dead, cold stars, forever getting further and further from one another, travelling forever into the dark recesses of dead, cold, lifeless space. (1) Life is Meaningless: If we are all doomed to die, then nothing really matters. No one’s life has any ULTIMATE significance. Our advancements to expand human knowledge, to alleviate human suffering, to learn to live in peace will all eventually be meaningless. Craig claims that, because human beings are doomed to be here for only a short time, astronomically speaking, we are no more significant than a “swarm of mosquitos”; and man, “because he ends in nothing, he IS nothing”. But, he says, even if we could live forever, life would still be meaningless. It is not MERE eternity that gives life meaning. There must be something that GIVES it meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Everything
    The Theory of Everything R. B. Laughlin* and David Pines†‡§ *Department of Physics, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305; †Institute for Complex Adaptive Matter, University of California Office of the President, Oakland, CA 94607; ‡Science and Technology Center for Superconductivity, University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801; and §Los Alamos Neutron Science Center Division, Los Alamos National Laboratory, Los Alamos, NM 87545 Contributed by David Pines, November 18, 1999 We discuss recent developments in our understanding of matter, we have learned why atoms have the size they do, why chemical broadly construed, and their implications for contemporary re- bonds have the length and strength they do, why solid matter has search in fundamental physics. the elastic properties it does, why some things are transparent while others reflect or absorb light (6). With a little more he Theory of Everything is a term for the ultimate theory of experimental input for guidance it is even possible to predict Tthe universe—a set of equations capable of describing all atomic conformations of small molecules, simple chemical re- phenomena that have been observed, or that will ever be action rates, structural phase transitions, ferromagnetism, and observed (1). It is the modern incarnation of the reductionist sometimes even superconducting transition temperatures (7). ideal of the ancient Greeks, an approach to the natural world that But the schemes for approximating are not first-principles has been fabulously successful in bettering the lot of mankind deductions but are rather art keyed to experiment, and thus tend and continues in many people’s minds to be the central paradigm to be the least reliable precisely when reliability is most needed, of physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind
    Part Two Philosophy of Mind 9781350067301_txt_prf.indd 179 21-08-2018 11:42:33 9781350067301_txt_prf.indd 180 21-08-2018 11:42:33 6 Spinoza’s Two Claims about the Mind-Body Relation Alison Peterman Introduction How is a particular mind related to its body?1 There are many ways to understand this question, and many different answers for those different ways. Spinoza makes a number of claims about this relationship, all of which are independently interesting. But it is not clear that they are compatible. In this chapter, I would like to focus on two of those claims, and to argue that although Spinoza sometimes run these two claims together, in fact he does not succeed in making them compatible with one another. I suggest that the illusion that they are compatible comes from an equivocation between two ways of using the phrase “insofar as” [quatenus], and that this type of equivocation runs deep in Spinoza’s metaphysics. Those two claims are: (1) Parallelism: the mind is causally and structurally linked to other minds in the same way that its body is linked to other bodies; (2) Idea-of: the mind is the idea of its body; or, the body is the object [objectum] of its mind. In focusing on these two, I will ignore some of those other interesting things that Spinoza writes about the mind-body relationship. For example, I will for the most part ignore his account of it in the earlier Short Treatise, where he claims that love constitutes the union of the mind with the body.2 But I will also ignore another of Spinoza’s commitments that might look more relevant: that the mind and the body are “one and the same thing, understood in two different ways” (E2p7s).
    [Show full text]
  • Nothing's Lost Forever
    Nothing’s Lost Forever EDMUND RICHARDSON I saw something that only I could see, because of my astonish- ing ability to see such things: Souls were rising, from the earth far below, souls of the dead, of people who had perished, from famine, from war, from the plague, and they floated up, like skydivers in reverse, limbs all akimbo, wheeling and spinning. And the souls of these departed joined hands, clasped ankles, and formed a web, a great net of souls, and the souls were three-atom oxygen molecules, of the stuff of ozone, and the outer rim absorbed them, and was repaired. Nothing’s lost for- ever. In this world, there’s a kind of painful progress. Longing for what we’ve left behind, and dreaming ahead. At least I think that’s so. —Tony Kushner, Angels in America On March 27, 1888, as the light was fading, several reporters knocked—softly and suspiciously—at the door of 166 Madison Avenue, New York. They were wel- comed by one of the city’s most distinguished lawyers, Luther Marsh, “looking almost precisely as all New York was used to seeing him at the bar—a short, well-built, kindly man, with a square, firm face, enclosed between white side whiskers.”1 Marsh ushered them upstairs into his study, where for decades the city’s elite had done business amongst the law-books. That night, the familiar room was unrecog- nizable. Dozens of strange new paintings were propped on the shelves, stood against the chairs and tables, and fixed to every spare inch of wall-space.
    [Show full text]
  • Man Is Condemned to Be Free by Jean-Paul Sartre from the Lecture, “Existentialism Is a Humanism” (1946) Translated by Philip Mairet (1948)
    Man is Condemned to Be Free by Jean-Paul Sartre from the lecture, “Existentialism is a Humanism” (1946) translated by Philip Mairet (1948) Existence Precedes Essence … we can begin by saying that existentialism, in our sense of the word, is a doctrine that does render human life possible; a doctrine, also, which affirms that every truth and every action imply both an environment and a human subjectivity. … [A]t bottom, what is alarming in the doctrine that I am about to try to explain to you is – is it not? – that it confronts man with a possibility of choice. To verify this, let us review the whole question upon the strictly philosophic level. What, then, is this that we call existentialism? … The question is only complicated because there are two kinds of existentialists. There are, on the one hand, the Christians, amongst whom I shall name Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, both professed Catholics; and on the other the existential atheists, amongst whom we must place Heidegger as well as the French existentialists and myself. What they have in common is simply the fact that they believe that existence comes before essence – or, if you will, that we must begin from the subjective. What exactly do we mean by that? If one considers an article of manufacture as, for example, a book or a paper- knife – one sees that it has been made by an artisan who had a conception of it; and he has paid attention, equally, to the conception of a paper-knife and to the pre-existent technique of production which is a part of that conception and is, at bottom, a formula.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind and the Problem of Free Will in the Light of Quantum Mechanics
    Philosophy of Mind and the Problem of Free Will in the Light of Quantum Mechanics. Henry P. Stapp Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory University of California Berkeley, California 94720 Abstract Arguments pertaining to the mind-brain connection and to the physical effectiveness of our conscious choices have been presented in two recent books, one by John Searle, the other by Jaegwon Kim. These arguments are examined, and it is explained how the encountered difficulties arise from a defective understanding and application of a pertinent part of contemporary science, namely quantum mechanics. The principled quantum uncertainties entering at the microscopic levels of brain processing cannot be confined to the micro level, but percolate up to the macroscopic regime. To cope with the conflict between the resulting macroscopic indefiniteness and the definiteness of our conscious experiences, orthodox quantum mechanics introduces the idea of agent-generated probing actions, each of which specifies a definite set of alternative possible empirically/experientially distinguishable outcomes. Quantum theory then introduces the mathematical concept of randomness to describe the probabilities of the various alternative possible outcomes of the chosen probing action. But the agent-generated choice of which probing action to perform is not governed by any known law or rule, statistical or otherwise. This causal gap provides a logical opening, and indeed a logical need, for the entry into the dynamical structure of nature of a process that goes beyond the currently understood quantum mechanical statistical generalization of the deterministic laws of classical physics. The well-known quantum Zeno effect can then be exploited to provide a natural process that establishes a causal psychophysical link within the complex structure consisting of a stream of conscious experiences and certain macroscopic classical features of a quantum mechanically described brain.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton
    The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton Chapter 4: Is Life What You Make It? Submitted by Paul Lussier ‘Recommended Readings’ for the Aspen/Yale Conference 2007 The following is an excerpt from: Terry Eagleton, The Meaning of Life. Oxford University Press (2007), pp.135-175 The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton Chapter 4: Is Life What You Make It? So far, we have looked more at meaning than at life. Yet the word 'life' is every bit as problematic as the word 'meaning', and it is not hard to see why. For surely the reason why we cannot talk about the meaning of life is that there is no such thing as life? Are we not, as Wittgenstein might say, bewitched here by our grammar, which can generate the word 'life' in the singular just as it can the word 'tomato'? Perhaps we have the word 'life' only because our language is intrinsically reifying, 'Essence is expressed by grammar', as Wittgenstein remarks.24 How on earth could everything that falls under the heading of human life, from childbirth to clog dancing, be thought to stack up to a single meaning? Isn't this exactly the delusion of the paranoiac, for whom everything is supposed to be ominously resonant of everything else, bound together in an oppressively translucent whole? Or, if you prefer, the delusion of philosophy, which as Freud mischievously commented is the nearest thing to paranoia? Not even an individual life adds up to a unified whole. It is true that some people see their lives as forming an elegant narrative all the way from Introduction to Epilogue, but not everyone views themselves like this.
    [Show full text]
  • Stop Asking Why There's Anything
    Erkenn (2012) 77:51–63 DOI 10.1007/s10670-011-9312-0 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Stop Asking Why There’s Anything Stephen Maitzen Received: 28 May 2010 / Accepted: 16 July 2011 / Published online: 14 August 2011 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Abstract Why is there anything, rather than nothing at all? This question often serves as a debating tactic used by theists to attack naturalism. Many people apparently regard the question—couched in such stark, general terms—as too profound for natural science to answer. It is unanswerable by science, I argue, not because it’s profound or because science is superficial but because the question, as it stands, is ill-posed and hence has no answer in the first place. In any form in which it is well-posed, it has an answer that naturalism can in principle provide. The question therefore gives the foes of naturalism none of the ammunition that many on both sides of the debate think it does. 1 Introduction Why is there anything, rather than nothing at all? Leibniz called it ‘‘the first question that should rightly be asked’’ (1714, p. 527), and Heidegger called it not only ‘‘the fundamental question of metaphysics’’ but ‘‘the first of all questions’’ (1959, p. 1). Nowadays the question more commonly comes up as a debating tactic used by theists to attack naturalism. Many people apparently regard the question—couched in such completely general terms—as too profound for natural science to answer. It is unanswerable by science, I’ll argue, not because it’s profound or because science is superficial but because the question, as it stands, is defective, ill-posed, and hence has no answer.
    [Show full text]