Similarity As an Extension of Symmetry and Its Application to Superrationality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Similarity As an Extension of Symmetry and Its Application to Superrationality Similarity as an Extension of Symmetry and its Application to Superrationality 1 Carlos Maximiliano Senci http://orcid.org/0000-0001-9131-3843 1IIESS-Conicet and Departamento de Humanidades-UNS Bahía Blanca, Buenos Aires Argentina [email protected] 2 Fernando Abel Tohmé https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2988-4519 2IMABB-Conicet and Dept. of Economics-UNS Bahía Blanca , Buenos Aires Argentina [email protected] Article Info CDD: 501 Received:05.11.2020; Revised: 01.02.2021; Accepted: 05.03.2021 https://doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2021.V44N2.CF Keywords: Game theory Symmetry Similarity Superrationality Abstract: In this paper we present a concept of similarity in games, on which to ground alternative solution concepts, some of which differ from the classical notions in the field. Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 44, n. 2, pp. 128-156, Apr.-Jun. 2021. Similarity as an Extension of Symmetry and its... 129 In order to do this we impose a constraint on players’ be- liefs that amounts to a variant of the well-known symmetry principle in classical bargaining theory. We show how this similarity relation helps to identify different Nash equilibria in games, and how these “similar Nash equilibria” can be extended to non-symmetric games. While the notion is nor- mative, it is nonetheless inspired by phenomena in which similarities between players lead to outcomes detected in behavioral studies. We study the strategic properties of the concept of similarity and discuss its relationships with Hofstadter’ notion of superrationality. 1 Introduction As we know, Game Theory studies situations of inter- action between intentional agents. By ‘interactive sit- uations’ we understand those in which more than one player intervenes, and in which the potential results are the product of the joint actions (simultaneous or not) of several players. Game theory proposes solution con- cepts, that is, rules indicating the choices to be made by the players in order to obtain results that satisfy some theoretical criteria of appropriateness. Solution concepts yield a set of strategy profiles (eventually the empty set) for each finite strategic game. In this sense, Game Theory is normative, since it prescribes solu- tions that disregard the actual decision-making pro- cesses carried out by flesh and blood humans. It rather provides solutions to be chosen by idealized agents. Nash Equilibrium (from now on denoted NE; Nash, 1950; Myerson, 1991, p. 105) is the most important so- lution concept in Non-Cooperative Game Theory. In- formally, a NE is a profile of strategies such that none of the players has incentives to change her strategy, given the strategies chosen by the other players. It is well known that the epistemic conditions required by the NE of the players are quite restrictive. In par- Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 44, n. 2, pp. 128-156, Apr.-Jun. 2021. Carlos Maximiliano Senci 130 ticular, in the simplest case of two players, the NE requires rationality and mutual knowledge of rational- ity, i.e. both players must be rational and know that they are rational (Aumann and Brandenburger, 1995). These players are clearly idealized agents. In many ubiquitous situations the NE does not pro- vide satisfactory solutions. The typical case is the Prisoner’s Dilemma, but there are other well-studied games, such as the Stag Hunt or Hi-Lo (Colman and Gold, 2018), in which there are payoff-dominant results that the standard theory cannot justify. An outcome is dominant if all players get larger payoffs than with any other results. In many games in which there are multiple NE, nothing indicates which one should be chosen. Then, it becomes necessary to arbitrate solutions that refine the concept of NE. The NE refinement program has gen- erated a large literature (see, in particular, Harsanyi and Selten, 1988). The attempt to refine concepts of strategic rationality does not seem to have found a general solution like the one sought by philosophers, able to accommodate all the contingencies that arise in relation to the justification of any solution. In the same way, it does not seem that they have been able to accommodate in the vast array of anomalies that arise from the experimental results. Behavioral Game Theory can be seen as a body of solution concepts cor- responding to those results, going beyond the limits of rational choice (Ross, 2014). But this proliferation of solution concepts, while an indication of the impetuous development of Behavioral Game Theory, also testifies to a certain failure, partial at least, to provide a uni- fied framework (Tohmé et. al., 2017). In this search of alternative solutions, sometimes it is convenient to assume that players are somewhat similar to each other. A similarity relation could refer Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 44, n. 2, pp. 128-156, Apr.-Jun. 2021. Similarity as an Extension of Symmetry and its... 131 to normative aspects, such as rationality. But empir- ical aspects without normative content may be also relevant. Such is the case if we think about the abili- ties or qualities of the players. This leads to solutions based on the strategic depth of players (k-level rea- soning; Camerer et al., 2004), their level of conformity to norms (Bernheim, 1994), or their levels of inequity aversion (Fehr and Schmidt, 1999), among others. The similarity between the players reduces the uncertainty experienced by each of them when facing players she considers similar to her. This behavioral phenomenon has been documented in a series of recent studies, in which different similarity primings had effects on co- ordination or cooperation (eg, Fischer, 2009; Di Guida and Devetag, 2013; Mussweiler and Ockenfels, 2013 ; Chierchia and Coricelli, 2015; Rubinstein and Salant, 2016). There are different attempts to capture similarity relationships between players. In this paper we pro- vide a formal representation of the concept of similar- ity, showing how it helps to identify different NE in games. We also show how these ‘similar Nash equi- libria’ can be extended to non-symmetric games, and under additional restrictions we will show how to ex- tend it to superrationality. Superrationality was proposed by Hofstadter (1983, 1985) to account for the cooperative solution in the Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) (Flood and Dresher 1952). It is one of the alternative solutions that have been ad- vanced according to which players could do better than the mutual defection in the PD. Proponents of the co- operative outcome usually enrich the description of the PD with an additional assumption according to which the players are somehow similar. Most notably, one of those lines of thought focuses on symmetry as the basic argument for cooperation, rooted in the alleged ability of the players to recognize that they are facing Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 44, n. 2, pp. 128-156, Apr.-Jun. 2021. Carlos Maximiliano Senci 132 the same situation and that their strategies are the same (Davis, 1977; Campbell, 1989; Rapoport, 1960). Hofstadter devised the idea of superrational thinkers as a solution for symmetric dilemmatic situations, that is, one in which the incentives are the same for all the players. Superrational thinkers reason their way to the solution by applying a meta-rationality norm implying that every thinker knows what the rational answer is, and knows that every other player knows this fact. So, superrational thinking is not a simple property of an individual but a relational property: “You need to depend not just on their being rational, but on their depending on every- one else to be rational, and on their de- pending on everyone to depend on every- one to be rational-and so on. A group of reasoners in this relationship to each other I call superrational. Superrational thinkers, by recursive definition, include in their cal- culations the fact that they are in a group of superrational thinkers.” (Hofstadter, 1985, p. 748). Since superrational thinking applies to symmetric situations, the (unique) rational solution identified at which each player arrives through her/his own rational reasoning is mirrored by the one found by any other player. Then, superrationality indicates that the solu- tion to each symmetric game is a profile in the diagonal of the game matrix. In Hofstadter’s words: “Any number of ideal rational thinkers faced with the same situation and undergoing similar throes of reasoning agony will nec- essarily come up with the identical answer eventually, so long as reasoning alone is the Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 44, n. 2, pp. 128-156, Apr.-Jun. 2021. Similarity as an Extension of Symmetry and its... 133 ultimate justification for their conclusion. Otherwise reasoning would be subjective, not objective as arithmetic is. A conclu- sion reached by reasoning would be a mat- ter of preference, not of necessity. Now some people may believe this of reason- ing, but rational thinkers understand that a valid argument must be universally com- pelling, otherwise it is simply not a valid argument.” (Hofstadter, 1985, p. 746). Following the lead of Hofstadter, who circumscribed superrationality to symmetric games, we start by con- sidering normal form symmetric games to propose a definition of similarity that extends to non-symmetric games. As a first step we need to find a way to ‘sym- metrize’ non-symmetric games, since in these games it is not clear what could mean ‘to make the same choice’. In order to do this we impose a constraint on players’ beliefs that amounts to a variant of the well-known symmetry principle in classical bargaining theory. While we do not allow players to perceive oth- ers as similar with regards to arbitrary features (such as beauty, trustworthiness, race, etc.) we assume them to reason on the basis of their strategic features.
Recommended publications
  • Game Theory Lecture Notes
    Game Theory: Penn State Math 486 Lecture Notes Version 2.1.1 Christopher Griffin « 2010-2021 Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 3.0 United States License With Major Contributions By: James Fan George Kesidis and Other Contributions By: Arlan Stutler Sarthak Shah Contents List of Figuresv Preface xi 1. Using These Notes xi 2. An Overview of Game Theory xi Chapter 1. Probability Theory and Games Against the House1 1. Probability1 2. Random Variables and Expected Values6 3. Conditional Probability8 4. The Monty Hall Problem 11 Chapter 2. Game Trees and Extensive Form 15 1. Graphs and Trees 15 2. Game Trees with Complete Information and No Chance 18 3. Game Trees with Incomplete Information 22 4. Games of Chance 24 5. Pay-off Functions and Equilibria 26 Chapter 3. Normal and Strategic Form Games and Matrices 37 1. Normal and Strategic Form 37 2. Strategic Form Games 38 3. Review of Basic Matrix Properties 40 4. Special Matrices and Vectors 42 5. Strategy Vectors and Matrix Games 43 Chapter 4. Saddle Points, Mixed Strategies and the Minimax Theorem 45 1. Saddle Points 45 2. Zero-Sum Games without Saddle Points 48 3. Mixed Strategies 50 4. Mixed Strategies in Matrix Games 53 5. Dominated Strategies and Nash Equilibria 54 6. The Minimax Theorem 59 7. Finding Nash Equilibria in Simple Games 64 8. A Note on Nash Equilibria in General 66 Chapter 5. An Introduction to Optimization and the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker Conditions 69 1. A General Maximization Formulation 70 2. Some Geometry for Optimization 72 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Generation Based Analysis Model for Non-Cooperative Games
    Generation Based Analysis Model for Non-Cooperative Games Soham Banerjee Department of Computer Engineering International Institute of Information Technology Pune, India Email: [email protected] Abstract—In most real-world games, participating agents are to its optimal solution which forms a good base for comparison all perfectly rational and choose the most optimal set of actions for the model’s performance. possible; but that is not always the case while dealing with complex games. This paper proposes a model for analysing II. PROPOSED MODEL the possible set of moves and their outcome; where not all participating agents are perfectly rational. The model proposed is The proposed model works within the framework of pre- used on three games, Prisoners’ Dilemma, Platonia Dilemma and determined assumptions; but may be altered or expanded to Guess 2 of the Average. All the three games have fundamental 3 other games as well. differences in their action space and outcome payoffs, making them good examples for analysis with the proposed model. • All agents have infinite memory - this means that an agent Index Terms—game theory, analysis model, deterministic remembers all previous iterations of the game along with games, superrationality, prisoners’ dilemma, platonia dilemma the observation as well as the result. • All the games have a well-defined pure strategy Nash Equilibrium. I. INTRODUCTION • The number of participating agents is always known. • All the games are non co-operative - this indicates that the While selecting appropriate actions to perform in a game, agents will only form an alliance if it is self-enforcing. a common assumption made is that, all other participating agents (co-operative or not) will make the most optimal move Each participating agent is said to posses a Generation of possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Stackelberg Reasoning in Symmetric Games: an Experimental
    Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental ANGOR UNIVERSITY replication and extension Pulford, B.D.; Colman, A.M.; Lawrence, C.L. PeerJ DOI: 10.7717/peerj.263 PRIFYSGOL BANGOR / B Published: 25/02/2014 Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Cyswllt i'r cyhoeddiad / Link to publication Dyfyniad o'r fersiwn a gyhoeddwyd / Citation for published version (APA): Pulford, B. D., Colman, A. M., & Lawrence, C. L. (2014). Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental replication and extension. PeerJ, 263. https://doi.org/10.7717/peerj.263 Hawliau Cyffredinol / General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. 23. Sep. 2021 Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental replication and extension Briony D. Pulford1, Andrew M. Colman1 and Catherine L. Lawrence2 1 School of Psychology, University of Leicester, Leicester, UK 2 School of Psychology, Bangor University, Bangor, UK ABSTRACT In common interest games in which players are motivated to coordinate their strate- gies to achieve a jointly optimal outcome, orthodox game theory provides no general reason or justification for choosing the required strategies.
    [Show full text]
  • Villager's Dilemma
    Villager's dilemma Beihang He Advertisement 0702,Department of Arts and Communication, Zhejiang University City College No.51 Huzhou Street Hangzhou Zhejiang, 310015 Tel: 13906539819 E-mail: [email protected] 1 Abstract:With deeper study of the Game Theory, some conditions of Prisoner’s Dilemma is no longer suitable of games in real life. So we try to develop a new model-Villager’s Dilemma which has more realistic conditions to stimulate the process of game. It is emphasize that Prisoner’s Dilemma is an exception which is lack of universality and the importance of rules in the game. And it puts forward that to let the rule maker take part in the game and specifies game players can stop the game as they like. This essay describes the basic model, the villager’s dilemma (VD) and put some extended use of it, and points out the importance of rules and the effect it has on the result of the game. It briefly describes the disadvantage of Prisoner’s Dilemma and advantage Villager’s Dilemma has. It summarizes the premise and scope of application of Villager’s Dilemma, and provides theory foundation for making rules for game and forecast of the future of the game. 2 1. Basic Model In the basic model, the villager’s dilemma (VD) is presented as follows: Three villagers who have the same physical strength and a robber who has two and a half times physical strength as three villagers are living in the same village. In other words, three villagers has to act together to defeat the robber who is stronger than anyone of them.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games
    Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games Topics: terminology and notations (OR 1.7), games and solutions (OR 1.1-1.3), rationality and bounded rationality (OR 1.4-1.6), formalities (OR 2.1), best-response (OR 2.2), Nash equilibrium (OR 2.2), 2 2 examples × (OR 2.3), existence of Nash equilibrium (OR 2.4), mixed strategy Nash equilibrium (OR 3.1, 3.2), strictly competitive games (OR 2.5), evolution- ary stability (OR 3.4), rationalizability (OR 4.1), dominance (OR 4.2, 4.3), trembling hand perfection (OR 12.5). Terminology and notations (OR 1.7) Sets For R, ∈ ≥ ⇐⇒ ≥ for all . and ⇐⇒ ≥ for all and some . ⇐⇒ for all . Preferences is a binary relation on some set of alternatives R. % ⊆ From % we derive two other relations on : — strict performance relation and not  ⇐⇒ % % — indifference relation and ∼ ⇐⇒ % % Utility representation % is said to be — complete if , or . ∀ ∈ % % — transitive if , and then . ∀ ∈ % % % % can be presented by a utility function only if it is complete and transitive (rational). A function : R is a utility function representing if → % ∀ ∈ () () % ⇐⇒ ≥ % is said to be — continuous (preferences cannot jump...) if for any sequence of pairs () with ,and and , . { }∞=1 % → → % — (strictly) quasi-concave if for any the upper counter set ∈ { ∈ : is (strictly) convex. % } These guarantee the existence of continuous well-behaved utility function representation. Profiles Let be a the set of players. — () or simply () is a profile - a collection of values of some variable,∈ one for each player. — () or simply is the list of elements of the profile = ∈ { } − () for all players except . ∈ — ( ) is a list and an element ,whichistheprofile () .
    [Show full text]
  • ECONS 424 – STRATEGY and GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 – Answer Key
    ECONS 424 – STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 – Answer key Exercise #1. Hawk-Dove game. Consider the following payoff matrix representing the Hawk-Dove game. Intuitively, Players 1 and 2 compete for a resource, each of them choosing to display an aggressive posture (hawk) or a passive attitude (dove). Assume that payoff > 0 denotes the value that both players assign to the resource, and > 0 is the cost of fighting, which only occurs if they are both aggressive by playing hawk in the top left-hand cell of the matrix. Player 2 Hawk Dove Hawk , , 0 2 2 − − Player 1 Dove 0, , 2 2 a) Show that if < , the game is strategically equivalent to a Prisoner’s Dilemma game. b) The Hawk-Dove game commonly assumes that the value of the resource is less than the cost of a fight, i.e., > > 0. Find the set of pure strategy Nash equilibria. Answer: Part (a) • When Player 2 (in columns) chooses Hawk (in the left-hand column), Player 1 (in rows) receives a positive payoff of by paying Hawk, which is higher than his payoff of zero from playing Dove. − Therefore, for Player2 1 Hawk is a best response to Player 2 playing Hawk. Similarly, when Player 2 chooses Dove (in the right-hand column), Player 1 receives a payoff of by playing Hawk, which is higher than his payoff from choosing Dove, ; entailing that Hawk is Player 1’s best response to Player 2 choosing Dove. Therefore, Player 1 chooses2 Hawk as his best response to all of Player 2’s strategies, implying that Hawk is a strictly dominant strategy for Player 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Eszter Babarczy: Community Based Trust on the Internet
    PTE BTK Nyelvtudományi Doktori Iskola Kommunikáció Doktori Program Babarczy Eszter: Community Based Trust on the Internet Doktori értekezés Témavezető: Horányi Özséb egyetemi tanár 2011. 1 Community-based trust on the internet Tartalom Introduction .................................................................................................................................................. 3 II. A very brief history of the internet ........................................................................................................... 9 Early Days ............................................................................................................................................... 11 Mainstream internet .............................................................................................................................. 12 The internet of social software .............................................................................................................. 15 III Early trust related problems and solutions ............................................................................................ 20 Trading .................................................................................................................................................... 20 Risks of and trust in content ....................................................................................................................... 22 UGC and its discontents: Wikipedia ......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Game Theory I
    Introduction to Game Theory I Presented To: 2014 Summer REU Penn State Department of Mathematics Presented By: Christopher Griffin [email protected] 1/34 Types of Game Theory GAME THEORY Classical Game Combinatorial Dynamic Game Evolutionary Other Topics in Theory Game Theory Theory Game Theory Game Theory No time, doesn't contain differential equations Notion of time, may contain differential equations Games with finite or Games with no Games with time. Modeling population Experimental / infinite strategy space, chance. dynamics under Behavioral Game but no time. Games with motion or competition Theory Generally two player a dynamic component. Games with probability strategic games Modeling the evolution Voting Theory (either induced by the played on boards. Examples: of strategies in a player or the game). Optimal play in a dog population. Examples: Moves change the fight. Chasing your Determining why Games with coalitions structure of a game brother across a room. Examples: altruism is present in or negotiations. board. The evolution of human society. behaviors in a group of Examples: Examples: animals. Determining if there's Poker, Strategic Chess, Checkers, Go, a fair voting system. Military Decision Nim. Equilibrium of human Making, Negotiations. behavior in social networks. 2/34 Games Against the House The games we often see on television fall into this category. TV Game Shows (that do not pit players against each other in knowledge tests) often require a single player (who is, in a sense, playing against The House) to make a decision that will affect only his life. Prize is Behind: 1 2 3 Choose Door: 1 2 3 1 2 3 1 2 3 Switch: Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Win/Lose: L W W L W L W L L W W L W L W L L W The Monty Hall Problem Other games against the house: • Blackjack • The Price is Right 3/34 Assumptions of Multi-Player Games 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Quant-Ph/0702167V2 30 Jan 2013
    Quantum Game Theory Based on the Schmidt Decomposition Tsubasa Ichikawa∗ and Izumi Tsutsui† Institute of Particle and Nuclear Studies High Energy Accelerator Research Organization (KEK) Tsukuba 305-0801, Japan and Taksu Cheon‡ Laboratory of Physics Kochi University of Technology Tosa Yamada, Kochi 782-8502, Japan Abstract We present a novel formulation of quantum game theory based on the Schmidt de- composition, which has the merit that the entanglement of quantum strategies is manifestly quantified. We apply this formulation to 2-player, 2-strategy symmetric games and obtain a complete set of quantum Nash equilibria. Apart from those available with the maximal entanglement, these quantum Nash equilibria are ex- arXiv:quant-ph/0702167v2 30 Jan 2013 tensions of the Nash equilibria in classical game theory. The phase structure of the equilibria is determined for all values of entanglement, and thereby the possibility of resolving the dilemmas by entanglement in the game of Chicken, the Battle of the Sexes, the Prisoners’ Dilemma, and the Stag Hunt, is examined. We find that entanglement transforms these dilemmas with each other but cannot resolve them, except in the Stag Hunt game where the dilemma can be alleviated to a certain degree. ∗ email: [email protected] † email: [email protected] ‡ email: [email protected] 1. Introduction Quantum game theory, which is a theory of games with quantum strategies, has been attracting much attention among quantum physicists and economists in recent years [1, 2] (for a review, see [2, 3, 4]). There are basically two reasons for this. One is that quantum game theory provides a general basis to treat the quantum information processing and quantum communication in which plural actors try to achieve their objectives such as the increase in communication efficiency and security [5, 6].
    [Show full text]
  • An Optimal Single-Winner Preferential Voting System Based on Game Theory∗
    An Optimal Single-Winner Preferential Voting System Based on Game Theory∗ Ronald L. Rivest and Emily Shen Abstract • The election winner is determined by a random- ized method, based for example on the use of We present an optimal single-winner preferential vot- ten-sided dice, that picks outcome x with prob- ing system, called the \GT method" because of its in- ability p∗(x). If there is a Condorcet winner x, teresting use of symmetric two-person zero-sum game then p∗(x) = 1, and no dice are needed. We theory to determine the winner. Game theory is not also briefly discuss a deterministic variant of GT, used to describe voting as a multi-player game be- which we call GTD. tween voters, but rather to define when one voting system is better than another one. The cast ballots The GT system, essentially by definition, is opti- determine the payoff matrix, and optimal play corre- mal: no other voting system can produce election sponds to picking winners optimally. outcomes that are liked better by the voters, on the The GT method is quite simple and elegant, and average, than those of the GT system. We also look works as follows: at whether the GT system has several standard prop- erties, such as monotonicity, consistency, etc. • Voters cast ballots listing their rank-order pref- The GT system is not only theoretically interest- erences of the alternatives. ing and optimal, but simple to use in practice; it is probably easier to implement than, say, IRV. We feel • The margin matrix M is computed so that for that it can be recommended for practical use.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding and Preventing Tacit Collusion Among Telecommunication Operators Patrick Maillé, Maurizio Naldi, Bruno Tuffin
    Understanding and Preventing Tacit Collusion among Telecommunication Operators Patrick Maillé, Maurizio Naldi, Bruno Tuffin To cite this version: Patrick Maillé, Maurizio Naldi, Bruno Tuffin. Understanding and Preventing Tacit Collusion among Telecommunication Operators. NET-COOP, Nov 2009, Eindhoven, Netherlands. hal-00447030 HAL Id: hal-00447030 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00447030 Submitted on 14 Jan 2010 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Understanding and Preventing Tacit Collusion among Telecommunication Operators Patrick Maill´e1, Maurizio Naldi2, and Bruno Tuffin3 1 Institut Telecom, Telecom Bretagne 2 rue de la Chˆataigneraie CS 17607 35576 Cesson S´evign´e Cedex, France [email protected] 2 Universit`a di Roma Tor Vergata Dip. di Informatica Sistemi Produzione Via del Politecnico 1 00133 Roma, Italy [email protected] 3 INRIA Rennes - Bretagne Atlantique Campus universitaire de Beaulieu 35042 Rennes Cedex, France [email protected] Abstract. Modeling the competition among telecommunication opera- tors (or providers) as a repeated game may explain why tacit collusion to maintain high charging prices can be observed. Such outcomes clearly do not benefit the users, nor do they provide operators with incentives to improve the network quality of service to outperform their competi- tors.
    [Show full text]
  • Nash Equilibria in the Response Strategy of Correlated Games A
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Nash Equilibria in the Response Strategy of Correlated Games A. D. Correia & H. T. C. Stoof In nature and society, problems that arise when diferent interests are difcult to reconcile are Received: 3 October 2018 modeled in game theory. While most applications assume that the players make decisions based only Accepted: 23 November 2018 on the payof matrix, a more detailed modeling is necessary if we also want to consider the infuence Published: xx xx xxxx of correlations on the decisions of the players. We therefore extend here the existing framework of correlated strategies by giving the players the freedom to respond to the instructions of the correlation device by probabilistically following or not following its suggestions. This creates a new type of games that we call “correlated games”. The associated response strategies that can solve these games turn out to have a rich structure of Nash equilibria that goes beyond the correlated equilibrium and pure or mixed-strategy solutions and also gives better payofs in certain cases. We here determine these Nash equilibria for all possible correlated Snowdrift games and we fnd these solutions to be describable by Ising models in thermal equilibrium. We believe that our approach paves the way to a study of correlations in games that uncovers the existence of interesting underlying interaction mechanisms, without compromising the independence of the players. Game theory1 has been used as a powerful tool to model problems from diverse research areas. In particular, evo- lutionary game theory2 aims to explain why some strategies are selected in the presence of many players3.
    [Show full text]