Stackelberg Reasoning in Mixed-Motive Games: an Experimental Investigation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stackelberg Reasoning in Mixed-Motive Games: an Experimental Investigation Journal of Economic Psychology 19 (1998) 279±293 Stackelberg reasoning in mixed-motive games: An experimental investigation Andrew M. Colman *, Jonathan A. Stirk Department of Psychology, University of Leicester, Leicester LE1 7RH, UK Received 26 June 1996; accepted 5 May 1997 Abstract The Stackelberg heuristic is a simulation heuristic in which a player optimizes against best- reply counterstrategies, and a game is Stackelberg-soluble if the resulting Stackelberg strate- gies are in equilibrium. To test the hypothesis that players use this heuristic in Stackelberg-sol- uble games, 100 subjects played all 12 ordinally non-equivalent 2 ´ 2 games, nine of which (including Prisoner's Dilemma and Stag Hunt) were Stackelberg-soluble and three (including Battle of the Sexes and Chicken) of which were non-Stackelberg-soluble. Subjects signi®cantly preferred Stackelberg strategies in Stackelberg-soluble games, and a protocol analysis of stated reasons for choice showed that joint payo maximization and strategic dominance were given as reasons signi®cantly more frequently in Stackelberg-soluble than in non-Stackelberg-solu- ble games. Ó 1998 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PsycINFO classi®cation: 2340 JEL classi®cation: C72 Keywords: Cognitive hypothesis testing; Decision making; Game theory; Heuristic modeling; Non-zero sum games * Corresponding author. Tel.: 01 16 2522170; fax: 01 16 2522067; e-mail: [email protected]. 0167-4870/98/$19.00 Ó 1998 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PII S 0 1 6 7 - 4 8 7 0 ( 9 8 ) 0 0 0 0 8 - 7 280 A.M. Colman, J.A. Stirk / Journal of Economic Psychology 19 (1998) 279±293 1. Introduction There are grounds for believing that, in certain classes of games at least, players tend to use a form of reasoning that Colman and Bacharach (1997) called the Stackelberg heuristic. This is a generalization of the ``minorant'' and ``majorant'' models that von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), Section 14.4.1, pp. 100±104 used to rationalize their solution of strictly competitive games. The assumption underlying the Stackelberg heuristic is that players reason with a type of simulation heuristic (Kahneman and Tversky, 1982) in which both players choose strategies that maximize their own payos on the assumption that any choice will invariably be met by a counterstrategy that maximizes the co-player's payo, as if the co-player could choose second in a perfect-information version of the game with foreknowledge of the ®rst player's choice. For example, a player in a simultaneous-choice game such as the well-known Prisoner's Dilemma game may use the following type of Stackelberg reasoning: Suppose my fellow prisoner were able to move second, with the bene®t of knowing what I had chosen to do. In that case, if I were to cooperate, then my fellow prisoner's sel®sh interest would be best served by respond- ing with a defecting choice, and I would end up with the worst possible payo. On the other hand, if I were to defect, then my fellow prisoner's self-interest would again be served by a defecting choice, but in this case I would get a slightly better payo. It follows that to do the best for my- self in the sequential version of the game I should defect; therefore I will defect in the actual simultaneous-choice version of the game. Formally, in any two-person game C áSi, Hiñ, where Si, i 2 {1, 2} is Play- er i's strategy set and Hi is a real-valued payo function de®ned on the set S S1 ´ S2, Player i applies the Stackelberg heuristic as follows. First, Player i assumes that Player j can anticipate Player i's thinking about the game as if choosing second with perfect information of Player i's choice. This implies that for every strategy si in Player i's strategy set Si, Player j, who is assum- edly rational, responds with a strategy f such that f(si) is invariably a best re- ply of Player j to si, so that Hj si; f si P Hj si; sj 8sj 2 Sj: Second, assuming that both players are fully informed about the rules of the game and the payo functions, Player i expects this to happen and chooses a payo-maximizing strategy based on the assumption that Player j's response will invariably be a best reply f(si). In other words, Player i chooses a count- A.M. Colman, J.A. Stirk / Journal of Economic Psychology 19 (1998) 279±293 281 erstrategy for which maxi Hi(si, f(si)) is attained. This is called Player i's Stackelberg strategy or h strategy. If in any game C the players' h strategies constitute a Nash equilibrium, then C is Stackelberg-soluble (or h-soluble) and the corresponding equilibrium is called a Stackelberg solution (or h so- lution). In a two-person game, a (Nash) equilibrium is an outcome in which each strategy is a payo-maximizing best reply to the co-player's strategy. There are several grounds for believing that the Stackelberg heuristic may in¯uence the thinking of human decision makers. First, the Stackelberg heu- ristic relies on evidential reasoning (Eells, 1985; Jerey, 1983; Nozick, 1969, 1993), a form of reasoning in which decisions are made by maximizing the conditional expected utilities of possible acts rather than the pure expect- ed utilities as in classical decision theory, the utilities of outcomes being weighted by their probabilities given the speci®ed acts, irrespective of wheth- er there is any causal connection between the acts and the outcomes. There is experimental evidence to show that people do, in certain circumstances, use evidential forms of reasoning. For example, Quattrone and Tversky (1984) reported that subjects expressed a greater willingness to vote in an election when they believed that the outcome would depend on the proportion of like-minded voters who voted rather than on the behaviour of non-aligned voters, even though the eect of an individual's vote would be negligible (and equal) in both cases, and they predicted that their preferred candidate would be more likely to win the election if they themselves voted. This is a clear example of evidential reasoning. Second, the Stackelberg heuristic is a form of simulation heuristic, by which people reason about events through an operation resembling the run- ning of a simulation model, and Kahneman and Tversky (1982) have provid- ed empirical evidence that people use simulation heuristics to analyse counterfactual propositions (e.g., ``If only I had driven home by my regular route, I would not have collided with the truck at the intersection'') by men- tally ``undoing'' events that have occurred and then running mental simula- tions of the events with the corresponding parameters of the model altered. The third ground for believing that people use Stackelberg reasoning is the powerful psychological appeal of payo dominance as a criterion for choosing between Nash equilibria in games, and the ability of experimental subjects to exploit payo-dominant equilibrium points by focusing successfully on them in certain pure coordination games (Schelling, 1960, Ch. 3; Mehta et al., 1994a, b) and in other games of common interests (Cooper et al., 1990, 1992a, b). If e and f are any two distinct Nash equilibria in a two-per- son game, then e (strictly) payo-dominates f i Hi(e) > Hi(f) for both 282 A.M. Colman, J.A. Stirk / Journal of Economic Psychology 19 (1998) 279±293 players i 2 {1, 2}. According to the payo-dominance principle, in any game, if one equilibrium point e payo-dominates all others, rational players will choose strategies corresponding to e. The Harsanyi and Selten (1988) general theory of equilibrium selection in games is based on this assumption (togeth- er with a slightly dierent principle of risk dominance), and most game the- orists have accepted its intuitive force (e.g., Crawford and Haller, 1990; Farrell, 1987, 1988; Gauthier, 1975; Lewis, 1969; Sugden, 1995). Games with unique payo-dominant Nash equilibria that are Pareto-opti- mal are called games of common interests (Aumann and Sorin, 1989), and al- though in any such game the payo-dominant equilibrium is the ``obvious'' choice, it has been argued that the payo-dominance principle cannot be jus- ti®ed by conventional game-theoretic reasoning (Gilbert, 1989, 1990). In a two-person common-interest game, for example, Player I has a reason to choose the strategy corresponding to the payo-dominant Nash equilibrium only if there is a reason to expect Player II to do likewise; but Player II has a reason to choose it only if there is a reason to expect Player I to choose it, and we have an in®nite regress that provides neither player with any reason for choosing the payo-dominant equilibrium. Colman and Bacharach (1997) ar- gued that the Stackelberg heuristic provides a clari®cation of the psycholog- ical appeal of payo dominance and an explanation for the otherwise inexplicable ability of experimental subjects to solve certain types of pure co- ordination games in practice. Colman (1997) has shown that all pure coordi- nation games are soluble by the Stackelberg heuristic with the help of the variable-frame theory of Bacharach (1993). Colman and Bacharach (1997) proved that every game of common interest is Stackelberg-soluble or h-soluble, that its h solution is its payo-dominant Nash equilibrium, and that in every game with Pareto-rankable Nash equilib- ria, a Stackelberg solution is a payo-dominant Nash equilibrium. They also proved that there are h-soluble games that are not games of common interests and games with payo-dominant Nash equilibria that are not h solutions.
Recommended publications
  • Game Theory Lecture Notes
    Game Theory: Penn State Math 486 Lecture Notes Version 2.1.1 Christopher Griffin « 2010-2021 Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 3.0 United States License With Major Contributions By: James Fan George Kesidis and Other Contributions By: Arlan Stutler Sarthak Shah Contents List of Figuresv Preface xi 1. Using These Notes xi 2. An Overview of Game Theory xi Chapter 1. Probability Theory and Games Against the House1 1. Probability1 2. Random Variables and Expected Values6 3. Conditional Probability8 4. The Monty Hall Problem 11 Chapter 2. Game Trees and Extensive Form 15 1. Graphs and Trees 15 2. Game Trees with Complete Information and No Chance 18 3. Game Trees with Incomplete Information 22 4. Games of Chance 24 5. Pay-off Functions and Equilibria 26 Chapter 3. Normal and Strategic Form Games and Matrices 37 1. Normal and Strategic Form 37 2. Strategic Form Games 38 3. Review of Basic Matrix Properties 40 4. Special Matrices and Vectors 42 5. Strategy Vectors and Matrix Games 43 Chapter 4. Saddle Points, Mixed Strategies and the Minimax Theorem 45 1. Saddle Points 45 2. Zero-Sum Games without Saddle Points 48 3. Mixed Strategies 50 4. Mixed Strategies in Matrix Games 53 5. Dominated Strategies and Nash Equilibria 54 6. The Minimax Theorem 59 7. Finding Nash Equilibria in Simple Games 64 8. A Note on Nash Equilibria in General 66 Chapter 5. An Introduction to Optimization and the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker Conditions 69 1. A General Maximization Formulation 70 2. Some Geometry for Optimization 72 3.
    [Show full text]
  • California Institute of Technology
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Caltech Authors - Main DIVISION OF THE HUM ANITIES AND SO CI AL SCIENCES CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY PASADENA, CALIFORNIA 91125 IMPLEMENTATION THEORY Thomas R. Palfrey � < a: 0 1891 u. "')/,.. () SOCIAL SCIENCE WORKING PAPER 912 September 1995 Implementation Theory Thomas R. Palfrey Abstract This surveys the branch of implementation theory initiated by Maskin (1977). Results for both complete and incomplete information environments are covered. JEL classification numbers: 025, 026 Key words: Implementation Theory, Mechanism Design, Game Theory, Social Choice Implementation Theory* Thomas R. Palfrey 1 Introduction Implementation theory is an area of research in economic theory that rigorously investi­ gates the correspondence between normative goals and institutions designed to achieve {implement) those goals. More precisely, given a normative goal or welfare criterion for a particular class of allocation pro blems (or domain of environments) it formally char­ acterizes organizational mechanisms that will guarantee outcomes consistent with that goal, assuming the outcomes of any such mechanism arise from some specification of equilibrium behavior. The approaches to this problem to date lie in the general domain of game theory because, as a matter of definition in the implementation theory litera­ ture, an institution is modelled as a mechanism, which is essentially a non-cooperative game. Moreover, the specific models of equilibrium behavior
    [Show full text]
  • Can Game Theory Be Used to Address PPP Renegotiations?
    Can game theory be used to address PPP renegotiations? A retrospective study of the of the Metronet - London Underground PPP By Gregory Michael Kennedy [152111301] Supervisors Professor Ricardo Ferreira Reis, PhD Professor Joaquim Miranda Sarmento, PhD Dissertation submitted in partial fulfilment of requirements for the degree of MSc in Business Administration, at the Universidade Católica Portuguesa June 2013 Abstract of thesis entitled “Can game theory be used to address PPP renegotiations? A retrospective study of the of the Metronet - London Underground PPP” Submitted by Gregory Michael Kennedy (152111301) In partial fulfilment of requirements for the degree of MSc in Business Administration, at the Universidade Católica Portuguesa June 2013 Public Private Partnerships (PPPs) have been introduced in many countries in order to increase the supply of public infrastructure services. The main criterion for implementing a PPP is that it will provide value for money. Often, however, these projects enter into financial distress which requires that they either be rescued or retendered. The cost of such a financial renegotiation can erode the value for money supposed to be created by the PPP. Due to the scale and complexity of these projects, the decision either to rescue or retender the project is not straightforward. We determine whether game theory can aid the decision making process in PPP renegotiation by applying a game theory model retrospectively to the failure of the Metronet - London Underground PPP. We study whether the model can be applied to a real PPP case, whether the application of this model would have changed the outcome of the case and, finally, whether and how the model can be used in future PPP renegotiations.
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Stackelberg Reasoning in Symmetric Games: an Experimental
    Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental ANGOR UNIVERSITY replication and extension Pulford, B.D.; Colman, A.M.; Lawrence, C.L. PeerJ DOI: 10.7717/peerj.263 PRIFYSGOL BANGOR / B Published: 25/02/2014 Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Cyswllt i'r cyhoeddiad / Link to publication Dyfyniad o'r fersiwn a gyhoeddwyd / Citation for published version (APA): Pulford, B. D., Colman, A. M., & Lawrence, C. L. (2014). Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental replication and extension. PeerJ, 263. https://doi.org/10.7717/peerj.263 Hawliau Cyffredinol / General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. 23. Sep. 2021 Strong Stackelberg reasoning in symmetric games: An experimental replication and extension Briony D. Pulford1, Andrew M. Colman1 and Catherine L. Lawrence2 1 School of Psychology, University of Leicester, Leicester, UK 2 School of Psychology, Bangor University, Bangor, UK ABSTRACT In common interest games in which players are motivated to coordinate their strate- gies to achieve a jointly optimal outcome, orthodox game theory provides no general reason or justification for choosing the required strategies.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games
    Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games Topics: terminology and notations (OR 1.7), games and solutions (OR 1.1-1.3), rationality and bounded rationality (OR 1.4-1.6), formalities (OR 2.1), best-response (OR 2.2), Nash equilibrium (OR 2.2), 2 2 examples × (OR 2.3), existence of Nash equilibrium (OR 2.4), mixed strategy Nash equilibrium (OR 3.1, 3.2), strictly competitive games (OR 2.5), evolution- ary stability (OR 3.4), rationalizability (OR 4.1), dominance (OR 4.2, 4.3), trembling hand perfection (OR 12.5). Terminology and notations (OR 1.7) Sets For R, ∈ ≥ ⇐⇒ ≥ for all . and ⇐⇒ ≥ for all and some . ⇐⇒ for all . Preferences is a binary relation on some set of alternatives R. % ⊆ From % we derive two other relations on : — strict performance relation and not  ⇐⇒ % % — indifference relation and ∼ ⇐⇒ % % Utility representation % is said to be — complete if , or . ∀ ∈ % % — transitive if , and then . ∀ ∈ % % % % can be presented by a utility function only if it is complete and transitive (rational). A function : R is a utility function representing if → % ∀ ∈ () () % ⇐⇒ ≥ % is said to be — continuous (preferences cannot jump...) if for any sequence of pairs () with ,and and , . { }∞=1 % → → % — (strictly) quasi-concave if for any the upper counter set ∈ { ∈ : is (strictly) convex. % } These guarantee the existence of continuous well-behaved utility function representation. Profiles Let be a the set of players. — () or simply () is a profile - a collection of values of some variable,∈ one for each player. — () or simply is the list of elements of the profile = ∈ { } − () for all players except . ∈ — ( ) is a list and an element ,whichistheprofile () .
    [Show full text]
  • ECONS 424 – STRATEGY and GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 – Answer Key
    ECONS 424 – STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 – Answer key Exercise #1. Hawk-Dove game. Consider the following payoff matrix representing the Hawk-Dove game. Intuitively, Players 1 and 2 compete for a resource, each of them choosing to display an aggressive posture (hawk) or a passive attitude (dove). Assume that payoff > 0 denotes the value that both players assign to the resource, and > 0 is the cost of fighting, which only occurs if they are both aggressive by playing hawk in the top left-hand cell of the matrix. Player 2 Hawk Dove Hawk , , 0 2 2 − − Player 1 Dove 0, , 2 2 a) Show that if < , the game is strategically equivalent to a Prisoner’s Dilemma game. b) The Hawk-Dove game commonly assumes that the value of the resource is less than the cost of a fight, i.e., > > 0. Find the set of pure strategy Nash equilibria. Answer: Part (a) • When Player 2 (in columns) chooses Hawk (in the left-hand column), Player 1 (in rows) receives a positive payoff of by paying Hawk, which is higher than his payoff of zero from playing Dove. − Therefore, for Player2 1 Hawk is a best response to Player 2 playing Hawk. Similarly, when Player 2 chooses Dove (in the right-hand column), Player 1 receives a payoff of by playing Hawk, which is higher than his payoff from choosing Dove, ; entailing that Hawk is Player 1’s best response to Player 2 choosing Dove. Therefore, Player 1 chooses2 Hawk as his best response to all of Player 2’s strategies, implying that Hawk is a strictly dominant strategy for Player 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Article
    © October 2017 | IJIRT | Volume 4 Issue 5 | ISSN: 2349-6002 The Analogous Application of Game Theory and Monte Carlo Simulation Techniques from World War II to Business Decision Making Dhriti Malviya1, Disha Gupta2, Hiya Banerjee3, Dhairya Shah4, Eashan Shetty5 1, 2,3,4,5 Narsee Monjee Institute of Management Studies, Mumbai, India Abstract- The Second World War, one of the most ‗Operations Research‘ only came up in the year 1940. gruelling events in the history of mankind, also marks During World War II, a team of humans referred to the emergence of one of modern-day’s most widely used as the Blackett‘s Circus in UK first applied scientific scientific disciplines – Operations Research (OR). techniques to analyze military operations to win the Rather than defining OR as a ‘part of mathematics’, a war and thus developed the scientific discipline – better characterization of the sequence of events would be that some mathematicians during World War II Operations Research. Operations Research includes were coerced into mixed disciplinary units dominated plenty of problem-solving techniques like by physicists and statisticians, and directed to mathematical models, statistics and algorithms to participate in an assorted mix of activities which were assist in decision-making. OR is used to analyze clubbed together under the rubric of ‘Operations advanced real-world systems, typically with the Research’. Some of these activities ranged from target of improving or optimizing the tasks. curating a solution for the neutron scattering problem The aim during WWII was to get utmost economical in atomic bomb design to strategizing military attacks usage of restricted military resources by the by means of choosing the best possible route to travel.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Game Theory I
    Introduction to Game Theory I Presented To: 2014 Summer REU Penn State Department of Mathematics Presented By: Christopher Griffin [email protected] 1/34 Types of Game Theory GAME THEORY Classical Game Combinatorial Dynamic Game Evolutionary Other Topics in Theory Game Theory Theory Game Theory Game Theory No time, doesn't contain differential equations Notion of time, may contain differential equations Games with finite or Games with no Games with time. Modeling population Experimental / infinite strategy space, chance. dynamics under Behavioral Game but no time. Games with motion or competition Theory Generally two player a dynamic component. Games with probability strategic games Modeling the evolution Voting Theory (either induced by the played on boards. Examples: of strategies in a player or the game). Optimal play in a dog population. Examples: Moves change the fight. Chasing your Determining why Games with coalitions structure of a game brother across a room. Examples: altruism is present in or negotiations. board. The evolution of human society. behaviors in a group of Examples: Examples: animals. Determining if there's Poker, Strategic Chess, Checkers, Go, a fair voting system. Military Decision Nim. Equilibrium of human Making, Negotiations. behavior in social networks. 2/34 Games Against the House The games we often see on television fall into this category. TV Game Shows (that do not pit players against each other in knowledge tests) often require a single player (who is, in a sense, playing against The House) to make a decision that will affect only his life. Prize is Behind: 1 2 3 Choose Door: 1 2 3 1 2 3 1 2 3 Switch: Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Win/Lose: L W W L W L W L L W W L W L W L L W The Monty Hall Problem Other games against the house: • Blackjack • The Price is Right 3/34 Assumptions of Multi-Player Games 1.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Heuristics, Thinking About Others, and Strategic
    Heuristics, thinking about others, and strategic management: Insights from behavioral game theory Davide Marchiori University of Southern Denmark Rosemarie Nagel ICREA, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, BGSE Jens Schmidt Aalto University Abstract The outcome of strategic decisions (such as market entry or technology adoption) depends on the decisions made by others (such as competitors, customers, or suppliers). To anticipate others’ decisions managers must form beliefs about them and consider that others also form such higher-order beliefs. In this paper we draw on insights from behavioral game theory —in particular the level-k model of higher-order reasoning— to introduce a two-part heuristic model of behavior in interactive decision situations. In the first part the decision maker constructs a simplified model of the situation as a game. As a toolbox for such formulations, we provide a classification of games that relies on both game-theoretic and behavioral dimensions. Our classification includes aggregative games in an extended Keynesian beauty contest formulation and two-person 2x2 games as their most simplified instances. In the second part we construct a two-step heuristic model of anchoring and adjustment based on the level-k model, which is a behaviorally plausible model of behavior in interactive decision situations. A key contribution of our article is to show how higher-order reasoning matters differently in different classes of games. We discuss implications of our arguments for strategy research and suggest opportunities for further study. Keywords: Behavioral game theory, beauty contest games, bounded rationality, heuristics in strategic Interaction, strategy, level k model, anchors. 1 1. Introduction “To change the metaphor slightly, professional investment may be likened to those newspaper competitions in which the competitors have to pick out the six prettiest faces from a hundred photographs, the prize being awarded to the competitor whose choice most nearly corresponds to the average preferences of the competitors as a whole; [.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Quant-Ph/0702167V2 30 Jan 2013
    Quantum Game Theory Based on the Schmidt Decomposition Tsubasa Ichikawa∗ and Izumi Tsutsui† Institute of Particle and Nuclear Studies High Energy Accelerator Research Organization (KEK) Tsukuba 305-0801, Japan and Taksu Cheon‡ Laboratory of Physics Kochi University of Technology Tosa Yamada, Kochi 782-8502, Japan Abstract We present a novel formulation of quantum game theory based on the Schmidt de- composition, which has the merit that the entanglement of quantum strategies is manifestly quantified. We apply this formulation to 2-player, 2-strategy symmetric games and obtain a complete set of quantum Nash equilibria. Apart from those available with the maximal entanglement, these quantum Nash equilibria are ex- arXiv:quant-ph/0702167v2 30 Jan 2013 tensions of the Nash equilibria in classical game theory. The phase structure of the equilibria is determined for all values of entanglement, and thereby the possibility of resolving the dilemmas by entanglement in the game of Chicken, the Battle of the Sexes, the Prisoners’ Dilemma, and the Stag Hunt, is examined. We find that entanglement transforms these dilemmas with each other but cannot resolve them, except in the Stag Hunt game where the dilemma can be alleviated to a certain degree. ∗ email: [email protected] † email: [email protected] ‡ email: [email protected] 1. Introduction Quantum game theory, which is a theory of games with quantum strategies, has been attracting much attention among quantum physicists and economists in recent years [1, 2] (for a review, see [2, 3, 4]). There are basically two reasons for this. One is that quantum game theory provides a general basis to treat the quantum information processing and quantum communication in which plural actors try to achieve their objectives such as the increase in communication efficiency and security [5, 6].
    [Show full text]
  • The Mondee Gills Game (MGG) Were Always the Same, Although the Scenery Changed with Time
    Mathematical Entertainments Michael Kleber and Ravi Vakil, Editors The Mondee Gills To switch or not to switch, that is the question ... game played in Mondee Gills is not so familiar because of the isolation of the country and pecu- Game AA liarities of the dialect of the Mondees. Many people confuse the game with its rogue variant sometimes played SASHA GNEDIN for money with thimbleriggers on the streets of big cities. Mainland historians trace the roots to primitive contests such as coin tossing and matching pennies. However, every Mondee knows that the game is as old as their land, and the land is really old. An ancient tomb unearthed by archaeol- This column is a place for those bits of contagious ogists on the western side of Capra Heuvel, the second- mathematics that travel from person to person in the highest hill in the country, was found to contain the remains of domesticated cave goats and knucklebones, which community, because they are so elegant, surprising, supports the hypothesis that the basics of the game go back to farmers of the late Neolithic Revolution. or appealing that one has an urge to pass them on. The rules of the Mondee Gills Game (MGG) were always the same, although the scenery changed with time. Nowa- Contributions are most welcome. days the Mondee Gills Monday TV broadcasts the game as an open-air reality show in which there are three caves, one goat, and two traditional characters called Monte and Con- nie. The goat is hidden by Monte in one of the caves before the show starts, two other caves are left empty.
    [Show full text]
  • M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics
    M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics Game Theory – Brief Introduction The work on this text has been supported by the project CZ.1.07/2.2.00/15.0203. What is Game Theory? We do not live in vacuum. Whether we like it or not, all of us are strategists. ST is art but its foundations consist of some simple basic principles. The science of strategic thinking is called Game Theory. Where is Game Theory coming from? Game Theory was created by Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) in their classic book The Theory of Games and Economic Behavior Two distinct approaches to the theory of games: 1. Strategic/Non-cooperative Approach 2. Coalition/Cooperative Approach Where is Game Theory coming from? The key contributions of John Nash: 1. The notion of Nash equilibrium 2. Arguments for determining the two-person bargaining problems Other significant names: N-Nash, A-Aumann, S-Shapley&Selten, H- Harsanyi Lecture 1 26.02.2010 M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics 1.1.Static Games of Complete Information Instructor: Georgi Burlakov The static (simultaneous-move) games Informally, the games of this class could be described as follows: First, players simultaneously choose a move (action). Then, based on the resulting combination of actions chosen in total, each player receives a given payoff. Example: Students’ Dilemma Strategic behaviour of students taking a course: First, each of you is forced to choose between studying HARD or taking it EASY. Then, you do your exam and get a GRADE. Static Games of Complete Information Standard assumptions: Players move (take an action or make a choice) simultaneously at a moment – it is STATIC Each player knows what her payoff and the payoff of the other players will be at any combination of chosen actions – it is COMPLETE INFORMATION Example: Students’ Dilemma Standard assumptions: Students choose between HARD and EASY SIMULTANEOUSLY.
    [Show full text]