(A) Natural Philosophy (Or Natural History): Its Meaning and Range 2

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

(A) Natural Philosophy (Or Natural History): Its Meaning and Range 2 Greek Natural Philosophy The Presocratics and their Importance for Environmental Philosophy First Edition By J. Baird Callicott, John van Buren, and Keith Wayne Brown Bassim Hamadeh, CEO and Publisher Marissa Applegate, Senior Field Acquisitions Editor Gem Rabanera, Project Editor Alia Bales, Associate Production Editor Miguel Macias, Senior Graphic Designer Alexa Lucido, Licensing Coordinator Sue Murray, Interior Designer Natalie Piccotti, Senior Marketing Manager Kassie Graves, Director of Acquisitions and Sales Jamie Giganti, Senior Managing Editor Copyright © 2018 by Cognella, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reprinted, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information retrieval system without the written permis- sion of Cognella, Inc. For inquiries regarding permissions, translations, foreign rights, audio rights, and any other forms of reproduction, please contact the Cognella Licensing Department at [email protected]. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for iden- tification and explanation without intent to infringe. Cover image copyright © 2017 Depositphotos/Jrleyland. Printed in the United States of America ISBN: 978-1-5165-2856-1 (pbk) / 978-1-5165-2857-8 (br) In memory of our early teachers in Greek natural philosophy: José Benardete and Catherine Lord, Syracuse University; Perry Robinson, University of New Brunswick; and Richard Owsley, University of North Texas. CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xi INTRODUCTION 2 (A) NATURAL PHILOSOPHY (OR NATURAL HISTORY): ITS MEANING AND RANGE 2 (B) THE ORGANIZATION, SCOPE, AND PURPOSE OF THIS BOOK 7 (C) RECONSTRUCTING PRESOCRATIC NATURAL PHILOSOPHY 10 (D) OUR INTERPRETIVE METHOD: THE DIACHRONIC DIALECTIC OF IDEAS 14 (E) WHY PHILOSOPHY SUDDENLY EMERGED WHEN IT DID: A COMMUNICATIONS REVOLUTION 18 (F) WHY PHILOSOPHY SUDDENLY EMERGED WHERE IT DID: THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 28 (G) CODA: NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS 38 FOR FURTHER READING 43 CHAPTER 1 THE MYTHOPOEIC WORLDVIEW 44 (A) HESIOD’S THEOGONY 44 (B) HESIOD’S WORKS AND DAYS 61 (C) THE MYTHOPOEIC WORLDVIEW IN BAREST OUTLINE 69 FOR FURTHER READING 70 CHAPTER 2 THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 72 (A) THALES 72 (B) ANAXIMANDER 79 (C) RATIONALIZING AND NATURALIZING MYTHOLOGY 92 (D) ANAXIMENES 95 (E) WHAT NEXT? 104 FOR FURTHER READING 104 CHAPTER 3 XENOPHANES AND HERACLITUS 108 (A) XENOPHANES 110 (B) HERACLITUS 114 FOR FURTHER READING 131 CHAPTER 4 THE ELEATIC SCHOOL 134 (A) PARMENIDES 135 (B) ZENO 147 (C) MELISSUS 159 (D) WAS XENOPHANES THE FOUNDER OF THE ELEATIC SCHOOL? 164 FOR FURTHER READING 166 CHAPTER 5 THE QUALITATIVE PLURALISTS: ANAXAGORAS 168 (A) AFTER THE ELEATICS 168 (B) PHILOSOPHY COMES TO ATHENS IN THE PERSON OF ANAXAGORAS 171 (C) ANAXAGORAS’S COSMOGONY, COSMOLOGY, AND ARCHĒ 174 (D) ANAXAGORAS’S MIND 185 (E) ONE WORLD OR MANY? 187 FOR FURTHER READING 188 CHAPTER 6 THE QUALITATIVE PLURALISTS: EMPEDOCLES 190 (A) RELIGION AND SCIENCE IN THE “ITALIAN TRADITION” OF PRESOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY 190 (B) EMPEDOCLES’S PERSONALITY 194 (C) EMPEDOCLES’S RELIGIOUS WORLDVIEW 196 (D) EMPEDOCLES’S WAY OF SAVING THE APPEARANCES 200 (E) EMPEDOCLES’S COSMOGONY AND COSMOLOGY 208 (F) EMPEDOCLES’S ZOOGONY 211 (G) EMPEDOCLES’S EPISTEMOLOGY 212 (H) SUCCESSES AND FAILURES OF THE QUALITATIVE PLURALISTS TO SAVE THE APPEARANCES 216 FOR FURTHER READING 219 CHAPTER 7 THE ATOMISTS: LEUCIPPUS AND DEMOCRITUS 220 (A) THE CROWN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHICAL ACHIEVEMENT BEFORE PLATO 220 (B) ATOMISM AND THE ELEATIC CONNECTION 223 (C) THE ATOMISTS’ IONIAN/ELEATIC ONTOLOGY 226 (D) PROPERTIES OF THE ATOMS 229 (E) MOTION 232 (F) THE ATOMS AS LETTER-ELEMENTS 235 (G) SAVING THE APPEARANCES 237 (H) APPEARANCE AND REALITY 242 (I) THE SOUL 243 (J) COSMOGONY, COSMOLOGY, BIOLOGY, AND METEOROLOGY 245 (K) ANTHROPOGONY AND POLITOGONY 247 - - (L) CHANCE (TUCHE) AND NECESSITY (ANAGKE) 248 (M) DEMOCRITUS RIDENS—THE LAUGHING PHILOSOPHER 250 (N) ETHICS 250 FOR FURTHER READING 252 CHAPTER 8 PYTHAGORAS AND THE PYTHAGOREANS 254 (A) ARISTOTLE’S ACCOUNT OF PYTHAGOREANISM 254 (B) PYTHAGORAS 259 (C) PYTHAGOREAN RELIGIOUS BELIEFS 263 (D) DID PYTHAGORAS INVENT MATHEMATICS? 265 (E) DID PYTHAGORAS INVENT HARMONICS? 268 (F) DID PYTHAGORAS INVENT ASTRONOMY? 270 (G) PYTHAGOREAN COSMOLOGY 273 (H) PYTHAGOREAN NUMEROLOGY 275 (I) ARISTOTLE’S ACCOUNT OF PLATO’S PYTHAGOREAN METAPHYSICS 277 (J) MAKING SENSE OF ARISTOTLE’S ACCOUNT OF PLATO’S PYTHAGOREAN METAPHYSICS 280 (K) PLATO’S EXOTERIC (WRITTEN) AND ESOTERIC (ORAL AND SECRET) PHILOSOPHY 284 (L) THE GOOD AND PLATO’S POLITOGONY 287 (M) PLATO’S GEOMETRICAL ATOMISM AND THE FOUR ELEMENTS 288 (N) PLATO’S COSMOGONY 291 (O) CODA 293 FOR FURTHER READING 295 CHAPTER 9 A NEOPRESOCRATIC MANIFESTO: HISTORY AND RELEVANCE OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY 298 (A) HELLENISTIC, MEDIEVAL, AND MODERN NATURAL PHILOSOPHY 300 (B) THE 20TH CENTURY ECLIPSE OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY 309 (C) THE SECOND SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION—QUANTUM PHYSICS, ASTROPHYSICS, ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCE 314 (D) DEFINING A NEW ROLE FOR PHILOSOPHY AT THE TURN OF THE 21ST CENTURY 326 (E) A 21ST-CENTURY NATURAL PHILOSOPHY RENAISSANCE— ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY, HUMANITIES, AND SOCIAL SCIENCES 333 (F) THE HISTORICAL SEQUENCE OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY 343 (G) A SECOND REVOLUTION IN COMMUNICATIONS AND INFORMATION TECHNOLOGY 346 (H) CODA 347 FOR FURTHER READING 348 REFERENCES 354 INDEX 367 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS J. Baird Callicott, known as a founder of the field of environmental philosophy and ethics, has also been researching and teaching Greek philosophy for almost fifty years at the University of Wisconsin-Stevens Point and the University of North Texas (UNT). Chapters 1–8 of this book are based on his course lectures. Keith Wayne Brown co-taught Callicott’s introductory Greek philosophy course as a Teaching Assistant at UNT from 1995–2015 and became an instructor of record in his own right, as Callicott retired from UNT. Brown joined Callicott as co-author in the preparation of the course lectures for publication. Callicott was delighted to learn that John van Buren—his co-editor in the book series on envi- ronmental philosophy at SUNY Press—was working on the Presocratics from an environmental-philosophy orientation. Upon receiving a preliminary edition of the course-lectures materials, van Buren agreed to become a co-author. His knowledge of contemporary scholarship in the field of Greek philosophy helps bolster the interpretation of the texts; and he brings the book’s classical historical focus to bear on the issues of Greek philosophy’s environmental origins and its relevance for contemporary environmental disciplines. All students of Greek natural philosophy owe an immense debt of gratitude to Hermann Diels (1848-1922). No work of the Presocratic philosophers survived the ravages of time and the fires of religious zealotry in whole and complete form. Diels lived in an era during which the backbone of European education consisted of reading Greek and Latin literature (the “classics”) in the original languages. He was thus prepared to undertake the gargantuan task of combing through all the extant literature from the “Golden Age of Greece” (the 5th century BCE) to Late Antiquity (as late as the 6th century) that provided information about the philosophies of the Presocratics. Diels collected this information in one magnum opus—Die Fragmente der Vorsokatiker, first published in 1903 by Weidmansche Buchhandlung in Berlin—which provided the Greek texts together with a German translation. Diels expanded this work in second, third, and fouth editions, assisted by Walther Kranz (1884-1960). After Diels died, Kranz edited a fifth, revised and further expanded edition, published over the years 1934 to 1937 and a sixth edi- tion, published in 1952, also by Weidmann. It is customary to cite this work simply as “DK”—“D” for Diels, “K” for Kranz. The DK texts are sorted into two data sets: “testimonia” (second- or third-hand accounts or summaries) and “ipsissima verba” (purportedly exact words, that is, direct quotations). A number is assigned to each philosopher and to each item pertaining to that philosopher. These letters and numbers have been adopted as the standard method of citing the Presocratics. For example, “DK 67A8” refers to Leucippus (67)—the inventor of the atomic xi theory of matter—an account of whose philosophy (A) is 8th in the arrangement of the Leucippus testimonia by Diels and Kranz. The sources from which Diels (and later Kranz) drew the “fragments” (as the ipsis- sima verba are customarily called) and the testimonia range widely not only over ten centuries but over many genres of literature—from the 5th-century BCE Histories of Herodotus (the earliest extant source) to the 4th-century BCE dialogues of Plato and treatises of Aristotle, to the 1st-century biographies and other writings of Plutarch, to the 3rd-century Christian apologetics of Hippolytus of Rome, all the way down to the 6th-century commentaries of Simplicius of Cilicia, a Neoplatonist. We cite these ancient authors as well so that the readers of this textbook can identify the ultimate source, in each instance, upon which Diels and Kranz drew. We might compare the task that Diels undertook to searching through scores of ancient treasure troves in which hundreds of pieces of dozens of jigsaw puzzles may be found lying in the midst of other materials, then trying to fit the pieces of each puzzle together in the hopes of forming at least part of an intelligible picture. Subsequent scholars may sometimes downgrade a few of the DK fragments to testimonia and many put the puzzle pieces together differently than did Diels and Kranz. In this textbook, we present selected fragments and testimonia of the Presocratic philosophers and other Greek authors in English translation. We have, in every case, worked directly from the Greek texts and have consulted the translations of other schol- ars in crafting our own: R. G. Bury. 1929. Plato, Timaeus. London: William Heinemann Ltd.; H.
Recommended publications
  • The Fairy Tale Sleeping Beauty and the Year 2020 by Richard John Fraser Cooper
    The Fairy Tale Sleeping Beauty and the Year 2020 By Richard John Fraser Cooper Who has not been taken aback by the unprecedented events of this year? Going forward, we are undoubtedly in a time of change, but what kind of change, and what may be learnt from times of change that have gone before? Much can be learnt when we more deeply question the events of one hundred years ago and see the movement of spiritual history in relation to 2020. Rudolf Steiner has drawn our attention to looking at history through the lens of 100 years. Each 100- year phase carries 3 x 33 1/3 years within it, to make a total of one hundred. Steiner showed how the rhythm of 331/3 years mirrors the life of Christ on earth, from birth to crucifixion and resurrection. It is therefore important to explore how we may reconnect with what was initiated 100 years ago, in its positive and negative aspects, to gain insight into mankind’s struggle toward the Christ impulse. 100 years ago from the ominous outbreak of the Coronavirus Crisis in 2020, the official implementation of the Treaty of Versailles was signed on the 10 January, 1920. The Treaty, enforcing reparation payments on Germany for its war guilt, was instrumental in laying the groundwork for the historical events that would later unfold; notably, the rearmament of Germany leading to the Second World War and the world order that would later emerge after 1945. Quite aptly, the signing had taken place in the Hall of Mirrors at the Palace of Versailles, in Paris, France, being rather symbolic of an elite struggling to pursue their own national and established political concerns separated from any of the spiritual implications of the decisions before them.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Unit 2 Pre-Socratic Thinkers and Their Contribution
    UNIT 2 PRE-SOCRATIC THINKERS AND THEIR CONTRIBUTION Contents 2.0 Objectives 2.1 Introduction 2.2 Pre-Socratic Thinkers 2.3 The Schools of the Pre-Socratics 2.4 The Ionian School or The Milesian School 2.5 The Pythagorean Brotherhood 2.6 The Eleatic School 2.7 The Atomist School 2.8 Challenges to the Study of Pre-Socratics: 2.9 The Pre-Socratics as Scientists 2.10 So can we call Anaximanes a Scientist? 2.11 The Pre-Socratics and their Predecessors: 2.12 Pre-Socratics and Modern science 2.13 Let Us Sum Up 2.14 Key Words 2.15 Further Readings and References 2.16 Answers to Check Your Progress 2.0 OBJECTIVES This unit will help us to understand the following: • Who are the Pre-Socratics • Schools of the Pre-Socratics era • Pre-Socratics as Proto-Scientists or First Scientists • Pre-Socratics and modern Science. 1 2.1 INTRODUCTION It has become an academic sutra to say that the entire academic edifice of the western world is founded on firm foundation laid down by the Greeks. This revolution is said to have taken place in the sixth century BCE. But we know that science began even before the Greek period. Civilizations that developed around the basins of great rivers –the Nile, the Euphrates with the Tigris and the Indus manifest a lot of scientific know-how. These people developed science to meet their existential needs. But it was Greeks who discovered the philosophical explanation that led to the birth of theoretical science. This is accepted as their singular contribution as their contribution led to what we might call the scientific approach to the study of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Sunday, July 8, 2018 12:01 PM
    Philosophy Sunday, July 8, 2018 12:01 PM Western Pre-Socratics Fanon Heraclitus- Greek 535-475 Bayle Panta rhei Marshall Mcluhan • "Everything flows" Roman Jakobson • "No man ever steps in the same river twice" Saussure • Doctrine of flux Butler Logos Harris • "Reason" or "Argument" • "All entities come to be in accordance with the Logos" Dike eris • "Strife is justice" • Oppositional process of dissolving and generating known as strife "The Obscure" and "The Weeping Philosopher" "The path up and down are one and the same" • Theory about unity of opposites • Bow and lyre Native of Ephesus "Follow the common" "Character is fate" "Lighting steers the universe" Neitzshce said he was "eternally right" for "declaring that Being was an empty illusion" and embracing "becoming" Subject of Heideggar and Eugen Fink's lecture Fire was the origin of everything Influenced the Stoics Protagoras- Greek 490-420 BCE Most influential of the Sophists • Derided by Plato and Socrates for being mere rhetoricians "Man is the measure of all things" • Found many things to be unknowable • What is true for one person is not for another Could "make the worse case better" • Focused on persuasiveness of an argument Names a Socratic dialogue about whether virtue can be taught Pythagoras of Samos- Greek 570-495 BCE Metempsychosis • "Transmigration of souls" • Every soul is immortal and upon death enters a new body Pythagorean Theorem Pythagorean Tuning • System of musical tuning where frequency rations are on intervals based on ration 3:2 • "Pure" perfect fifth • Inspired
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Cosmos in Milesian Philosophy
    The Concept of Cosmos in Milesian Philosophy Viivi Lähteenoja 19 July 2017 Tiedekunta/Osasto – Fakultet/Sektion – Laitos – Institution – Department Faculty Humanistinen tiedekunta Filosofian, historian, kulttuurin ja taiteiden tutkimuksen laitos Tekijä – Författare – Author Viivi Esteri Lähteenoja Työn nimi – Arbetets titel – Title The Concept of Cosmos in Milesian Philosophy Oppiaine – Läroämne – Subject Teoreettinen filosofia Työn laji – Arbetets art – Aika – Datum – Month and Sivumäärä– Sidoantal – Number of pages Level year Pro gradu -tutkielma 19 heinäkuuta 2017 83 Tiivistelmä – Referat – Abstract Tämä tutkielma käsittelee kreikan sanan kosmos käyttöä aikaisessa esisokraattisessa filosofiassa, eli miletoslaisten Thaleen, Anaksimandroksen, sekä Anaksimeneen ajattelussa. Tutkielman tavoite on haastaa nykyään yleinen ajatus siitä, että miletoslaiset olisivat olleet puhtaita luonnonfilosofeja, tutkimalla moniselitteisen kosmos-sanan käyttöä. Tämä saavutetaan kokoamalla kaikki näitä ajattelijoita koskevat tekstit, joissa kyseinen sana esiintyy. Ensin tekstit käännetään alkukielestä ja ne analysoidaan filologisesti. Filologisten havaintojen perusteella tekstit asetetaan seuraavaksi niiden filosofiseen kontekstiin, jolloin voidaan osallistua kirjallisuudessa käytävään keskusteluun näiden ajattelijoiden kokonaisfilosofiasta. Lopuksi esitetään vielä excursus liittyen kahteen muuhun keskeiseen esisokraattiseen termiin, phusis ja arkhê. Taustalla tässä työtavassa on ajatus siitä, että esisokraattisen filosofian tutkimuksessa on vuosisatojen
    [Show full text]
  • Heraclitus on Pythagoras
    Leonid Zhmud Heraclitus on Pythagoras By the time of Heraclitus, criticism of one’s predecessors and contemporaries had long been an established literary tradition. It had been successfully prac­ ticed since Hesiod by many poets and prose writers.1 No one, however, practiced criticism in the form of persistent and methodical attacks on both previous and current intellectual traditions as effectively as Heraclitus. Indeed, his biting criti­ cism was a part of his philosophical method and, on an even deeper level, of his self­appraisal and self­understanding, since he alone pretended to know the correct way to understand the underlying reality, unattainable even for the wisest men of Greece. Of all the celebrities figuring in Heraclitus’ fragments only Bias, one of the Seven Sages, is mentioned approvingly (DK 22 B 39), while another Sage, Thales, is the only one mentioned neutrally, as an astronomer (DK 22 B 38). All the others named by Heraclitus, which is to say the three most famous poets, Homer, Hesiod and Archilochus, the philosophical poet Xenophanes, Pythago­ ras, widely known for his manifold wisdom, and finally, the historian and geog­ rapher Hecataeus – are given their share of opprobrium.2 Despite all the intensity of Heraclitus’ attacks on these famous individuals, one cannot say that there was much personal in them. He was not engaged in ordi­ nary polemics with his contemporaries, as for example Xenophanes, Simonides or Pindar were.3 Xenophanes and Hecataeus, who were alive when his book was written, appear only once in his fragments, and even then only in the company of two more famous people, Hesiod and Pythagoras (DK 22 B 40).
    [Show full text]
  • On Nature and Grace: the Role of Reason in the Life of Faith
    On Nature and Grace: The Role of Reason in the Life of Faith Peter Kalkavage St. John's College, Annapolis Theology on Tap Harry Browne's 2 July 2013 "Ever since the creation of the world his invisible nature, namely, his eternal power and deity, has been clearly perceived in the things that have been made." Romans 1:20 My goal this evening is to praise reason-that is, speculative reason-in the context of Christian faith. Speculative here refers to reason that seeks the truth for its own sake. Many voices inspired my effort: Clement of Alexandria, who extolled the wisdom of ancient Greek philosophers; Anselm, who spoke of faith seeking understanding; Augustine, whose path to God incorporated the philosophic eros for deathless truth; Bonaventure, who coined the remarkable phrase and title, itinerarium mentis in Deum, the mind's journey into God; and Dante, for whom the hallmark of heaven is the perfection of the mind. A more recently composed inspiration has been John Paul's great encyclical Fides et ratio ("Faith and Reason"). The hero of my reflections is Aquinas. As a young student, Thomas was unresponsive and seemed dull. But Albert the Great said something about him that turned out to be prophetic: "We call this young man a dumb ox, but his bellowing in doctrine will one day resound throughout the world." Aquinas is regularly in need of being rediscovered. I say this because he is a logically rigorous author, whom some readers find dry and uninspiring. Admittedly, his writing lacks the emotional power of Augustine's Confessions, the rhetorical energy of Anselm's Proslogion, and the inspired poetic flights of Dante.
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanical Miracles: Automata in Ancient Greek Religion
    Mechanical Miracles: Automata in Ancient Greek Religion Tatiana Bur A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy Faculty of Arts, University of Sydney Supervisor: Professor Eric Csapo March, 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. Tatiana Bur, March 2016. Table of Contents ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ....................................................................................................... 1 A NOTE TO THE READER ................................................................................................... 2 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................ 3 PART I: THINKING ABOUT AUTOMATION .......................................................................... 9 CHAPTER 1/ ELIMINATING THE BLOCAGE: ANCIENT AUTOMATA IN MODERN SCHOLARSHIP ................. 10 CHAPTER 2/ INVENTING AUTOMATION: AUTOMATA IN THE ANCIENT GREEK IMAGINATION ................. 24 PART II: AUTOMATA IN CONTEXT ................................................................................... 59 CHAPTER 3/ PROCESSIONAL AUTOMATA ................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Master Essay Question List, Exam #1
    PHIL 320: HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY STUDY QUESTIONS FOR MID-TERM EXAM Milesians 1. What ideas do Thales and Anaximander have in common? Where do they disagree? What, do you suppose, accounts for their disagreement? 2. Explain the role of the apeiron in Anaximander’s system. Discuss at least two possible interpretations of what Anaximander means by ‘apeiron’. 3. Discuss and amplify, if you can, the claim (made by Bertrand Russell) that “the Milesian school is important, not for what it achieved, but for what it attempted.” 4. What was Anaximander’s objection to making a common element (such as water, as Thales had proposed) the archê? How did Anaximenes, who proposed air as the archê, avoid this objection? 5. It is often claimed that Anaximenes attempted to account for qualitative differences in quantitative terms. What can be said in favor of this claim? What can be said against it? 6. Compare the role of the traditional Greek elements in the theories of Anaximander and Anaximenes. Discuss the importance of the notion of opposition in each of the theories. 7. Compare the role of the notion of opposition in the theories of Anaximander, Anaximenes, and Heraclitus. Heraclitus 1. The notion of logos plays an important role in Heraclitus’s thought. Explain, in as much detaill as you can, what the notion is and what role it plays. 2. According to Plato, Heraclitus said that it is impossible to step into the same river twice. Heraclitus’s own words, in fragment 12, read as follows: “Upon those that step into the same rivers different and different waters flow .
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Heidegger on Science
    WHY READ HEIDEGGER ON SCIENCE? Trish Glazebrook Heidegger wrote extensively concerning science for more than sixty years. Four aspects of his analysis in particular demonstrate the breadth and scope of his sustained critique of science, and indicate specific trajectories for its further development. First, he has much to say to traditional philosophers of science concerning the experimental method, the role and function of mathematics and measurement, the nature of paradigms and incommensu- rabilty, and realism versus antirealism. Second, his assessment of technol- ogy is incipient in and arises from his reading of the history of physics, so theorists who overlook this aspect of his work may find they are working with a deficient theoretical framework when attempting to come to terms with his critique of technology. Third, he offers rich conceptual resources to environmental philosophers, especially those who work at the intersection of environment and international development. Fourth, his arguments for reflection on science support a renewed sense of social obligation on the part of the sciences that should be of especial interest to science, technol- ogy, and society theorists. I have examined these first two issues elsewhere.1 Rather than repeat- ing that work here, I situate this volume against traditional philosophy of science only by showing briefly how his concern with science begins with a tension in his thinking between realism and idealism. On the second issue, I show here only how Heidegger’s thinking concerning Ge-stell arises directly from his prior thinking about basic concepts and the mathemati- cal in science. The issues of ecophenomenology and the social obligations of the sciences are continuations of fertile and promising lines of thinking Heidegger opened.
    [Show full text]
  • Green Politics and the Concept of Nature: Heidegger, Nature
    Green Politics and the Concept of Nature: Heidegger, Nature and the Earth Reetta Vaahtoranta Thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Ph.D. Department of International Politics Aberystwyth University September, 2014 1 Summary This thesis investigates the role that the concept of nature plays in green politics. Nature, in the green literature, is usually assumed to refer to the nonhuman environment. But critics of this way of thinking about nature argue that humans exist in such interconnected networks with their environments that environments cannot be divided into categories of human and nonhuman. These criticisms suggest that we should abandon talking about nature and concentrate instead on investigating the complex relationships we share with our environments. But even in the light of these criticisms the idea of nature does seem to articulate something important about green politics which cannot be communicated by just investigating the relationships that we share with our environments. I turn to the philosophy of Martin Heidegger to make sense of this concept of nature. Heidegger makes numerous references to the unfolding of nature and the earth in his works. His philosophy has thus been used to make sense of what is at stake in taking care of our environments. In mainstream green readings of Heidegger, nature is understood as referring to the spontaneous growth of a nonhuman nature. However, I will approach nature in Heidegger’s work differently, divorcing these concepts of nature and the earth from descriptions of the material growth of nonhuman natural beings. This allows us to understand the importance of the idea of nature in green politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Unveiling the Goddess Artemis of Ephesus As a Symbol of Nature at the Turn of the Nineteenth Century
    Unveiling the Goddess Artemis of Ephesus as a symbol of nature at the turn of the nineteenth century Frederika Tevebring In 1807 Alexander von Humboldt published his Ideen zu einer Geographie der Pflanzen nebst ein Naturgemälde der Tropenlander, a translation from French of one of the volumes written as a result of his five-year expedition to Latin America. The German translation includes a frontispiece by Humboldt’s friend, the Danish artist Bertel Thorvaldsen. The image shows a statue of Artemis of Ephesus being unveiled by Apollo.1 At the base of the statue lies a tablet with the inscription Metamorphose der Pflanzen, a reference to Humboldt’s much-esteemed friend Goethe to whom the fron- tispiece is dedicated. In a letter to Goethe Humboldt expresses his enthu- siasm for the image and how he looks forward to presenting the book to his friend. “After so many years of absence I did not want appear before you in any other way but through this small tribute, which is a testimo- nial of my deep reverence and profound gratefulness towards you,” and “my friend Thorvaldsen in Rome has come up with this vignette for me. It refers to the synthesis of Poetry, Philosophy and Natural sciences brought together in your person.”2 Thorvaldsen’s picture was not the first of its kind; the unveiling of the ancient goddess had been a reoccurring pictorial trope in discourses on the pursuit of philosophical and scientific knowledge since the seventeenth century, when it also became increasingly popular on frontispieces to scientific treatises. Goethe himself had made use of similar images on several occasions.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminism and the Mastery of Nature/Val Plumwood
    Feminism and the Mastery of Nature Feminism and the Mastery of Nature draws on the feminist critique of reason to argue that the master form of rationality of western culture has been systematically unable to acknowledge dependency on nature, the sphere of those it has defined as ‘inferior’ others. Because its knowledge of the world is sytematically distorted by the elite domination which has shaped it, the master rationality has developed ‘blind spots’ which may threaten our survival. The future depends increasingly on our ability to create a truly democratic and ecological culture beyond dualism. The book shows how the feminist critique of dominant forms of rationality can be extended to integrate theories of gender, race and class oppression with that of the domination of nature. Val Plumwood illuminates the relationship between women and nature, and between ecological feminism and other feminist theories. Exploring the contribution feminist theory can make to radical green thought and to the development of a better environmental philosophy, Feminism and the Mastery of Nature challenges much existing work in green theory and environmental philosophy, and engages with the heavily masculine presence which has inhabited many accounts of the area. It will be essential reading for those working in these areas, and for all those seeking to understand the historical, philosophical and cultural roots of the environmental crisis and the culture of denial which blocks response to it. Val Plumwood teaches in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Tasmania, Australia. Feminism for Today General Editor: Teresa Brennan. The Regime of the Brother After the Patriarchy Juliet Flower MacCannell History After Lacan Teresa Brennan Feminism and the Mastery of Nature Val Plumwood London and New York First published 1993 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003.
    [Show full text]