Equality of Opportunity: a Progress Report

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Equality of Opportunity: a Progress Report Soc Choice Welfare (2002) 19: 455–471 99209092 Equality of opportunity: A progress report John E. Roemer Yale University, Department of Political Science, 124 Prospect Street, New Haven, CT 06520-8301, USA (e-mail: [email protected]) Received: 5 January 2001/Accepted: 4 December 2001 1 Introduction Probably the most universally supported conception of justice in advanced societies is that of equal opportunity. What does this mean, and how can it be formalized? The first treatment of this problem in social choice theory involved interpreting equality of opportunity as equality of opportunity sets, that is, rendering the sets of choices available to di¤erent individuals the same. In my view, this literature was too abstract – it failed to take su‰cient cues from popular and long-standing conceptions of equality of opportunity. A consequence of this over-abstractness is that no empirical work, on what equal-opportunity policies should be in real-world situations, has followed from this work, as far as I am aware. Those popular conceptions have, in contrast, influenced greatly the recent literature in egalitarian political philosophy, particularly the idea that in the equal-opportunity ethic, there is, as well as a desire to equalize something, an insistence that individuals be held responsible for what happens to them. This is popularly formulated in the ‘level-the-playing-field’ metaphor: equal- opportunity policy must create a level playing field, after which each individ- ual is on his own – what outcomes finally occur will reflect individual e¤ort, and outcome di¤erentials are ethically acceptable, if the playing field was ini- tially level, and if they are due to di¤erential e¤ort. John Rawls (1971), in his path-breaking work, certainly understood, and supported, the idea that the social mandate to equalize outcomes across indi- I am grateful to my collaborators, listed in the references, for permitting me to report some of the results of our joint work in this paper, which was read as the Arrow Lec- ture at the bi-annual meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare, in Alicante, July 2000. 456 J. E. Roemer viduals was rightfully constrained by how responsibly individuals had behaved, but his model of souls contracting behind the veil of ignorance failed to cap- ture the intuitions correctly (see Roemer 1996, Chapt. 5). Ronald Dworkin, in two articles published in 1981, came much closer to getting it right. Dworkin (1981a,b) distinguished between a person’s preferences and his resources, where the latter comprised endowments which the individual had no role in choosing. He argued that the ethically attractive notion of equality entailed equalizing resources across individuals, but allowing di¤erences to emerge in final conditions due to the exercise of choice following from di¤erential pref- erences: thus, Dworkin said people should be held responsible for their pref- erences but not their resources. A moment’s thought will convince you that it is not so easy to make the cut between preferences and resources, at least if one wants preferences to be attributes for which the individual is rightly held responsible. (For example, resources clearly influence preference formation, so if one is not responsible for resources like family background, should one be responsible for exercising preferences induced by childhood nurture?) Never- theless, Dworkin’s contribution was path-breaking, and other philosophers took Dworkin’s work further. Dworkin even proposed an economic model of his idea, what economists would call a market for contingent claims behind a veil of ignorance conceived di¤erently from Rawls’s, in which souls know the preferences of the persons with whom they are associated, but not the resource bundles those persons will receive in the birth lottery. The general structure of Dworkin’s theory is that a person’s attributes (endowments, preferences, actions) can be partitioned into two sets – those for which we think it is morally correct to hold him accountable or responsible, and those for which we think it is not so. Call the first set responsible factors and the second, arbitrary factors. An egalitarian should seek to equalize the final conditions (perhaps, welfares) of individuals to the extent that those con- ditions are due to di¤erences in the sets of arbitrary factors, but allow di¤er- ences in condition to the extent that such are due to di¤erences in responsible factors. It is this conception of ‘responsible’ and ‘arbitrary’ factors which, I think, is key to the notion of equal opportunity. I will now adopt a somewhat less general approach, and say that the outcomes individuals sustain are the con- sequence of circumstances, e¤ort, and policy, where circumstances are aspects of an individual’s environment and actions which are either beyond his con- trol, or for which we (society) wish not to hold him responsible, e¤ort com- prises the actions he takes for which we do wish to hold him responsible, and policy is the instrument by which society (or the planner) influences outcomes – perhaps some allocation of a publicly owned resource. Equal-opportunity policy aims to level the playing field. What are the troughs in that metaphor- ical playing field? They are the disadvantages that some persons face, with regard to achieving high levels of welfare – or, more generally, the condition about which the planner is concerned – due to unfortunate circumstances. Thus, leveling the playing field means choosing that policy that will make it the case that an individual’s final condition will be, as far as possible, only a Equality of opportunity 457 function of the e¤ort he makes. In particular, equality of opportunity finds no moral bad in inequality of final condition across individuals ascribable to dif- ferential e¤ort. In this way, it di¤ers from the equality-of-outcome ethic. 2 A formalization We can formalize this view as follows. Suppose the condition for which we desire to equalize opportunities – the opportunity equalisandum – is measured by a function uðC; e; jÞ, where C denotes the individual’s circumstances, e his e¤ort, and j the policy of the intervening agency or planner. u need not mea- sure welfare in the economist’s sense: it could be income, or life expectancy, or wage-earning capacity. I further specialize by assuming that an individual’s type is the value of his C, that the population has a finite number of types, and that there is a continuum of individuals in each type. From now on, we denote types 1; 2; ...; t, with the generic element t. We denote the set of types by T, and the set of feasible policies by F. We assume, as well, that, for any policy j implemented by the planner, t there will be a distribution of e¤ort in each type, denoted by Fj, which is a probability measure on the set of non-negative real numbers – the domain of e¤ort. (Thus, we here make another assumption, that e¤ort can be captured by a one dimensional variable.) Letting P be the set of probability distribu- tions on Rþ, we take the mapping F : T Â F ! P as a primitive of the model. An economist would say that e¤ort responses are the consequence of utility maximization facing policies, but that does not here concern us, and there is no reason to further complexify by modeling that process. Let me give two examples. Let u be wage earning capacity, a person’s type be the socio-economic status (SES) of his parents, e¤ort be the number of years of school he attends, and policy be the per-pupil educational expendi- tures of the state, which, we assume, may be varied according to the socio- economic characteristics of the neighborhood in which the school is located. In this conception, we do not hold a person responsible for his parents’ SES, but we do hold him responsible for the number of years of school he attends. Equal-opportunity policy entails distributing an educational budget among schools so that, so far as possible, the wages individuals eventually earn are, on average, equal across SES types of child who attended school similar numbers of years. Intuitively, that policy would spend more per pupil in low SES neighborhoods than in high SES neighborhoods. The policy would be used to compensate individuals with disadvantaged circumstances so that, finally, at each level of school attendance, the wages of individuals, in the various types, would be equal. Here is a second example. Let u be life expectancy, type be, again, the eco- nomic class of the parents of the individual, e¤ort be a measure of ‘life-style quality,’ in the sense of exercising, eating healthily, not smoking, and so on, and policy be some allocation of medical care services to the population. Here, the equal-opportunity goal is to choose the policy so that the life expectancies of 458 J. E. Roemer individuals of di¤erent types are equal for cohorts of those types whose mem- bers have lived equally healthy life-styles. Of course, the distribution of e¤ort within a type, in these two examples, may well respond to the policy, which is why we predicated that distribution, above, on both the type and the policy. There is, however, an inconsistency between the model, as I have thus far described it, and the intent of the modeler. Everyone knows that the distribu- tion of e¤ort is, indeed, a characteristic of the type. If schools spend $5000 per student on upper middle class children, we will observe a di¤erent distribution of years of school completed, our proposed e¤ort measure, than if they spend the same amount on poor, ghetto children.
Recommended publications
  • Political Ideas and Movements That Created the Modern World
    harri+b.cov 27/5/03 4:15 pm Page 1 UNDERSTANDINGPOLITICS Understanding RITTEN with the A2 component of the GCE WGovernment and Politics A level in mind, this book is a comprehensive introduction to the political ideas and movements that created the modern world. Underpinned by the work of major thinkers such as Hobbes, Locke, Marx, Mill, Weber and others, the first half of the book looks at core political concepts including the British and European political issues state and sovereignty, the nation, democracy, representation and legitimacy, freedom, equality and rights, obligation and citizenship. The role of ideology in modern politics and society is also discussed. The second half of the book addresses established ideologies such as Conservatism, Liberalism, Socialism, Marxism and Nationalism, before moving on to more recent movements such as Environmentalism and Ecologism, Fascism, and Feminism. The subject is covered in a clear, accessible style, including Understanding a number of student-friendly features, such as chapter summaries, key points to consider, definitions and tips for further sources of information. There is a definite need for a text of this kind. It will be invaluable for students of Government and Politics on introductory courses, whether they be A level candidates or undergraduates. political ideas KEVIN HARRISON IS A LECTURER IN POLITICS AND HISTORY AT MANCHESTER COLLEGE OF ARTS AND TECHNOLOGY. HE IS ALSO AN ASSOCIATE McNAUGHTON LECTURER IN SOCIAL SCIENCES WITH THE OPEN UNIVERSITY. HE HAS WRITTEN ARTICLES ON POLITICS AND HISTORY AND IS JOINT AUTHOR, WITH TONY BOYD, OF THE BRITISH CONSTITUTION: EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION? and TONY BOYD WAS FORMERLY HEAD OF GENERAL STUDIES AT XAVERIAN VI FORM COLLEGE, MANCHESTER, WHERE HE TAUGHT POLITICS AND HISTORY.
    [Show full text]
  • Unit 5 Equality
    UNIT 5 EQUALITY Structure 5.1 Introduction 5.2 Equality vs. Inequality 5.2.1 Struggle for Equality 5.3 What is Equality? 5.4 Dimensions of Equality 5.4.1 Legal Equality 5.4.2 Political Equality 5.4.3 Economic Equality 5.4.4 Social Equality 5.5 Relation of Equality with Liberty and Justice 5.5.1 Equality and Liberty As Opposed To Each Other 5.5.2 Equality and Liberty Are Complementary To Each Other 5.5.3 Equality and Justice 5.6 Towards Equality 5.7 Plea for Inequality in the Contemporary World 5.8 Marxist Concept of Equality 5.9 Summary 5.10 Exercises 5.1 INTRODUCTION Of all the basic concepts of social, economic, moral and political philosophy, none is more confusing and baffling than the concept of equality because it figures in all other concepts like justice, liberty, rights, property, etc. During the last two thousand years, many dimensions of equality have been elaborated by Greeks, Stoics, Christian fathers who separately and collectively stressed on its one or the other aspect. Under the impact of liberalism and Marxism, equality acquired an altogether different connotation. Contemporary social movements like feminism, environmentalism are trying to give a new meaning to this concept. Basically, equality is a value and a principle essentially modern and progressive. Though the debate about equality has been going on for centuries, the special feature of modern societies is that we no longer take inequality for granted or something natural. Equality is also used as a measure of what is modern and the whole process of modernisation in the form of political egalitarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Concepts of Inequality Development Issues No
    Development Strategy and Policy Analysis Unit w Development Policy and Analysis Division Department of Economic and Social Affairs Concepts of Inequality Development Issues No. 1 21 October 2015 Inequality—the state of not being equal, especially in status, rights, and opportunities1—is a concept very much at the heart Summary of social justice theories. However, it is prone to confusion in public debate as it tends to mean different things to different The understanding of inequality has evolved from the people. Some distinctions are common though. Many authors traditional outcome-oriented view, whereby income is distinguish “economic inequality”, mostly meaning “income used as a proxy for well-being. The opportunity-oriented inequality”, “monetary inequality” or, more broadly, inequality perspective acknowledges that circumstances of birth are in “living conditions”. Others further distinguish a rights-based, essential to life outcomes and that equality of opportunity legalistic approach to inequality—inequality of rights and asso- requires a fair starting point for all. ciated obligations (e.g. when people are not equal before the law, or when people have unequal political power). Concerning economic inequality, much of the discussion has on poverty reduction. Pro-poor growth approaches made their boiled down to two views. One is chiefly concerned with the debut and growth and equity (through income redistribution) inequality of outcomes in the material dimensions of well-being were seen as separate policy instruments, each capable of address- and that may be the result of circumstances beyond one’s control ing poverty. The central concern was in raising the incomes of (ethnicity, family background, gender, and so on) as well as talent poor households.
    [Show full text]
  • Quong-Left-Libertarianism.Pdf
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64–89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University of Manchester HAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this Wquestion must find a way of incorporating and reconciling two moral ideas. The first is a particular conception of individual freedom: because we are agents with plans and projects, we should be accorded a sphere of liberty to protect us from being used as mere means for others’ ends. The second moral idea is that of equality: we are moral equals and as such justice requires either that we receive equal shares of something—of whatever it is that should be used as the metric of distributive justice—or else requires that unequal distributions can be justified in a manner that is consistent with the moral equality of persons. These twin ideas—liberty and equality—are things which no sound conception of justice can properly ignore. Thus, like most political philosophers, I take it as given that the correct conception of justice will be some form of liberal egalitarianism. A deep and difficult challenge for all liberal egalitarians is to determine how the twin values of freedom and equality can be reconciled within a single theory of distributive justice. Of the many attempts to achieve this reconciliation, left-libertarianism is one of the most attractive and compelling. By combining the libertarian commitment to full (or nearly full) self-ownership with an egalitarian principle for the ownership of natural resources, left- libertarians offer an account of justice that appears firmly committed both to individual liberty, and to an egalitarian view of how opportunities or advantages must be distributed.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Why Not Capitalism? Richard J. Arneson [This Is the Not-Quite-Final Version of an Essay Published in Distributive Justice
    1 Why Not Capitalism? Richard J. Arneson [This is the not-quite-final version of an essay published in Distributive Justice and Access to Advantage, Alexander Kaufman, ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), pp., 207-234.] Should egalitarians oppose the idea of a capitalist market economy? This is an extremely vague and ambiguous question, but also an extremely important one. If left- wing ideas are to have a justified popularity, left-wingers should be clear as to what they are for and what they are against. If there is an egalitarian radicalism that offers a distinctive and plausible alternative to the philosophical liberal egalitarianisms of theorists such as John Rawls, Ronald Dworkin, Amartya Sen, and Thomas Nagel, egalitarian radicals need to articulate their rival vision. Anyone wrestling with these issues today owes an enormous intellectual debt to the late G. A. Cohen. For many years he worked with great success to determine what is living and what is dead in the thinking of Karl Marx, what exactly is wrong with the Lockean libertarianism of Robert Nozick, and why the grand social justice theory of John Rawls should be rejected despite its grandeur. Toward the end of his life he reworked an essay originally published in 2001 into a very short book, Why Not Socialism? The book directly addresses the vague and ambiguous question stated just above. Cohen suggests that when we reflect on the idea of an ideal camping trip among friends and consider (1) how it should be organized and (2) what is the content of the moral principles that the imagined camping trip satisfies, we get a conditional argument for a certain socialist organization of society.
    [Show full text]
  • After the New Social Democracy Offers a Distinctive Contribution to Political Ideas
    fitzpatrick cvr 8/8/03 11:10 AM Page 1 Social democracy has made a political comeback in recent years, After thenewsocialdemocracy especially under the influence of the Third Way. However, not everyone is convinced that this ‘new social democracy’ is the best means of reviving the Left’s social project. This book explains why and offers an alternative approach. Bringing together a range of social and political theories After the After the new new social democracy engages with some of the most important contemporary debates regarding the present direction and future of the Left. Drawing upon egalitarian, feminist and environmental social democracy ideas it proposes that the social democratic tradition can be renewed but only if the dominance of conservative ideas is challenged more effectively. It explores a number of issues with this aim in mind, including justice, the state, democracy, welfare reform, new technologies, future generations and the new genetics. Employing a lively and authoritative style After the new social democracy offers a distinctive contribution to political ideas. It will appeal to all of those interested in politics, philosophy, social policy and social studies. Social welfare for the Tony Fitzpatrick is a Senior Lecturer in the School of Sociology and Social twenty-first century Policy, University of Nottingham. FITZPATRICK TONY FITZPATRICK TZPPR 4/25/2005 4:45 PM Page i After the new social democracy TZPPR 4/25/2005 4:45 PM Page ii For my parents TZPPR 4/25/2005 4:45 PM Page iii After the new social democracy Social welfare for the twenty-first century TONY FITZPATRICK Manchester University Press Manchester and New York distributed exclusively in the USA by Palgrave TZPPR 4/25/2005 4:45 PM Page iv Copyright © Tony Fitzpatrick 2003 The right of Tony Fitzpatrick to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. A LeftLeft----LibertarianLibertarian Theory of Rights Arabella Millett Fisher PhD University of Edinburgh 2011 Contents Abstract....................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements.......................................................................................................v Declaration.................................................................................................................. vi Introduction..................................................................................................................1 Part I: A Libertarian Theory of Justice...................................................................11
    [Show full text]
  • Why Tax Wealth Transfers?: a Philosophical Analysis
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Law Faculty Scholarly Articles Law Faculty Publications 2016 Why Tax Wealth Transfers?: A Philosophical Analysis Jennifer Bird-Pollan University of Kentucky College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/law_facpub Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, Taxation-Federal Estate and Gift Commons, and the Tax Law Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Repository Citation Bird-Pollan, Jennifer, "Why Tax Wealth Transfers?: A Philosophical Analysis" (2016). Law Faculty Scholarly Articles. 582. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/law_facpub/582 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Faculty Publications at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Law Faculty Scholarly Articles by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Why Tax Wealth Transfers?: A Philosophical Analysis Notes/Citation Information Jennifer Bird-Pollan, Why Tax Wealth Transfers?: A Philosophical Analysis, 57 B.C. L. Rev. 859 (2016). This article is available at UKnowledge: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/law_facpub/582 WHY TAX WEALTH TRANSFERS?: A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS JENNIFER BIRD-POLLAN Abstract: The one-hundredth anniversary of the estate tax provides an ideal moment to reflect on the role of wealth transfer taxation in the larger scheme of the U.S. tax system. Wealth and income inequality are at historically high levels, and the responses to these issues are often reduced to a simplistic polit- ical dichotomy of "right" versus "left." The multitude of views of the Ameri- can people cannot be reduced to such simple generalities without losing im- portant nuances.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Left Egalitarian Embrace of Equal Opportunity and Its Problems
    The Left Egalitarian Embrace of Equal Opportunity and its Problems Peter Breiner University at Albany, State University of New York [email protected] “’So, is it good to be rich?’ 'Yes, if you make it the hard way … It’s not for me to pass moral judgment.’” “While there’s capitalism, there’ll be socialism, because there is always a response to injustice.” Ed Miliband, leader of the Labour Party, From an Interview, Daily Telegraph Sept 15, 2012. In an interview from 2012 Ed Miliband leader of the British Labour Party displays the fundamental problem in the recent embrace by left parties and left political leaders of equality of opportunity. On the one hand Miliband articulates the defining principle of the left politically—an awareness that capitalism leads to injustice and inequality of assets and control while the socialist argument has always centered on a defense of equality of distribution and the treatment of all members of society with equal respect separate from the roles that they play. On the other hand, he embraces the notion that there is a way for individuals to become rich, through effort and hard work, which is morally neutral. The essence of this seemingly muddled view is an attempt to square the circle between the justice of equality of distribution of essential goods and an embrace of equal opportunity of a certain kind—one that is beyond moral judgment because the competitive process is ostensibly open and fair and the outcome the result of initiative and effort. This embrace of equal opportunity simultaneous with an acknowledgment that socialism points to the injustices of capitalism seems to rest on a further questionable distinction between getting rich the hard way, presumably purely by one’s own 1 effort and talents and thus deserved, and getting rich the easy way, presumably by good fortune or good circumstances, or through non-productive activity such as speculation and thus undeserved.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Socialist Equality of Opportunity
    Filosofi C 2015 Handledare: Lars Lindblom Institutionen för idé- & samhällsstudier Umeå Universitet VT 15 The Structure of Socialist Equality of Opportunity G. A. COHEN’S SOCIALISM: A DEFENCE MÅNS PETTERSSON 1 Table of Contents Introduction ............................................................................................................................................. 2 Scanlon on the Diversity of Objections to Inequality.............................................................................. 3 Delineating the Disagreements: What is the Point of Equality?.............................................................. 5 Social Relations Egalitarianism ......................................................................................................... 12 Democratic Equality vs. Luck Egalitarianism: a Fundamental Objection ........................................ 14 Luck Egalitarianism: a Defense............................................................................................................. 18 Marxism and Materialism ................................................................................................................. 20 Socialism: Justice, Freedom and Exploitation ................................................................................... 25 Concluding Remarks ............................................................................................................................. 32 References ............................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Social Democracy and Neoliberalism: Beyond Sibling Rivalry
    Global Policy, February 2018 Social Democracy and Neoliberalism: Beyond Sibling Rivalry Steve Fuller University of Warwick Abstract The failure of ‘progressivism’ to gain traction in the current political landscape can be diagnosed in many ways. The diagnosis pursued here, partly in response to a set of recent debates, is that social democracy and neoliberalism have been artificially divided by the spectre of Marxism. But now that Marxism is no longer a serious geopolitical force (though it remains quite potent in academia), the time is ripe for the two ‘centre-left’ movements to come together by recovering their common Fabian heritage, which stresses the value of social experimentation. Policy Recommendations • Marxism should no longer be regarded as the polestar of Left-leaning politics. This point is already reflected in the actions of most politicians and policymakers today, but it needs to be embraced by the academic community if its opinions are to have any relevance in today’s political arena. • The shift away from Marx should be made in the context of reconciling the differences between ‘social democracy’ and ‘neoliberalism’, two technocratic forms of state capitalism that draw their inspiration from British Fabianism but have been increasingly seen by academics as polar opposites. This infighting, typically mediated by some phantom conception of Marxism, has contributed to the Left’s blindsiding by the rise of ‘populism’. • Fabianism’s strength in this renewed context is that it approaches technological innovation from the standpoint of enabling greater flexibility in terms of social organization, combined with more intensive interest in data collection. These provide the structural preconditions for inducing a sort of ‘super-liberal’ attitude at the administrative level that encourages systematic social experimentation, for which Karl Popper originally applied the clunky phrase, ‘piecemeal social engineering’.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Science Master's Thesis 18494 Words Dr Nicholas Vrousalis
    1 David Minear Master’s Thesis David Minear (S1441973) Leiden University: Political Science Master’s Thesis 18494 words Dr Nicholas Vrousalis Libertarianism without inequality or inconsistency: a critical examination of Peter Vallentyne and Michael Otsuka 2 David Minear Master’s Thesis Contents Having your cake and eating it too ...................................................................................................... 3 1 Robert Nozick on self-ownership and equality ................................................................................ 5 1.1 Entitlement Theory ..................................................................................................................... 5 1.2 Self-ownership ............................................................................................................................. 6 1.3 Lockean Proviso ........................................................................................................................... 7 1.4 Patterns ........................................................................................................................................ 8 1.5 Value of Nozick............................................................................................................................. 9 2 G.A. Cohen’s critique of Nozick .......................................................................................................... 9 2.1 Effective Autonomy ..................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]