The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism springer.com Philosophy : Philosophy of Science Milkov, Nikolay, Peckhaus, Volker (Eds.) The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism First discussion of the Berlin Group in a book form in English First three chapters on Dubislav in English and one on Paul Oppenheim Reassesses the role of the Vienna Circle in the development of the scientific philosophy The Berlin Group for scientific philosophy was active between 1928 and 1933 and was closely related to the Vienna Circle. In 1930, the leaders of the two Groups, Hans Reichenbach and Rudolf Carnap, launched the journal Erkenntnis. However, between the Berlin Group and the Springer Vienna Circle, there was not only close relatedness but also significant difference. Above all, 2013, X, 332 p. 2 illus. while the Berlin Group explored philosophical problems of the actual practice of science, the 1st Vienna Circle, closely following Wittgenstein, was more interested in problems of the language edition of science. The book includes first discussion ever (in three chapters) on Walter Dubislav’s logic and philosophy. Two chapters are devoted to another author scarcely explored in English, Kurt Grelling, and another one to Paul Oppenheim who became an important figure in the Printed book philosophy of science in the USA in the 1940s–1960s. Finally, the book discusses the Hardcover precursor of the Nord-German tradition of scientific philosophy, Jacob Friedrich Fries. Printed book Hardcover Order online at springer.com/booksellers ISBN 978-94-007-5484-3 Springer Nature Customer Service Center GmbH Customer Service £ 109,99 | CHF 141,50 | 119,99 € | Tiergartenstrasse 15-17 131,99 € (A) | 128,39 € (D) 69121 Heidelberg Available Germany Discount group T: +49 (0)6221 345-4301 Science (SC) [email protected] Product category Contributed volume Series Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science Other renditions Softcover ISBN 978-94-007-9209-8 Softcover ISBN 978-94-007-5486-7 Prices and other details are subject to change without notice. All errors and omissions excepted. Americas: Tax will be added where applicable. Canadian residents please add PST, QST or GST. Please add $5.00 for shipping one book and $ 1.00 for each additional book. Outside the US and Canada add $ 10.00 for first book, $5.00 for each additional book. If an order cannot be fulfilled within 90 days, payment will be refunded upon request. Prices are payable in US currency or its equivalent. ISBN 978-94-007-5484-3 / BIC: PDA / SPRINGER NATURE: SCE34000 Part of .
Recommended publications
  • Guide to Proper Names and References in Gödel's “Protokolle
    Guide to proper names and references in Gödel’s “Protokolle” notebook People Abel Othenio Abel (1875-1946) professor of paleontology and paleobiology at the University of Vienna. Founder of the group of professors known as the “Bärenhöhle” that blocked the appointment and promotion of Jews Adele Adele Nimbursky, née Porkert (1899–1981), Gödel’s girlfriend, separated from her first husband; she and Gödel would marry in September 1938 Bachmann Friedrich Bachmann (1909–1982), mathematician, doctoral student of Scholz’s at Münster, where he received his Ph.D. in 1933; from 1935 at University of Marburg, as assistant then Privatdozent Behmann Heinrich Behmann (1891–1970), German mathematician; his reply to Perelman’s criticism of Gödel’s result had appeared in the journal Mind in April 1937. He was dismissed from his position at ​ ​ the University of Halle after the war for his Nazi Party activities Beer Gustav Beer, member of the Vienna Circle and Menger’s Mathematical Colloquium Benjamin Abram Cornelius Benjamin (1897–1968), American philosopher of science on the University of Chicago faculty 1932 to 1945 Bernays Paul Bernays (1888–1977), Swiss mathematician and logician; close collaborator with David Hilbert on the foundations of mathematics and the axiomatization of set theory Brentano Franz Brentano (1838-1917), resigned as priest, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, founder of Gestalt Brunsvick Egon Brunswik (1903–1955), Hungarian-born psychologist, assistant to Karl Bühler in Vienna, active member of Otto Neurath’s “Unity of Science” movement Bühler Karl Bühler (1879–1963), professor of psychology at the University of Vienna. He led an effort to reorganize Vienna’s city schools by incorporating scientific findings from child psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Philosophy and the Dynamics of Reason
    Scientific Philosophy and the Dynamics of Reason Michael Friedman Stanford University Scientific philosophy—in the sense of an attempt to revolutionize philosophy as a whole and as a discipline under the guidance of such an idea—is a characteristically twentieth century phenomenon, but, like so many aspects of twentieth century culture, it has deep roots in the nineteenth century. In particular, the idea of a scientific philosophy first arose in the second half of the nineteenth century, as a self-conscious intellectual reaction to what was then perceived as the “speculative” and “metaphysical” excesses of post-Kantian German idealism. In this context, a number of late nineteenth century natural scientists and mathematicians, faced with radically new problems within the shifting intellectual foundations of their own disciplines, turned to philosophy for conceptual resources. Repelled by the speculative metaphysics of post-Kantian idealism, they looked in what they took to be healthier philosophical directions—partly towards a return to the more sober, more scientifically oriented philosophizing of Kant himself, and partly towards a parallel return to the earlier anti-metaphysical stance represented by British empiricism. But the late nineteenth century scientific thinkers in question— principally Hermann von Helmholtz, Ernst Mach, and Henri Poincaré—were also faced with the problem of adapting such earlier philosophical ideas to a revolutionary new situation within the mathematical and physical sciences. Both Kantianism and empiricism had now to be adjusted to the development of non-Euclidean geometries, closely related fundamental changes in logic and the foundations of mathematics, the emergence of physiology and psycho-physics as experimental scientific disciplines, and novel, non-Newtonian styles of physical theorizing in such new areas as thermodynamics, the statistical-molecular theory of matter, and electro-magnetism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism BOSTON STUDIES in the PHILOSOPHY and HISTORY of SCIENCE
    The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY AND HISTORY OF SCIENCE Editors ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University JURGEN¨ RENN, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science KOSTAS GAVROGLU, University of Athens Managing Editor LINDY DIVARCI, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Editorial Board THEODORE ARABATZIS, University of Athens ALISA BOKULICH, Boston University HEATHER E. DOUGLAS, University of Pittsburgh JEAN GAYON, Universit´eParis1 THOMAS F. GLICK, Boston University HUBERT GOENNER, University of Goettingen JOHN HEILBRON, University of California, Berkeley DIANA KORMOS-BUCHWALD, California Institute of Technology CHRISTOPH LEHNER, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science PETER MCLAUGHLIN, Universit¨at Heidelberg AGUSTI´ NIETO-GALAN, Universitat Aut`onoma de Barcelona NUCCIO ORDINE, Universit´a della Calabria ANA SIMOES,˜ Universidade de Lisboa JOHN J. STACHEL, Boston University SYLVAN S. SCHWEBER, Harvard University BAICHUN ZHANG, Chinese Academy of Science VOLUME 273 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/5710 Nikolay Milkov • Volker Peckhaus Editors The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism 123 Editors Nikolay Milkov Volker Peckhaus Department of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Paderborn University of Paderborn 33098 Paderborn 33098 Paderborn Germany Germany ISSN 0068-0346 ISBN 978-94-007-5484-3 ISBN 978-94-007-5485-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg New York London Library of Congress
    [Show full text]
  • Vienna Circle Institute Library
    Vienna Circle Institute Library Volume 4 Series editor Friedrich Stadler University of Vienna, Institute Vienna Circle, Wien, Austria Institut Wiener Kreis Society for the Advancement of the Scientifi c World Conception Advisory Editorial Board: Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, Otto Pfersmann, Université Paris I Panthéon – France Sorbonne, France Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Miklós Rédei, London School of Economics, UK Nancy Cartwright, London School of Alan Richardson, University of British Economics, UK Columbia, CDN Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Gerhard Schurz, University of Düsseldorf, Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Germany Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Peter Schuster, University of Vienna, Austria Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Karl Sigmund, University of Vienna, Austria Italy Hans Sluga, University of California at Berkeley, Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Elliott Sober, University of Wisconsin, USA Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Antonia Soulez, Université de Paris 8, France Germany Wolfgang Spohn, University of Konstanz, Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Germany Thomas E. Uebel, University of Manchester, UK Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Pierre Wagner, Université de Paris 1, Sorbonne, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, France Germany C. Kenneth Waters, University of Minnesota, USA Clemens Jabloner,
    [Show full text]
  • Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus (Eds.): the Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 273
    556 B OOK R EVIEWS Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus (eds.): The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 273. Springer, Dordrecht, 2013, x+332 pages During the last few decades, historians and philosophers of science radically changed our perspective on logical empiricism in general, and on the Vienna Circle in particular. Though there are still some members of the Circle who did not get much attention (Victor Kraft, Richard von Mises, Felix Kaufmann, Josef Schächter etc.), we are in a quite good position to judge many of their efforts. On the other hand, our historical understanding of logical empiricism in general leaves some- thing to be desired due to the circumstances that the so-called “Berlin Group” is underestimated in the literature. The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism, edited by Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus, is meant to bring attention to the German wing of logical empiricism, thus doing justice to that forgotten projects and figures who had (in)directly an important influence on the philosophy of science in the United States after World War II. Among the most important members, one finds Hans Reichenbach, Kurt Grelling, Walter Dubislav, Paul Oppenheim, Olaf Helmer, Kurt Lewin, and Carl Gustav Hempel. The collection is devoted to their ideas and con- text in the European philosophy of science scene. Part 1 is an introductory chapter composed of two papers: a longer article by Nikolay Milkov about the ‘affinities and divergences’ between the Vienna Circle and the Berlin Group. Though Milkov provides many important details and no- tions, his explanations are lacking sometimes, but I will come back to that later.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Dubislav's Philosophy of Science and Mathematics1
    Walter Dubislav’s Philosophy of Science and Mathematics1 ―Dubislav … knew more about mathematical and logistical [logical] matters and the ‗theory of theories‘ [philosophy of science] than anybody I met.‖ Karl Korsch, letter to Morton Wurtele, February 19, 1953 (Korsch 2001, ix, 1500) Summary Walter Dubislav (1895–1937) was a leading member of the Berlin Group for Empirical / Scientific Philosophy. This ―sister group‖ of the more famous Vienna Circle emerged around Hans Reichenbach‘s seminars at the University of Berlin in 1927 and 1928. Du- bislav was to collaborate with Reichenbach, an association that eventuated in their con- jointly conducting university seminars. Sadly, the political changes in Germany in 1933 proved ruinous to Dubislav. He published scarcely anything after Hitler came to power and in 1937 committed suicide under tragic circumstances. The intent here is to pass in review Dubislav‘s philosophy of logic, mathematics, and science. The point of this expo- sition is to shed light on some seminal yet hitherto largely neglected currents in the history of philosophy of science. 1. Exact Philosophy by Kant and Fries 1 For a profile of Dubislav‘s life in connection with his works, see the author‘s. … Our Acknowledgements go to the participants on two seminars that we hold at the University of 1 Unlike the majority of the logical empiricists, Dubislav was a distinguished historian of logic and philosophy.2 He had explored the logical theories of Blaise Pascal, Leibniz, and Bernard Bolzano, among others.3 But his interest centered above all on Kant and Jacob Friedrich Fries. Dubislav regarded these philosophers as especially important because both did original and highly influential work in the substantiation (Begründung) of human knowledge and in concept-formation, topics central to his formalist philosophy of mathe- matics and science.
    [Show full text]
  • Phd in Philosophy
    PhD in Philosophy CYCLE XXXII COORDINATOR Prof. Adriano Fabris Hermann Lotze on the Mind–Body Problem and the 19th Century Philosophy and Psychology: With Special Attention to William James Academic Discipline (SSD) M-FIL/06 Doctoral Candidate Supervisors Michele Vagnetti Prof. Alessandro Pagnini Apl. Prof. Dr. Nikolay Milkov Coordinator Prof. Fabris Adriano Years 2017/2020 CONTENTS 1. Preliminary remarks on Hermann Lotze’s metaphysics 1 1.1. Lotze on science and metaphysics 1 1.2. Lotze’s atomism 6 1.3. Philosophy of space: metaphysics and geometry 12 2. Physiological and psychological studies in the first half of the 19th century 26 2.1. The study of the nervous system 26 2.2. Hermann Lotze on phrenology and the question of the location of the mind 35 2.3. Three scientific psychologists 39 2.3.1. Ernst Heinrich Weber 39 2.3.2. Gustav Theodor Fechner 44 2.3.3. Alfred Wilhelm Volkmann 53 3. The reductionist approach to the mind–body problem and its critics 54 3.1. Hermann von Helmholtz 56 3.2. The dispute between Büchner and Lotze 60 3.3. Two further scholars 64 3.3.1. J. F. Herbart 64 3.3.2. J. F. Fries 69 4. Hermann Lotze on the relation between body and mind 78 4.1. Pilosophical psychology and perspectivism 86 4.2. Physiological psychology between materialism and mentalism 94 4.3. The psycho-physical mechanism: the occasionalist way 103 I 4.4. The psycho-physical mechanism: the interaction 110 4.5. Lotze’s theory of local signs 113 4.6.
    [Show full text]
  • The Berlin School of Logical Empiricism and Its Legacy
    Nicholas Rescher July 6, 2006 THE BERLIN SCHOOL OF LOGICAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS LEGACY 1. BACKGROUND What has become generally known as the Berlin School of Logical Empiricism constitutes a philosophical movement that was based in Berlin’s Gesellschaft fuer empirische Philosophie and erected on foundations laid by Albert Einstein. His revolutionary work in physics had a profound impact on philosophers interested in scientific issues, prominent among them Paul Oppenheim and Hans Reichenbach, the founding fathers of the school, who joined in viewing him as their hero among philosopher-scientists. Overall the membership of this school falls into three groups, as per Display 1.1 The founding generation was linked by the circumstance that both Grelling and Reichenbach were collaborators of Oppenheim; the middle generation by the fact that both Hempel and Helmer were students of Reichenbach’s in Berlin; and the younger generation by the fact that all of its members were students and (at least in their early years) disciples either of Reichenbach or of Hempel in the USA. Three stages are thus at issue: an initial phase in Berlin, a transatlantic migration, and a continuation in the U.S.A.—principally in Pittsburgh. 1 Various other people were involved in the Berlin School in a more peripheral way. A detailed account of its early days in Berlin (roughly 1927 to 1933) is given in Dieter Hoffman’s contribution to Dannenberg et. al. 1994, entitled “Zur Geschichte der Berliner Gesellschaft für empirisch/wissenschaftliche Philosophie.” 2 ___________________________________________________ Display 1 THE BERLIN SCHOOL I. THE FOUNDING GENERATION • Paul Oppenheim (1885-1977) • Kurt Grelling (1886-1942) • Hans Reichenbach (1891-1953) • Walter Dubislav (1895-1937) II.
    [Show full text]
  • Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague
    Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague Adam Tamas Tuboly Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences; University of Pécs, Pécs, Hungary [email protected] 1 Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague1 1. Introduction When Carnap wrote a short intellectual autobiography for Marcel Boll in March 1933, he mentioned two things about Prague: (1) that he became a professor at the German University in 1931, and (2) that he worked on his Logische Syntax der Sprache until 1933.2 These things are well known. Carnap spent, however, five long years in Prague, just like he did before in Vienna: so, one might ask, whether (1) and (2) indeed sufficiently characterize his Prague- period. Philipp Frank (1949, 45), who was there for almost twenty years when Carnap arrived, wrote that “[f]rom 1931 on we [i.e. Frank and Carnap] had in this way a new center of ‘scientific world conception’ at the University of Prague.” This seems to be much more than what Carnap claimed. Actually Carnap might have had great expectations regarding Prague: the First Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences, where the Vienna Circle made public its manifesto, was organized by Frank there in 1929; five years later in 1934 the Preliminary Conference of the International Congresses for the Unity of Science was hosted again in Prague. As Jan Sebestik (1994, 205) claimed, “Prague has always been one of the important European centres of learning and of science, and it has often been the forerunner of vast currents or movements, both intellectual and political.” The city also had a long tradition of scientifically oriented philosophical thinking: through Bernard Bolzano, members of the Brentano-School (such as Anton Marty, Tomáš G.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat.
    [Show full text]
  • The Old and the New 'Erkenntnis'
    Erkenntnis 9, 1-4, 1975 D.Reidel Publishing Company Dordrecht-Holland CARL G. HEMPEL THE OLD AND THE NEW ©ERKENNTNIS© In this first issue of the new Erkenntnis, it seems fitting to recall at least briefly the character and the main achievements of its distinguished namesake and predecessor. The old Erkenntnis came into existence when Hans Reichenbach and Rudolf Carnap as- sumed the editorship of the Annalen der Philosophie and gave the journal its new title and its characteristic orientation; the first issue appeared in 1930. The journal was backed by the Ge- sellschaft f r Empirische Philosophie in Berlin, in which Reichenbach, Walter Dubislav, and Kurt Grelling were the leading figures, and by the Verein Ernst Mach in Vienna, whose philo- sophical position was strongly influenced by that of the Vienna Circle; a brief account of these groups, and of several kindred schools and trends of scientific and philosophical think- ing, was given by Otto Neurath in his ©Historische Anmerkungen© (Vol. 1, pp. 311-314). As Reichenbach noted in his introduction to the first issue, the editors of Erkenntnis were concerned to carry on philosophical inquiry in close consideration of the procedures and re- sults of the various scientific disciplines: analysis of scientific research and its presupposi- tions was expected to yield insight into the character of all human knowledge, while at the same time, the objectivity and the progressive character of science inspired the convection that philosophy need not remain an array of conflicting ©systems©, but could attain to the status of objective knowledge. As a student in Berlin and Vienna during those years, I experienced vividly the exhilarating sense, shared by those close to those two philosophical groups, of being jointly engaged in a novel and challenging intellectual enterprise in which philosophical issues were dealt with ©scientifically© and philosophical claims were amenable to support or criticism by logically rigorous arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Kurt Grelling: Steadfast Scholar in a Time of Madness*
    KURT GRELLING: STEADFAST SCHOLAR IN A TIME OF MADNESS* Abraham S. Luchins and Edith H. Luchins Kurt GRELLING (1886-1942) was probably best known for the paradox or an- tinomy that bears his name; it was also called the „not autological‘‘ or the „het- erological‘‘ paradox. Paul OPPENHEIM wrote to us in 1964 that GRELLING was famous for this paradox. In recent years GRELLING, as well as OPPENHEIM, have become known for their analysis of Gestalt concepts. [The article on Gestalt as a functional whole by GRELLING and OPPENHEIM and our Overview of it ap- peared in Gestalt Theory, 21 (1/1999), pp. 49-54 and pp. 43-48 respectively.] GRELLING's Paradox, NELSON, and BORN In the winter term 1905/1906, GRELLING came to study at the University of Göttingen, world-famous for mathematics and for the great David HILBERT (1862- 1943). HILBERT's efforts to axiomatize mathematics were shaken, as were the en- tire foundations of mathematics, by the announcement in 1903 of Bertrand RUS- SELL's antinomy or paradox. In a biography of HILBERT, Constance REID (1970) wrote: By 1904, after its publication by RUSSELL, the antinomy was having --- in HILBERT's opinion - a „downright catastrophic effect“ in mathematics. One after another, the great gifted workers in set theory ... had all withdrawn from the field, conceding defeat. The sim- plest and most important deductive methods, the most ordinary and fruitful concepts seemed to be threatened, for this antinomy and others had appeared simply as a result of employing definitions and deductive methods which had been customary in mathematics.
    [Show full text]