Norms and Causation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Norms and Causation 1 Cause and Norm [Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophy] Christopher Hitchcock Division of Humanities and Social Sciences California Institute of Technology Joshua Knobe Department of Philosophy University of North Carolina 2 Cause and Norm1 1. Introduction Much of the philosophical literature on causation has focused on the concept of ‗actual‘ causation, sometimes called ‗token‘ causation. In particular, it is this notion of actual causation that many philosophical theories of causation have attempted to capture.2 In this paper, we address the question: what purpose does this concept serve? As we shall see in the next section, one does not need this concept for purposes of prediction or rational deliberation. What then could the purpose be? We will argue that one can gain 1 We would like to thank Nancy Cartwright, Clark Glymour, Alison Gopnik, Dennis Hilton, Christoph Hoerl, David Lagnado, Tania Lombrozo, David Mandel, Laurie Paul, Jonathan Schaffer, Jim Woodward, Gideon Yaffe and audience members at the McDonnell workshop on Causal and Moral Cognition (California Institute of Technology), the University of Southern California, the workshop on the Origins and Functions of Causal Thinking IV (Venice, Italy), Rutgers University, the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (Toronto), the Workshop on Causal and Counterfactual Understanding (University of Warwick), and the Workshop on Counterfactuals (Erasmus University Rotterdam). 2 For example, Armstrong (2004), Barker (2004), Björnsson (2007), Davidson (1980), Dowe (2000), Eells (1001. Chapter 6), Ehring (1997), Ganeri, Noordhof and Ramachandran (1996, 1998), Glymour and Wimberly (2007), Hall (2007), Halpern and Pearl (2005), Hiddleston (2005), Hitchcock (2001, 2004, 2007a), Kvart (1997), Lewis (1973/1986, 1986a, 2000), McDermott (1995), Menzies (1989, 1996, 2004a, 2004b), Noordhof (1999, 2004), Pearl (2000, chapter 10), Ramachandran (1997, 1998, 2004a, 2004b), Schaffer (2001), Tooley (1987), Woodward (2003, chapter 2) and Yablo (2002, 2004). 3 an important clue here by looking at the ways in which causal judgments are shaped by people‘s understanding of norms. 2. The problem We may illustrate the concept of actual causation with a simple example: Assassin and Backup set off on a mission to poison Victim. Assassin puts poison in Victim‘s drink. Backup stands at the ready; if Assassin hadn‘t poisoned the drink, Backup would have. Both poisons are lethal. Victim drinks the poison and dies. This is an example of causal preemption: Assassin‘s action causes Victim‘s death, and also preempts Backup‘s action, which would have caused the death if Assassin had not acted. Cases of causal preemption have received a lot of attention, since they provide problems for both regularity and counterfactual theories of causation. Backup‘s presence, plus his willingness to use the poison, together with the composition of the poison, Victim‘s thirst, and other factors, are nomically sufficient for Victim‘s death without the need to mention Assassin; nonetheless, Backup is not a cause of Victim‘s death. And Victim‘s death would have occurred even if Assassin had not acted; nonetheless, Assassin‘s action is a cause of Victim‘s death. Our little story has a causal structure, which can be represented abstractly using a neuron diagram (fig. 1) or a system of structural equations as follows: 4 AS = 1 BS = 1 AP = AS BP = BS & ~AP PD = AP BP VD = PD (Where AS represents ‗Assassin sets off‘, BS ‗Backup sets off‘, AP ‗Assassin poisons the drink‘, BP ‗Backup poisons the drink‘, PD ‗The drink is poisoned‘, and VD ‗Victim dies‘.) These representations tell us how each event in the story depends upon the other events in the story. For example, they tell us that Backup would have poisoned the drink just in case he set off, and Assassin hadn‘t poisoned the drink. Note that there is nothing inherently general or universal about the causal structure. For example, the last equation only tells us that in this particular case, Victim would have died if his drink had been poisoned, and would not have died if it had not been poisoned. It does not say that poisonings always, or even typically, cause deaths.3 Over and above this causal structure, however, we have the judgment that Assassin‘s actions caused Victim to die, while Backup‘s actions did not. This is a judgment about actual causation. We wish to ask what the purpose of such a judgment is. In particular, why don‘t we make do with just the causal structure? After all, the causal structure suffices to allow us to make predictions about what will happen, given any 3 See Hitchcock (2007a, 2007b) for further discussion of this point. 5 combination of the relevant causal antecedents. The causal structure allows us to infer what would happen if we were to interfere with the system to disrupt the causal relationships in various ways. And the causal structure allows us to answer any counterfactual questions about how things might have gone differently. What more could we want from knowledge of causation? We may approach this problem from a slightly different direction. There have been a number of attempts to extend the counterfactual theory of causation to accommodate cases of causal preemption. One promising line, realized in somewhat different ways by Lewis (1986), Halpern and Pearl (2005), Hall (2007), and Hitchcock (2007), is to identify causation not with counterfactual dependence in the actual situation, but rather with counterfactual dependence in a certain kind of ‗normalized‘ version of the actual situation. This normalized situation is reached by replacing abnormal features of the actual situation with more normal alternatives. Thus in our little causal story, while Victim‘s death does not counterfactually depend upon Assassin‘s action in the actual situation described, it would depend upon Assassin‘s action in the normalized version of the situation where Backup is not present. This is a rough sketch only; the details need not detain us. The question that arises is: what purpose can be served by a concept that has these contours? What purpose can be served by identifying factors that would have made a difference, not in the actual situation, but in a modified version of the actual situation? 3. Solution sketch 6 Before we begin examining the purpose of the concept of actual causation, it might be helpful to consider one popular view about the purpose of the concept of causal structure. Several authors have championed the view that the purpose of understanding causal structure is to predict the outcomes of interventions (e.g., Cartwright 1979; Woodward 2003). In particular, it has been suggested that the key difference between knowing causal structure and merely knowing facts about correlations is that the former type of knowledge can enable people to predict the outcomes of intervention in a way that the latter cannot. To see the distinctive role of the concept of causation here, consider what might happen if you discovered a correlation whereby people who are beaten as children tend to be more violent as adults. Just by knowing that correlation, you could predict that a child who was beaten would be more likely to later become violent. Why then would you want to know whether there was actually a causal relationship between being beaten and becoming violent? The idea we will be drawing on here is that this information about causation proves useful when one‘s goal is not only to predict the results of subsequent observations but also to actively intervene in the world. Hence, in this example, the important thing about knowing whether there was a causal relationship here would be that this sort of knowledge would allow you to determine whether you could actually prevent people from becoming violent in adulthood by intervening to prevent them from being beaten as children. Our aim here is to construct an account that extends this basic insight, showing how people‘s concept of actual causation enables them to design effective interventions. In particular, we argue that information that has nothing to do with causal structure can 7 sometimes prove helpful in determining which intervention would be most suitable and that people are actually making use of this information in deciding which factors to denominate as ‗causes.‘ In general, while causal structure identifies all of the factors that could be manipulated (either singly or in combination) to effect a change in the outcome, the actual causes are the factors that should be manipulated. For a simple example, consider a student who has just gotten an F on a test and is wondering how this outcome might have been avoided. At least in theory, she might consider all sorts of different possibilities: ‗I would not have gotten an F if the teacher had been eaten by a lion.‘ ‗I would not have gotten an F if the Earth‘s gravitational pull had suddenly decreased.‘ ‗I would not have gotten an F if I had had less to drink the night before the test.‘ Yet although all of these different counterfactuals might be correct, she is only likely to entertain one of these, and only one of them actually points toward a suitable target of intervention. She should not be wasting her time thinking about the possibility of avoiding a bad grade by introducing lions or decreasing the Earth‘s gravitational pull. The thing to focus on here is the possibility of getting a better grade by drinking less. It is in addressing problems like this one, we think, that the concept of actual causation really earns its keep. Information about causal structure entails many different counterfactuals about how a given outcome might have been avoided. But people‘s judgments of actual causation do something more. They select, from amongst all of these different counterfactuals, a chosen few that might actually be worth considering.
Recommended publications
  • How Babies Think
    osq216Gpnk3p.indd 4 3/9/16 5:37 PM RAISE GREAT Thirty years ago most psychologists, KIDS philosophers and psychiatrists thought that babies and young children were ir- rational, egocentric and amoral. They believed children were locked in the con- crete here and now—unable to under- Even the stand cause and effect, imagine the ex - periences of other people, or appreciate youngest the difference between reality and fanta- sy. People still often think of children as children know, defective adults. experience and But in the past three decades scien- tists have discovered that even the young- learn far more est children know more than we would ever have thought possible. Moreover, than scientists studies suggest that children learn about the world in much the same way that sci- Photographs by ever thought entists do—by conducting experiments, Timothy analyzing statistics, and forming intuitive Archibald possible theories of the physical, biological and psychological realms. Since about 2000, researchers have started to understand the underlying computational, evolutionary and neurological mechanisms that under- pin these remarkable early abilities. These revolutionary ndings not only change our ideas about babies, they give us a fresh perspective on human nature itself. PHYSICS FOR BABIES Why were we so wrong about babies for so long? If you look cursorily at children who are four years old and younger (the age range I will discuss in this article), you might indeed conclude that not much is going on. Babies, after all, cannot talk. And even preschoolers are not good at re- porting what they think. Ask your aver- age three-year-old an open-ended ques- tion, and you are likely to get a beautiful but incomprehensible stream-of-con- sciousness monologue.
    [Show full text]
  • Children's Causal Inferences from Indirect Evidence
    Running head: CHILDREN’S CAUSAL INFERENCES Children’s causal inferences from indirect evidence: Backwards blocking and Bayesian reasoning in preschoolers David M. Sobel Department of Cognitive and Linguistic Sciences, Brown University Joshua B. Tenenbaum Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, MIT Alison Gopnik Department of Psychology, University of California at Berkeley Cognitive Science in press. Children’s causal 2 Abstract Previous research suggests that children can infer causal relations from patterns of events. However, what appear to be cases of causal inference may simply reduce to children recognizing relevant associations among events, and responding based on those associations. To examine this claim, in Experiments 1 and 2, children were introduced to a “blicket detector”, a machine that lit up and played music when certain objects were placed upon it. Children observed patterns of contingency between objects and the machine’s activation that required them to use indirect evidence to make causal inferences. Critically, associative models either made no predictions, or made incorrect predictions about these inferences. In general, children were able to make these inferences, but some developmental differences between 3- and 4- year-olds were found. We suggest that children’s causal inferences are not based on recognizing associations, but rather that children develop a mechanism for Bayesian structure learning. Experiment 3 explicitly tests a prediction of this account. Children were asked to make an inference about ambiguous data based on the base-rate of certain events occurring. Four- year-olds, but not 3-year-olds were able to make this inference. Children’s causal 3 Children’s causal inferences from indirect evidence: Backwards blocking and Bayesian reasoning in preschoolers As adults, we know a remarkable amount about the causal structure of the world.
    [Show full text]
  • DOI: 10.1126/Science.1223416 , 1623 (2012); 337 Science Alison Gopnik
    Scientific Thinking in Young Children: Theoretical Advances, Empirical Research, and Policy Implications Alison Gopnik Science 337, 1623 (2012); DOI: 10.1126/science.1223416 This copy is for your personal, non-commercial use only. If you wish to distribute this article to others, you can order high-quality copies for your colleagues, clients, or customers by clicking here. Permission to republish or repurpose articles or portions of articles can be obtained by following the guidelines here. The following resources related to this article are available online at www.sciencemag.org (this information is current as of October 13, 2012 ): Updated information and services, including high-resolution figures, can be found in the online version of this article at: on October 13, 2012 http://www.sciencemag.org/content/337/6102/1623.full.html Supporting Online Material can be found at: http://www.sciencemag.org/content/suppl/2012/09/26/337.6102.1623.DC1.html A list of selected additional articles on the Science Web sites related to this article can be found at: http://www.sciencemag.org/content/337/6102/1623.full.html#related This article cites 29 articles, 8 of which can be accessed free: www.sciencemag.org http://www.sciencemag.org/content/337/6102/1623.full.html#ref-list-1 This article appears in the following subject collections: Psychology http://www.sciencemag.org/cgi/collection/psychology Downloaded from Science (print ISSN 0036-8075; online ISSN 1095-9203) is published weekly, except the last week in December, by the American Association for the Advancement of Science, 1200 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy News
    2015-2016 PHILOSOPHY NEWS INSIDE Wayne Sumner’s Roseman Lecture 2015 In Memoriam: Brilliant (But Brief) Global Justice: Francis Sparshott Legal Career From Theory to Practice 1926-2015 UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY 2 Philosophy News CONTENTS Welcome & Reports 3 Brad Inwood 8 Wayne Sumner’s Legal Career 10 Roseman Lecture 2015 12 Ergo 14 Fackenheim Portrait 15 In Memoriam Francis Sparshott 16 People & Awards 18 Book Launch 2015 23 PHILOSOPHY NEWS www.philosophy.utoronto.ca We wish to thank the Editors: Anita Di Giacomo Department of Philosophy generous donors to the Mary Frances Ellison University of Toronto Department of Philosophy, Layout: Dragon Snap Design 170 St. George Street, 4th Floor without whom Philosophy Toronto ON M5R 2M8 News would not be possible. Canada Philosophy News Tel: 416-978-3311 Please support the Department 2015-2016 edition Fax: 416-978-8703 in our endeavours! Spring, 2016 YOUR PRIVACY: The University of Toronto respects your privacy. We do not rent, trade or sell our mailing lists. The information on this form is collected and used for the administration of the University’s advancement activities undertaken pursuant to the University of Toronto Act, 1971. If you have any questions, please refer to <www.utoronto.ca/privacy> or contact the University’s Freedom of Information and Protection of Privacy Coordinator at 416-946-7303, McMurrich Building, Room 201, 12 Queen’s Park Crescent West, Toronto, ON M5S 1A8. If you do not wish to receive future newsletters from the Department of Philosophy, please contact us at 416-978-2139 or at [email protected] University of Toronto 3 Welcome his year, year in the department, Tom served as undergradu- Philosophy ate coordinator and tri-campus TA coordinator, and we T News, the are thankful for his excellent services in these two jobs.
    [Show full text]
  • Current Directions in Psychologi
    CDPXXX10.1177/0963721414556653Gopnik et al.Flexibility and Open-Mindedness in Younger Learners 556653research-article2015 Current Directions in Psychological Science When Younger Learners Can Be Better 2015, Vol. 24(2) 87–92 © The Author(s) 2015 Reprints and permissions: (or at Least More Open-Minded) sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0963721414556653 Than Older Ones cdps.sagepub.com Alison Gopnik1, Thomas L. Griffiths1, and Christopher G. Lucas2 1Department of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley, and 2School of Informatics, University of Edinburgh, United Kingdom Abstract We describe a surprising developmental pattern we found in studies involving three different kinds of problems and age ranges. Younger learners are better than older ones at learning unusual abstract causal principles from evidence. We explore two factors that might contribute to this counterintuitive result. The first is that as our knowledge grows, we become less open to new ideas. The second is that younger minds and brains are intrinsically more flexible and exploratory, although they are also less efficient as a result. Keywords cognitive development, causal learning, Bayesian models, simulated annealing There is a tension in the field of cognitive development. also suggest that younger learners might sometimes be Children perform worse than adults on many measures. open to more possibilities than older ones. As they grow older, children become more focused, they Theoretically, we propose two possible complemen- plan better, and, of course, they know more. Yet very tary explanations for this pattern, inspired by viewing young children are prodigious learners, and they are children’s learning through the lens of computer science. especially good at learning about causes.
    [Show full text]
  • Words About Young Minds
    Words About Young Minds The Concepts of Theory, Representation, and Belief in Philosophy and Developmental Psychology Eric Schwitzgebel B.A. (Stanford University) 1990 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the graduate division of the University of California at Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Elisabeth A. Lloyd (chair) Professor John R. Searle Professor Alison Gopnik (psychology) May, 1997 The dissertation of Eric Schwitzgebel is approved. _____________________________________________________ Professor Elisabeth A. Lloyd (chair) Date _____________________________________________________ Professor John R. Searle Date _____________________________________________________ Professor Alison Gopnik Date University of California at Berkeley May 1997 Words About Young Minds: The Concepts of Theory, Representation, and Belief in Philosophy and Developmental Psychology Copyright © Eric Schwitzgebel May 1997 Abstract Words About Young Minds: The Concepts of Theory, Representation, and Belief in Philosophy and Developmental Psychology Eric Schwitzgebel Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California at Berkeley Professor Elisabeth A. Lloyd, Chair I examine three philosophically important concepts that play a foundational role in developmental psychology: theory, representation, and belief. I describe different ways in which the concepts have been understood and present reasons why a developmental psychologist, or a philosopher attuned to cognitive development, should prefer one understanding of these concepts over another. I take up the concept of theories with an eye to recent debate in psychology over whether the cognitive development of young children can fruitfully be characterized as involving theory change. I propose, instead, a novel account of theories intended to capture what scientific theories and everyday theories have in common.
    [Show full text]
  • Pretense, Counterfactuals, and Bayesian Causal Models: Why What Is Not Real Really Matters
    Cognitive Science 37 (2013) 1368–1381 Copyright © 2013 Cognitive Science Society, Inc. All rights reserved. ISSN: 0364-0213 print / 1551-6709 online DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12069 Pretense, Counterfactuals, and Bayesian Causal Models: Why What Is Not Real Really Matters Deena S. Weisberg,a Alison Gopnikb aDepartment of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania bDepartment of Psychology, University of California at Berkeley Received 31 July 2012; received in revised form 16 October 2012; accepted 3 December 2012 Abstract Young children spend a large portion of their time pretending about non-real situations. Why? We answer this question by using the framework of Bayesian causal models to argue that pretend- ing and counterfactual reasoning engage the same component cognitive abilities: disengaging with current reality, making inferences about an alternative representation of reality, and keeping this representation separate from reality. In turn, according to causal models accounts, counterfactual reasoning is a crucial tool that children need to plan for the future and learn about the world. Both planning with causal models and learning about them require the ability to create false premises and generate conclusions from these premises. We argue that pretending allows children to practice these important cognitive skills. We also consider the prevalence of unrealistic scenarios in chil- dren’s play and explain how they can be useful in learning, despite appearances to the contrary. Keywords: Cognitive development; Imaginative cognition; Counterfactual reasoning; Causal reasoning; Bayesian learning 1. Introduction Children and adults understand the rules that govern reality, but they also know how to leave reality behind. This is one of the most important and fascinating aspects of human cognition: the ability to disengage from the real world and to move into the realm of imagination.
    [Show full text]
  • Alison Gopnik CV Page 1
    ALISON GOPNIK ADDRESS Dept. of Psychology University of California at Berkeley Berkeley, California, U.S.A. 94720 email: Gopnik at Berkeley dot edu EDUCATION 1975 B.A., Majors in philosophy and psychology, with great distinction, McGill University 1980 D.Phil., Experimental psychology, Oxford University FELLOWSHIPS, PRIZES AND HONORS 1981 Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada Postdoctoral Fellowship 1984 Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada University Research Fellowship 1998 Center for Advanced Studies in the Behavioral Sciences Fellowship 1999 Osher Fellowship 2006 Moore Distinguished Visiting Scholar Fellowship - California Institute of Technology 2009 J. James Woods Distinguished Lecturer in Science and Mathematics 2009 San Francisco Public Library Literary Laureate 2010 Cattell Fellowship 2010 Elected American Psychological Society Fellow 2010 Little-Franklin Distinguished Lecturer in Public Science 2011 All Souls Distinguished Visiting Scholar Fellowship - University of Oxford 2011 Cognitive Development Society Book Award for “The Philosophical Baby” 2011 Elected Fellow of the Society of Experimental Psychologists 2012 Robb Distinguished Lecturer 2012 Honorary Professor - University of Auckland 2013 Elected Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences Alison Gopnik CV Page 1 2014 Elected Fellow of the Cognitive Science Society 2016 Graham Lecturer in Science – University of Toronto 2016 Invited Participant in the White House Summit on Women 2017 King’s College Distinguished Visiting
    [Show full text]
  • [This Letter Is Closed Now, Accepting No More Signatures]
    March 31st, 2017 To: H.E. Réka Szemerkényi, Ambassador of Hungary to the United States of America Zoltán Balog, Minister of Human Capacities, Ministry of Human Capacities, Hungary László Palkovics, Minister of State for Education, Ministry of Human Capacities, Hungary Dear Ambassador Szemerkényi, Minister Balog, and Minister Palkovics, We are writing to express our dismay about the proposed legislation that would effectively end a 25-year history of scientific excellence in Budapest. As an international body of psychologists, neuroscientists, and cognitive scientists, we can tell you that our colleagues at Central European University are among the most respected in the world. Their intellectual legacy has had a global impact. We believe any city should count itself fortunate to have such a renowned center of academic excellence in its midst. The proposed legislation will make it effectively impossible for CEU to continue to occupy its current position as one of the foremost scientific institutions internationally. We respectfully ask that you preserve CEU’s ability to act as a center of leadership and innovation in Hungary and the world by withdrawing this legislation. [This letter is closed now, accepting no more signatures] Sincerely, 1. Laura Schulz, Professor of Cognitive Science, Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, MIT 2. Rebecca Saxe, Professor of Cognitive Science, Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, MIT 3. John E. Richards, Carolina Distinguished Professor, Department of Psychology, University of South Carolina. 4. Michael Tomasello, Duke University, Durham, NC, and Max Planck for Evolutionary Anthropology, Leipzig, Germany. 5. Philippe G. Schyns, Professor of Visual Cognition, Director of the Institute of Neuroscience and Psychology, university of Glasgow, UK 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Developmental Psychology Children’S Causal Inferences from Conflicting Testimony and Observations Sophie Bridgers, Daphna Buchsbaum, Elizabeth Seiver, Thomas L
    Developmental Psychology Children’s Causal Inferences From Conflicting Testimony and Observations Sophie Bridgers, Daphna Buchsbaum, Elizabeth Seiver, Thomas L. Griffiths, and Alison Gopnik Online First Publication, November 16, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0039830 CITATION Bridgers, S., Buchsbaum, D., Seiver, E., Griffiths, T. L., & Gopnik, A. (2015, November 16). Children’s Causal Inferences From Conflicting Testimony and Observations. Developmental Psychology. Advance online publication. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0039830 Developmental Psychology © 2015 American Psychological Association 2015, Vol. 51, No. 12, 000 0012-1649/15/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0039830 Children’s Causal Inferences From Conflicting Testimony and Observations Sophie Bridgers Daphna Buchsbaum University of California, Berkeley University of Toronto Elizabeth Seiver, Thomas L. Griffiths, and Alison Gopnik University of California, Berkeley Preschoolers use both direct observation of statistical data and informant testimony to learn causal relationships. Can children integrate information from these sources, especially when source reliability is uncertain? We investigate how children handle a conflict between what they hear and what they see. In Experiment 1, 4-year-olds were introduced to a machine and 2 blocks by a knowledgeable informant who claimed to know which block was better at activating the machine, or by a naïve informant who guessed. Children then observed probabilistic evidence contradicting the informant and were asked to identify the block that worked better. Next, the informant claimed to know which of 2 novel blocks was a better activator, and children chose 1 block to try themselves. After observing conflicting data, children were more likely to say the informant’s block was better when the informant was knowledgeable than when she was naïve.
    [Show full text]
  • The Psychological Representation of Modality
    The psychological representation of modality Jonathan Phillips and Joshua Knobe Abstract A series of recent studies have explored the impact of people’s judgments regarding physical law, morality, and probability. Surprisingly, such studies indicate that these three apparently unrelated types of judgments often have precisely the same impact. We argue that these findings provide evidence for a more general hypothesis about the kind of cognition people use to think about possibilities. Specif- ically, we suggest that this aspect of people’s cognition is best understood using an idea developed within work in the formal semantics tradition, namely the notion of modality. On the view we propose, people may have separate representations for physical, moral and probabilistic considerations, but they also integrate these various considerations into a unified representation of modality. The past few decades have witnessed an explosion of research on the way that humans understand physics, morality, and probability. This research has explored the impact on people’s cognition of regarding an event as physically impossible, morally wrong, or highly improbable (Griffiths et al. 2010, Knobe 2010, Marr 1982, Spelke 1990). One remarkably underappreciated fact is that these factors often have the exact same impact. That is, there are a number of different respects in which a judgment that something violates physical law has the same impact as a judgment that it is morally wrong, which in turn has the same impact as a judgment that it is statistically improbable. As we go on to argue, the number of different phenomena in which this precise pattern can be found suggests that there is some deeper connection between these factors.
    [Show full text]
  • AI on the Beach the COVID-19 Pandemic Is Not Over and the Future Is Uncertain, but There Has Lately Been a Semblance of What Life Was Like Before
    editorial AI on the beach The COVID-19 pandemic is not over and the future is uncertain, but there has lately been a semblance of what life was like before. As thoughts turn to the possibility of a summer holiday, we ofer suggestions for books and podcasts on AI to refresh the mind. uring the pandemic, social media at Berkeley) addresses ‘child-inspired AI’, and AI technology have only grown that is, the role of studying how children Din importance. An excellent book learn in building AI systems, emphasizing that takes a look at the rise of the companies imitation, abstract causal models, and active behind these technologies is Genius Makers learning via exploration. Matthew Botvinick by Cade Metz1. Metz, a New York Times (DeepMind) describes the interrelations journalist, interviewed key players in the between neuroscience and psychology, development of modern machine learning including how much we understand about and its deployment by tech companies. With the brain, and how that knowledge might an insider’s sources and a journalist’s knack relate to the design of AI. for storytelling, he describes the people, For another big-picture take on machine ideas and history of “The Mavericks Who intelligence, listen to Melanie Mitchell Brought AI to Google, Facebook, and the (Sante Fe Institute) who thinks about the World” (subtitle). We recommend the book interactions between complexity and AI. for readers who want to understand the Pamela McCorduck, author of Machines main ideas behind the latest AI technologies, Who Think (first published in 1979; second the personalities of prominent people, and edition in 20044) tells fascinating stories important events in the field.
    [Show full text]