Notes and References

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Notes and References Notes and References 1 'The Great Educators' 1. A. N. Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay on Cosmology. 2 Plato 1. The Epinomis of Plato, trans. J. Harward, § 487. On the assumption that the Epinomis can be ascribed to Plato, see A. E. Taylor, Plato: The Man and His Work, pp. 497-8. All the succeeding quotations from Plato's writings are from Jowett's 1875 translation, and the references are to the marginal page numbers of that work. 2. For Greek education see Werner Jaeger, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture, trans. G. Highet;H. I. Marrou,A History ofEducation in Antiquity, trans. G. Lamb; F. A. G. Beck, Greek Education, 450-350 B.C.; W. Barclay, Educational Ideals in the Ancient World. 3. § 313. 4. Protagoras, § 340. Cf. Euthydemus, § 277. 5. Protagoras, § 309. 6. Laches, § 186. 7. Protagoras was the first to accept payment (Protagoras, § 348): 'You proclaim in the face of Hellas that you are a Sophist or teacher of virtue or education and are the first that demanded pay in return.' His method of exacting payment - a form of payment by results - was as follows (Protagoras, § 328): 'When a man has been my pupil, if he likes he pays my price, but there is no compulsion; and if he does not like, he has only to go into a temple and take an oath of the value of the instructions, and he pays no more than he declares to be their value.' The result was, as reported by Socrates in the Meno, § 91: 'I know of a single man, Protagoras, who made more out of his craft than the illustrious Pheidias, who created such noble works, or any ten other statuaries. ' The sophists have been designated the founders of educational science: Jaeger, Paideia, vol. I, p. 295. 8. Laches, § 186. 248 Doctrines of the Great Educators 9. James Bowen, A History of Western Education, vol. I, The Ancient World, pp. 86-7; J. S. Mill in Barry Gross (ed.), Great Thinkers on Plato, pp.151-2. 10. Meno, § 92. 11. § 312. 12. See A. E. Taylor, Socrates, and R. W. Livingstone, Portrait of Socrates. 13. Metaphysics, § 1078, b. 14. § 216. 15. Cf. metaphor of midwife in Theaetetus, § 150; also Symposium, § 209. Cf. Jaeger, vol. II, p. 27: 'He [Socrates] is the greatest teacher in European history.' 16. Symposium, § 204. 17. Ibid., § 217. 18. Apology, § 31. 19. Ibid., § 33. 20. § 348. 21. Cf. Theaetetus, § 201: 'Knowledge is true opinion accompanied by a reason.' 22. How Gertrude Teaches her Children, Eng. trans. (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1907) p. 46. Cf. p. 57. 23. Cf. for successful examples, J. Adams, Primer on Teaching (Edin­ burgh: T. & T. Clark, 1903) pp. 90-108; also Exposition and Illustration (London: Macmillan, 1909) pp. 80-2. 24. See R. S. Black, Plato's Life and Thought, or A. E. Taylor, Plato. 25. See R. C. Lodge, Plato's Theory of Education. 26. § 599. 27. § 644. 28. § 185. 29. § 45. 30. § 50. 31. § 339. 32. § 21. 33. §§ 325-6. 34. For a reconstruction of Plato's own upbringing see Graham Wallas, The Art of Thought (London: Jonathan Cape, 1926) p. 230. 35. The Works of Xenophon, trans. H. G. Dakyns (London: Macmillan, 1897) vol. III, pt i, pp. 226-7 and note. See also Jaeger, Paideia, vol. III, pp.175-7. 36. The modem name for the work. Plato's was Politeia, meaning 'state' or 'constitution', and thus a general treatise on government. See Bowen, Ancient World, p. 105. 37. W. Boyd, Plato's Republicfor Today. 38. Emile (Everyman ed.) p. 8. 39. Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers (Glasgow: J. MacLehose & Sons, 1904) I 140. 40. Cf. Jaeger, Paideia, vol. I, pp. 102-4. 'All virtues are summed up in righteousness.' Also II 202. Notes and References 249 41. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, III 13: 'Justice has been acknowledged by us to be a social virtue.' 42. Cf. Rousseau, Emile, p. 202: 'It is true ... that we have a very imperfect knowledge of the human heart if we do not also examine it in crowds; but it is none the less true that to judge of men we must study the individual man, and that he who had a perfect knowledge of the inclinations of each individual might foresee all their combined effects in the body of the nation.' Also Jaeger, vol. II, p. 366: 'He [Plato] is founding politics upon ethics ... For Plato the perfect state is only the ideal frame of a good life.' 43. Robin Barrow, Plato, Utilitarianism and Education, p. 1. 44. Republic, § 369. 45. K. R. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, p. 171; Barrow, Plato, p. 50. 46. Note that Plato presupposes an initial inequality. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, II: 'Similars do not constitute a state.' 47. Politics, 12. 48. Republic, §§ 369-72. 49. Ibid., § 373. 50. Ibid., § 372. 51. Lewis Campbell, Plato's Republic (London: John Murray, 1902) p.54. 52. Greek pseudos, a fable or myth, introduced to elucidate an argument, not as a deliberate lie. See Barrow, Plato, p. 130. 53. Republic, § 415. 54. Ibid., § 423. 55. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, II 5, 23: 'What will be the education, form of government, laws of the lower class Socrates has nowhere determined.' Cf., however, Republic, § 467. 56. Campbell, Plato's Republic, p. 65. 57. Ibid., p. 54. Plato refers to the workers as 'those whose natural talents were defective from the first, and whose souls have since been so grievously marred and enervated by their life of drudgery as their bodies have been disfigured by their crafts and trades'. Republic, § 495. 58. Barrow, Plato, p. 151. 59. Politics, 13. 60. Cf. Protagoras, § 322: 'For cities cannot exist, if a few only share in the virtues as in the arts.' Also Aristotle, Politics, III 15, and II 2. 61. Prolegomena to Ethics (OUP, 1899) § 207. 62. Republic, §§ 376-412. 63. Almost equivalent to the term Arts in a university curriculum. 64. Republic, § 410. Cf. passage from Protagoras quoted above. 65. Republic, § 376: ct. and contrast Aristotle, Politics, VII 15. 'The care of the body ought to precede that of the soul, and the training of the appetitive part should follow: none the less the care of it must be for the sake of the reason, and our care of the body for the sake of the soul. ' 66. Republic, § 377. 67. Cf. Aristotle, Politics" VII 17. 68. Republic, § 376. 250 Doctrines of the Great Educators 69. Ibid., § 378. 70. Ibid., 71. Barrow, Plato, p. 110. 72. Republic, § 380. 73. § 383. 74. § 386. 75. Republic, §§ 386-8. 76. § 389. Cf. the international morality in More's Utopia. 77. Republic, § 392. 78. Ibid., §§ 392-403. 79. § 395. 80. § 401. 81. § 401. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, VII 17: 'All that is mean and low should be banished from their sight.' Also B. Bosanquet, The Education of the Young in the Republic of Plato (CUP, 1904) p. 102, fn. 82. Republic, § 522. 83. Ibid., §§ 403-12. 84. § 404. 85. § 411. 86. § 412. 87. § 522. 88. § 536. 89. Republic, § 376. Here we have the beginnings of vocational selection and of selection board procedures. 90. Ibid., § 413. Not quite 'an education through perfect circumstances', as Lewis Campbell supposed, Plato's Republic, p. 73. 91. Republic, §§ 521-41. 92. Ibid., § 535. 93. § 487. 94. § 490. 95. § 521. 96. § 518. 97. See Jaeger vol. II, pp. 267-8 for description of Plato's philosopher. 98. Republic, § 523. 99. § 522. 100. § 525. 101. Republic, § 527 .. 102. Ibid., § 526. This argument is repeated in almost identical terms in the Laws, § 747: 'Arithmetic stirs up him who is by nature sleepy and dull, and makes him quick to learn, retentive, shrewd, and aided by art divine he makes progress quite beyond his natural powers.' 103. Republic, § 527. 104. Ibid., § 531. 105. E. C. Moore, What Is Education? (Boston and London: Ginn, 1915) ch. 3. It must be put to Plato's credit that in interpreting a faculty as a function (Republic, § 477) he avoided the 'faculty' doctrine which long retarded the development of psychology. 106. Republic, § 526. The idea of good, or 'the Form of the Good', is the Notes and References 251 ultimate principle in Plato's philosophy, at once the source of all being and of all knowledge. Cf. ibid., § 509. 107. Ibid., § 527. 108. Ibid. 109. § 530. In accordance with this principle the calculation of Neptune into existence by Adams and Leverrier would have been commended by Plato; the verification of its existence by actual observation would have merited his contempt. 110. Marrou, p. 371, translates music here by 'acoustics' - 'the science of mathematics introduced by Pythagoras, the study of the numerical structure of intervals and rhythms'. 111. Republic, § 531. 112. Ibid., § 533. In the Cratylus Plato defined the dialectician as 'he who knows how to ask questions and how to answer them'. In the Phaedrus he identifies dialectic with the process of division and generalisation, and he adds, Republic, § 537, 'For according as a man can survey a subject as a whole or not, he is or is not a dialectician.' 113. Republic, § 534. 114. Ibid., §§ 537-41. 115. § 536. The tests for philosophers include intelligence tests. The tests for the guardians are mainly temperament tests. 116. § 539. Cf. Aristotle, Ethics, 13: 'The young man is not a fit student of Politics. ' 117. Republic, § 540. 118. Ibid. Cf. §§ 451-7. 119. Ibid., § 457. The great waves or paradoxes in the construction of Plato's ideal state are: (1) the community of goods and of pursuits; (2) the community of wives and children; (3) summarised in the statement, 'Until kings are philosophers or philosophers are kings, cities will never cease from ill.' 120.
Recommended publications
  • Births, Marriages, and Deaths
    DEC. 31, 1955 MEDICAL NEWS MEDICALBRrsIJOURNAL. 1631 Lead Glazes.-For some years now the pottery industry British Journal of Ophthalmology.-The new issue (Vol. 19, has been forbidden to use any but leadless or "low- No. 12) is now available. The contents include: solubility" glazes, because of the risk of lead poisoning. EXPERIENCE IN CLINIcAL EXAMINATION OP CORNEAL SENsITiVrry. CORNEAL SENSITIVITY AND THE NASO-LACRIMAL REFLEX AFTER RETROBULBAR However, in some teaching establishments raw lead glazes or ANAES rHESIA. Jorn Boberg-Ans. glazes containing a high percentage of soluble lead are still UVEITIS. A CLINICAL AND STATISTICAL SURVEY. George Bennett. INVESTIGATION OF THE CARBONIC ANHYDRASE CONTENT OF THE CORNEA OF used. The Ministry of Education has now issued a memo- THE RABBIT. J. Gloster. randum to local education authorities and school governors HYALURONIDASE IN OCULAR TISSUES. I. SENSITIVE BIOLOGICAL ASSAY FOR SMALL CONCENTRATIONS OF HYALURONIDASE. CT. Mayer. (No. 517, dated November 9, 1955) with the object of INCLUSION BODIES IN TRACHOMA. A. J. Dark. restricting the use of raw lead glazes in such schools. The TETRACYCLINE IN TRACHOMA. L. P. Agarwal and S. R. K. Malik. APPL IANCES: SIMPLE PUPILLOMETER. A. Arnaud Reid. memorandum also includes a list of precautions to be ob- LARGE CONCAVE MIRROR FOR INDIRECT OPHTHALMOSCOPY. H. Neame. served when handling potentially dangerous glazes. Issued monthly; annual subscription £4 4s.; single copy Awards for Research on Ageing.-Candidates wishing to 8s. 6d.; obtainable from the Publishing Manager, B.M.A. House, enter for the 1955-6 Ciba Foundation Awards for research Tavistock Square, London, W.C.1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trinity Review, May 1948
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, Trinity Review (1939 - 1980) Catalogs, etc.) 5-1-1948 The Trinity Review, May 1948 Trinity College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/review Recommended Citation Trinity College, "The Trinity Review, May 1948" (1948). Trinity Review (1939 - 1980). 11. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/review/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, Catalogs, etc.) at Trinity College Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Trinity Review (1939 - 1980) by an authorized administrator of Trinity College Digital Repository. The Trinity Review Volume II May, 1948 Number 3 EDITORIAL BOARD THOMAS C. F. LOWRY Editor-in-Chief HARRY M. BRACKEN F. ScoTT BILLYOU Executive Editor Business Manager STANLEY F. RODGERS GEORGE W. STOWE Art Editor Circulation Manager LEONARD c. OVERTON FRANK LAMBERT, }R. ]OHN w. COOTE RoBERT M. BLUM EDWARD R . PARONE ROBERT W. HERBERT APOLOGIA The third number of this volume of the Review is ap­ pearing on the wee~end designated by the college as com­ memorative of its one hundred and twenty-fifth anniversary. It is a happy coincidence that such a celebration should be in order at the time of the Review's evident emergence from the ran~s of embryonic underta~ings to those com­ prised of established and vital institutions. The newly instituted editorial board wishes at this time to pledge itself to the maintenance and furthering of the literary ideals so well defined by the previous editors. A special debt of gratitude is owed to Harold W.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's "Euthyphro"
    24.231 Ethics – Handout 1 Plato, “The Euthyphro” I. Plato’s Dialogue Plato’s Question: What is it to be pious? - He is not looking for a list of things that are pious - He is not looking for a property that (even all) pious things have. Euthyphro’s (best?) answer: To be pious is to be loved by all the gods. Plato’s Argument against Euthyphro’s answer: Perhaps all and only those things/actions that are loved by the gods are pious. But why is that? Are pious things loved by the gods because they are pious, or are they pious because they are loved by the gods? Socrates and Euthyphro agree that they must be loved by the gods because they are pious. But, says Socrates, in that case, being pious cannot be the same thing as being god-beloved. Because something that is god-beloved is so because it is loved by the gods. But something that is pious isn’t so because it is loved by the gods; rather, it is loved by the gods because it is pious. Being loved by the gods causes god-belovedness, but being loved by the gods does not cause piety. So god-belovedness and piety cannot be the same thing. (This kind of argument will be relevant again in the selection from Moore that we’re reading for Wednesday.) II. The “Euthyphro Problem” Socrates’ question about whether what’s loved by the gods is pious because it is loved by them, or loved by them because it is pious, forms the lynchpin of an important contemporary debate about what moral philosophers call “Divine Command Theory.” According to DCT, morally good actions are good because they are commanded by God.
    [Show full text]
  • The Highest Good for Plato Goodness Is an Abstract Concept That Is Very
    The Highest Good for Plato Goodness is an abstract concept that is very difficult to define, and saying what counts as the highest good is perhaps even more so. In Republic, Plato attempts to say something about what makes things good, but his answer is very vague in the end. Still, we can get some clarity on what he would have answered if asked what the highest good is, from what he says in this text. What counts as the highest good for Plato can be said to be knowledge of the Form of the Good, because it is necessary for knowing and using the other Forms well. The nature of the Forms is not clear in Republic; Plato writes about them as if his audience already knows what they are. Still, we can get some sense of what forms are like from the text. In several places he says that when two or more things share the same name, then they share a form. For example, in Book IV Socrates and Glaucon talk about the form of justice: “…are things called by the same name, whether they are bigger or smaller than one another, like or unlike with respect to that to which the name applies? Alike. Then a just man won’t differ at all from a just city in respect to the form of justice; rather he’ll be like the city” (435 a-b). But what is a Form, exactly? We can start to get a sense of what Plato means by a Form by looking back at Euthyphro.
    [Show full text]
  • Agorapicbk-17.Pdf
    Excavations of the Athenian Agora Picture Book No. 17 Prepared by Mabel L. Lang Dedicated to Eugene Vanderpool o American School of Classical Studies at Athens ISBN 87661-617-1 Produced by the Meriden Gravure Company Meriden, Connecticut COVER: Bone figure of Socrates TITLE PAGE: Hemlock SOCRATES IN THE AGORA AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY 1978 ‘Everything combines to make our knowledge of Socrates himself a subject of Socratic irony. The only thing we know definitely about him is that we know nothing.’ -L. Brunschvicg As FAR AS we know Socrates himselfwrote nothing, yet not only were his life and words given dramatic attention in his own time in the Clouds of Ar- istophanes, but they have also become the subject of many others’ writing in the centuries since his death. Fourth-century B.C. writers who had first-hand knowledge of him composed either dialogues in which he was the dominant figure (Plato and Aeschines) or memories of his teaching and activities (Xe- nophon). Later authors down even to the present day have written numerous biographies based on these early sources and considering this most protean of philosophers from every possible point of view except perhaps the topograph- ical one which is attempted here. Instead of putting Socrates in the context of 5th-century B.C. philosophy, politics, ethics or rhetoric, we shall look to find him in the material world and physical surroundings of his favorite stamping- grounds, the Athenian Agora. Just as ‘agora’ in its original sense meant ‘gathering place’ but came in time to mean ‘market place’, so the agora itself was originally a gathering place I.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Apology of Socrates and Crito
    COLLEGE SERIES OF GREEK AUTHORS EDITED UNDER THE SUPERVISION OF JOHN WILLIAMS WHITE, LEWIS R. PACKARD, a n d THOMAS D. SEYMOUR. PLATO A p o l o g y o f S o c r a t e s AND C r i t o EDITED ON THE BASIS OF CRON’S EDITION BY LOUIS DYER A s s i s t a n t ·Ρι;Οχ'ε&^ο^ ι ν ^University. BOSTON: PUBLISHED BY GINN & COMPANY. 1902. I P ■ C o p · 3 Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1885, by J o h n W il l ia m s W h i t e a n d T h o m a s D. S e y m o u r , In the Office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington. J . S. C u s h in g & Co., P r i n t e r s , B o s t o n . PREFACE. T his edition of the Apology of Socrates and the Crito is based upon Dr. Christian Cron’s eighth edition, Leipzig, 1882. The Notes and Introduction here given have in the main been con­ fined within the limits intelligently drawn by Dr. Cron, whose commentaries upon various dialogues of Plato have done and still do so much in Germany to make the study of our author more profitable as well as pleasanter. No scruple has been felt, how­ ever, in making changes. I trust there are few if any of these which Dr. Cron might not himself make if he were preparing his work for an English-thinking and English-speaking public.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Project for Education in the Early Socratic Dialogues
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1996 Plato's project for education in the early Socratic dialogues. Heather Lynne Reid University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Reid, Heather Lynne, "Plato's project for education in the early Socratic dialogues." (1996). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2285. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2285 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PLATO'S PROJECT FOR EDUCATION IN THE EARLY SOCRATIC DIALOGUES A Dissertation Presented by HEATHER LYNNE REID Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 1996 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by Heather Lynne Reid 1996 All Rights Reserved PLATO'S PROJECT FOR EDUCATION IN THE EARLY SOCRATIC DIALOGUES A Dissertation Presented by HEATHER LYNNE REID Approved as to style and content by: ca Gareth B. Matthews, Chair Robert Ackerman, Member J^n Robison, Department Head philosophy ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my dissertation director Gareth B. Matthews for his special balance of support and criticism throughout this project, as well as Bruce Aune and Marios Philippides for their comments on early stages of the manuscript. I also wish to thank the Department of Philosophy of the University of Southern California for providing library privileges and research support necessary to the completion of this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Colby Alumnus Vol. 64, No. 2: Winter 1975
    Colby College Digital Commons @ Colby Colby Alumnus Colby College Archives 1975 Colby Alumnus Vol. 64, No. 2: Winter 1975 Colby College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/alumnus Part of the Higher Education Commons Recommended Citation Colby College, "Colby Alumnus Vol. 64, No. 2: Winter 1975" (1975). Colby Alumnus. 86. https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/alumnus/86 This Other is brought to you for free and open access by the Colby College Archives at Digital Commons @ Colby. It has been accepted for inclusion in Colby Alumnus by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Colby. "") - -� � :O:-'-! . .. - ---� � ) =-.::-� -=---��-- ) :..:... • _ _I._ --�- -- - .. - - - . - .. ...:-.:.- .· :;:- . ... z· > - ' . they be regarded with an appropriate dignity, and The President's Page taken seriously, during the years of residence. The president of a prominent college in another part of the country wrote an article during some of the more difficult years on the campuses entitled "How to Sur­ vive Though Surrounded by Students," or something like that. His first and most important word of advice was "Listen to them." It did not take two Constitutional Conventions to convince most of us on the faculty and in the admin­ istration that students ought to be listened to. Let me enumerate some of the ways in which students are listened to at Colby, and let me emphasize that what they have to say is taken seriously. Each year two students are elected by their fellows to be representatives to the board of trustees. They do not vote, but neither do the two faculty representa­ tives. They do, however, have the full privilege of the floor, and they receive all the written materials and hear all the discussions that full voting trustees have FEW OBSERVATIONS ARE IN ORDER WITH REGARD TO access to.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato the ALLEGORY of the CAVE Republic, VII 514 A, 2 to 517 A, 7
    Plato THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE Republic, VII 514 a, 2 to 517 a, 7 Translation by Thomas Sheehan THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE SOCRATES: Next, said I [= Socrates], compare our nature in respect of education and its lack to such an experience as this. PART ONE: SETTING THE SCENE: THE CAVE AND THE FIRE The cave SOCRATES: Imagine this: People live under the earth in a cavelike dwelling. Stretching a long way up toward the daylight is its entrance, toward which the entire cave is gathered. The people have been in this dwelling since childhood, shackled by the legs and neck..Thus they stay in the same place so that there is only one thing for them to look that: whatever they encounter in front of their faces. But because they are shackled, they are unable to turn their heads around. A fire is behind them, and there is a wall between the fire and the prisoners SOCRATES: Some light, of course, is allowed them, namely from a fire that casts its glow toward them from behind them, being above and at some distance. Between the fire and those who are shackled [i.e., behind their backs] there runs a walkway at a certain height. Imagine that a low wall has been built the length of the walkway, like the low curtain that puppeteers put up, over which they show their puppets. The images carried before the fire SOCRATES: So now imagine that all along this low wall people are carrying all sorts of things that reach up higher than the wall: statues and other carvings made of stone or wood and many other artifacts that people have made.
    [Show full text]
  • BMC 13 - Georg Philipp Telemann (1681-1767): Orchestral Music
    BMC 13 - Georg Philipp Telemann (1681-1767): Orchestral Music Born in Magdeburg in 1681, Telemann belonged to a family that had long been connected with the Lutheran Church. His father was a clergyman, his mother the daughter of a clergyman, and his elder brother also took orders, a path that he too might have followed had it not been for his exceptional musical ability. As a child he showed considerable musical talent, mastering the violin, flute, zither and keyboard by the age of ten and composing an opera (Sigismundus) two years later to the consternation of his family (particularly his mother's side), who disapproved of music. However, such resistance only reinforced his determination to persevere in his studies through transcription, and modeling his works on those of such composers as Steffani, Rosenmüller, Corelli and Antonio Caldara. After preparatory studies at the Hildesheim Gymnasium, he matriculated in Law (at his mother's insistence) at Leipzig University in 1701. That he had little intention of putting aside his interest in music is evident from his stop at Halle, en route to Leipzig, in order to make the acquaintance of the young Handel, with whom he was to maintain a lifelong friendship. It was while he was a student at Leipzig University that a career in music became inevitable. At first it was intended that he should study language and science, but he was already so capable a musician that within a year of his arrival he founded the student Collegium Musicum with which he gave public concerts (and which Bach was later to direct), wrote operatic works for the Leipzig Theater; in 1703 he became musical director of the Leipzig Opera, and was appointed Organist at the Neue Kirche in 1704.
    [Show full text]