Genericity: A –Theoretic Analysis

Massimo Marinacci

Draft of December 1994y

1 Introduction

In many results of Mathematical Economics the notion of smallness plays a crucial role. Indeed, it often turns out that desirable properties do not hold in all the environment of interest, but only in some of its parts. For example, this is usually the case in the di¤erentiable approach to General Equilibrium (see e.g. [4]). The purpose of the analysis then becomes to prove that the desired property fails only in a negligible part of the environment. This is the so called generic point of view (see e.g. [14, pp. 316- 319]). In a similar approach it is crucial to make precise what is meant by terms like negligible and generic. Two notions of smallness are available. On one hand, nowhere dense and meager (often called …rst category) subsets have been regarded as small in a topological sense. To help intuition, observe that a nowhere dense of the is a subset full of holes. On the other hand, from a measure-theoretic viewpoint the notion of small is represented by nullsets. Consequently, quoting [15, p.4], ”it is natural to ask whether these notions of smallness are related”. This is the purpose of the study of residual measures, i.e. Borel measures that give measure zero to all meager sets. With respect to a residual measure, meager subsets are small not only in a topological sense, but also in measure–theoretic one. In this paper we will investigate under which conditions these measures exist. In particular, it will turn

Department of Economics, Northwestern University. I wish to thank Keith Burns and Itzhak Gilboa for helpful comments. Financial support from Ente Einaudi is gratefully acknowledged. yFirst draft: February 1993.

1 out that in many interesting spaces these measures do not exist. This means that in such spaces for any given …nite Borel measure  there always exists a meager subset A such that (A) > 0; i.e. a topologically negligible which is not negligible from a measure-theoretic standpoint. A similar situation already occurs in Euclidean spaces. In fact, in these spaces genericity analysis integrates topological and measure-theoretic considerations. For example, by considering as negligible the sets whose closure has zero. However, in Euclidean spaces the topological and measure-theoretic notions employed have usually a strong intuitive basis, and there is a natural way to integrate them. This is not the case in abstract spaces, where the analysis is usually based on the topological notions of smallness. Our results show that in many spaces of interest it is impossible to have a measure-theoretic support for the topological approach. In other words, there is no Borel measure for which all the topologically negligible sets get measure zero. Stronger results have been obtained for nonatomic measures by Marczewski and Sikorski [12] and [13]. In particular, they have proved that given any nonatomic …nite Borel measure de…ned on a metric spaces with a basis whose cardinal is nonmeasurable (see below; separable metric spaces are an example) it is always possible to decompose the space in two disjoint subsets, one meager, the other one of measure zero. The results presented here are weaker, but hold for any …nite Borel measure, not necessarily nonatomic. As an aside, it is worth noting that the results of Marczewski and Sikorski are im- portant for the analysis of Nash re…nements in normal form games with in…nite strategy spaces. Here the problem is to …nd the appropriate in…nite counterpart of completely mixed strategies, on which re…nements for …nite games are based. A natural candidate are the Borel measures with full support, i.e. measures assigning strictly positive mass to every nonempty open subset. In Simon and Stinchcombe [19] is developed an ap- proach to in…nite games re…nements based on full support Borel measures. However, the results of Marczewski and Sikorski show that for every full support nonatomic mea- sure  on a metric space with a basis whose cardinal is nonmeasurable, there exists a partition A; Ac such that A is meager and (Ac) = 0. In other words, even though  f g puts strictly positive measure to all open sets, there exists a topologically large set like Ac which gets zero measure under . As nonatomic measures are an important class of mixed strategies, this shows that full support measures are a much weaker notion

2 than completely mixed strategies in …nite spaces. Besides genericity analysis, residual measures are interesting in the theory of Boolean algebras. Indeed, let A be a Boolean -algebra and P a probability measure (not nec- essarily strictly positive) de…ned on it. By the Loomis-Sikorski representation theo- rem, to the pair (A; P ) can be associated a measure space characterized by a residual measure. Using techniques of this type it is possible to derive some results about prob- ability measures de…ned on Boolean algebras from propositions established for residual measures. The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 contains some preliminary notions. Section 3 gives existence results concerning residual measures. In section 4 the results of section 3 are used in order to obtain some non-existence results for probability measures de…ned on Boolean algebras. Finally, in section 5 the constructions of the previous sections are used to get a result about the ranges of probability measures on Boolean algebras. We follow the notation of [10]. This implies, for instance, that lower and upper cases will usually denote, respectively, sets and Boolean algebras.

2 Preliminary notions

2.1 Measures

Let X be a and let cl(a) and int(a) denote, respectively, the closure and the of a subset a X. A subset a is nowhere dense if int (cl(a)) = ?, i.e.  if the closure of a has empty interior. Nowhere dense subsets have no interior points. A subset a is meager (or of the …rst category) if it can be represented as a countable of nowhere dense subsets. They are the subsets of X which can be approximated by nowhere dense subsets. We now de…ne some classes of Borel probability measures.

De…nition 1 A Borel probability measure P de…ned on a topological space X is regular if for all Borel subsets a we have

P (a) = sup P (c): c aand cclosed = inf P (v): a vand vopen : f  g f  g

3 De…nition 2 A Borel probability measure P de…ned on a topological space X is - additive if whenever g is a of open subsets such that g g for , then f g  

P g = sup P (g ):

! [ Let M denote the - of all meager Borel subsets. Next we de…ne residual measures.

De…nition 3 A Borel probability measure P de…ned on a topological space X is resid- ual if P (a) = 0 for all a M. 2

Given a probability measure P on a …eld A, a subset a A is called a P -atom if: 2 (i) P (a) > 0;

(ii) if b a and b A, then either P (b) = 0 or P (a b) = 0:  2 n De…nition 4 A Borel probability measure P de…ned on a topological space X is nonatomic if there are no P -atoms.

In the sequel we make use also of the notion of nonmeasurable cardinal. Indeed, suppose that on the power set of a space X there exists a di¤use probability measure , i.e. a measure giving measure zero to all singletons. In such a case, the cardinal number of X is called measurable. Instead, a cardinal is called nonmeasurable if the @ previous property does not hold for all spaces of cardinality . @ Now we turn to Boolean algebras. For basic notions and results we refer to [10]. We begin with a de…nition. A bit of notation: 1 is the unit element of A, while n1=1 an is the supremum of an 1 in A. f gn=1 P De…nition 5 A probability measure P on a Boolean algebra A is a real-valued function such that:

(i) P (a) 0 for all a A;  2

(ii) P ( 1 an) = 1 P (an) whenever an 1 A is a set of pairwise disjoint n=1 n=1 f gn=1  elements for which 1 a exists; P P n=1 n P 4 (iii) P (1) = 1:

It is worth noting that P has not been de…ned as a strictly positive measure (i.e. it is not required P (a) = 0 i¤ a is the zero element). It is important to distinguish the previous de…nition from the usual de…nition of probability measures on …elds of subsets. Let A be a …eld of subsets. A real–valued set function P on A is countably additive if:

(iii’) P ( 1 an) = 1 P (an) whenever an 1 A is a set of pairwise disjoint n=1 n=1 f gn=1  elements such that 1 an A. S P n=1 2 S Condition (iii’)is quite di¤erent from condition (iii) in de…nition 5, as it was stressed in [8]. In fact, 1 an, the supremum of an 1 in A, can exists even when 1 an is n=1 f gn=1 n=1 not in A. Instead, if 1 an A, then 1 an = 1 an. Therefore, if a set function P n=1 2 n=1 n=1 S satis…es (iii’), then it satis…es (iii), while a set function which satis…es (iii’)can fail to S S P satisfy (iii). We illustrate this failure with what would be otherwise a counterexample to the results of next section.

Example. Let A be the smallest …eld of subsets of [0; 1) generated by the intervals

[a; b), with 0 a < b 1: The …eld A is both separable and atomless (these notions   are introduced below). It is known that each element of A can be expressed as a …nite and disjoint union of half-open intervals of the form [a; b). Consequently, each element of A contains an open subset. Now, let m be the restriction of the Lebesgue measure on A. We want to show that m does not satisfy condition (iii) of de…nition 5. In fact, let us construct a subset of [0; 1) in a way similar to that of the Cantor set. However, n 1 n this time at stage n we delete 2 intervals of the form [a; b) and of length (3 ), with

0 < < 1: We denote by c ;n what remains after stage n and we set c  = n1=1 c ;n . The subsets c belong to A for all n 1: Moreover, we have c c where c was ;n   0 T de…ned in section 2. Thus cl(c ) c , and so c is nowhere dense. This implies that  c  does not contain any open subset. Therefore, c  not belong to A because we have already seen that each element of A has a non-empty interior. Furthermore, for the same reason all subsets of c do not belong to A. To sum up, 1 c = c A and n=1 ;n 6 2 n1=1c ;n = ?. In section 2 we said that m(c ) = 1 . Looking at the construction ^ T of c  , it is easy to see that the continuity of m implies m(c ) = m(c  ). Therefore, using again the continuity of m, we have limn m(c ;n ) = m(c  ) = 1 . But !1 5 m( n1=1c ;n ) = m(?) = 0. Hence, limn m(c ;n ) > m( n1=1c ;n ), and it easy to verify ^ !1 ^ that this violates condition (iii) of de…nition 5.

2.2 Duality

This subsection contains some preliminary material on Stone spaces that will be used in section 4. The reader not interested in section 4 can skip this section without loss of continuity. Following [10], Ult(A) denotes the Stone space of A and Clop(Ult(A)) the dual algebra of Ult(A). In the next section we will make use of a generalization of the Loomis-Sikorski representation theorem, due to [18]. To report this generalization we need some further notions. A subset of Ult(A) is -closed provided it is the intersection of countably many subsets in Clop(Ult(A)). A subset of Ult(A) is -nowhere dense if it is a subset of a nowhere dense -closed set. Clearly, a -nowhere dense subset is nowhere dense. Finally, a subset of Ult(A) is of the -category if it is the union of countably many subsets -nowhere dense in Ult(A). Observe that a -category subset is meager in Ult(A). Let M0 be the -ideal of all subsets of the -category in  (Clop (Ult(A))), the -…eld generated by Clop(Ult(A)). Set

= (u v1) v2 with u Clop(Ult(A)) and v1; v2 M0 F f [ 2 2 g is a …eld contained in (Clop(Ult(A))). Let s : A Clop(Ult(A)) be the Stone F ! isomorphism. Let h be the -homomorphism from onto the quotient algebra M0 F Fj de…ned by

h(a) = b : ba M0 f 2 F 2 g where a . Let  be a homomorphism from A onto M0 de…ned by (a) = h(s(a)), 2 F Fj where a A.  is called the canonical homomorphism. This is the version of Sikorski’s 2 result we are interested in:

Proposition 1 (Sikorski) The canonical homomorphism is a -isomorphism from A onto M0. Fj A Boolean algebra satis…es the countable chain condition, c.c.c. for short, if each pairwise disjoint family in A is at most countable. For this class of Boolean algebras, the next result is proved in [18]:

6 Proposition 2 (Sikorski) A Boolean algebra A satis…es the c.c.c. if and only if every nowhere dense subset in Ult(A) is -nowhere dense.

Therefore, if a Boolean algebra A satis…es the c.c.c., then a subset of Ult(A) is meager i¤ it is -nowhere dense. Let M 0 be the -ideal of all meager subsets in

(Clop(Ult(A))). By proposition 2, M0 = M 0 in a Boolean algebra which satis…es Fj Fj the c.c.c. Separable Boolean algebras and atomless Boolean algebras are the two other notions we are interested in. A Boolean algebra A is separable if there exists a D of nonzero elements of A which is dense in A, i.e. such that for every a A, with 2 a = 0, there is an element a0 D with a0 a. A Boolean algebra is atomless if it has 6 2  no atoms. An atom is a nonzero element a A such that, for every element a0 A 2 2 with a0 a; we have either a0 = a or a0 = 0, where 0 is the zero element of A.  In view of the results of section 3 we are particularly interested in the Boolean algebras in separable Stone spaces. To deal with them we introduce a cardinal function. Let s be a countable subset of the Stone space Ult(A). Let d( ) be the cardinal function  on A de…ned by

d(A) = min s : s is a dense subset of Ult(A) : fj j g

Clearly, Ult(A) is separable i¤ d(A) = 0. @ Remark. Unlike [10], we denote by Bai(X) the Baire -…eld of X and not the -…eld of subsets with the Baire property. Moreover, we call Baire subsets the elements of Bai(X).

3 Existence of residual measures

We begin by proving a quite useful existence result.

Proposition 3 Let X be a separable T1 space. Then there exists a residual regular measure i¤ X has an isolated point.

Proof. If x is an isolated point, the Dirac probability measure x is a residual regular measure. For the converse, suppose that X is perfect (i.e. X has no isolated points).

7 Since X is a T1 space, all singletons x , for x X, are closed subsets. Since X is f g 2 perfect, no singleton can be at the same time both open and closed. So int( x ) = f g ? and the singletons are nowhere dense subsets. Let s be a countable dense subset of X and let P be a regular residual measure. We have P (s) = 0 since P ( x ) = 0; the f g singletons being nowhere dense subsets. Then P (s) = x s P ( x ) = 0: Since s is a 2 f g dense subset, X s does not contain any nonempty open subset. This implies that all n P closed subsets c contained in X s are such that int(c) = ?, i.e. they are nowhere n dense subsets. Then P (c) = 0: Since P is regular, we have:

P (X s) = sup P (c): c X s and c closed : n f  n g It follows P (X s) = 0 and so P (X) = P (X s) + P (s) = 0 for any regular residual n n measure P:  Remark. After the …rst draft of this paper was completed, I have found a similar result in [6, p.113]. However my proof is di¤erent and more direct than that given in [6]. Remark. The Borel measure on [0; 1] is not residual. In fact, there exists a nowhere dense subset with positive Borel measure. This set is constructed like the Cantor set, except that now, at each stage, are deleted intervals of length 3n , with 0 < < 1: The set has Borel measure 1 , and it is nowhere dense. For later reference, we denote this set by c . In [5, proposition 5] it is stated that in a perfect metric space cannot exist a nonzero residual measure which is compact regular. In [2, proposition 4a] it is proved that there exists a nonzero -additive residual measure on a metric space X i¤ X has an isolated point. We can give a more general result.

Proposition 4 Let X be a metric space. Then there exists a nonzero residual measure i¤ X has an isolated point.

Proof. In [5, p.249] it is proved that a perfect metric space contains a dense subset s which is meager. Let P be a residual measure. Then P (s) = 0: Since s is dense, we have int(X s) = ?. Moreover, since X is a metric space, P is regular. Therefore, n in order to complete the proof it su¢ ces to follow the same reasoning employed in the …nal part of the proof of proposition 3. 

8 Proposition 4 is a partial generalization of the well known fact that an Euclidean space can be decomposed in two sets, one of Lebesgue measure zero, the other meager. In proposition 4 we considered metric spaces. Similar results hold for other topo- logical spaces, as the next proposition shows. Here T3 means regular and T1.

Proposition 5 Let X be a T3 separable space. Then there exists a residual measure i¤ X has an isolated point.

Proof. A separable space has the countable chain property. Therefore it follows from [2, proposition 2a] and from [1, proposition 6] that every residual measure is - additive. On the other hand, by [7, theorem 5.4] every -additive probability measure on a regular space is a regular probability measure. A simple application of proposition 3 completes the proof.  Now we turn to nonatomic residual measures. The next proposition contains some non–existence results for this class of measures. In particular, points (i) and (iv) will be employed in section 4. We denote by Is(X) the set of all isolated points of the space X.

Proposition 6 (i) Let X be a T3 separable space. Then there is no nonzero nonatomic residual measure.

(ii) Let X be a separable metric space. Then there is no nonzero nonatomic residual measure.

(iii) Let X be a T3 space such that Is(X) forms a dense subset. If Is(X) is nonmeasurable, then there is no nonatomic residual measure. (iv) Let X be a compact Hausdor¤ space such that Is(X) forms a dense subset. Then there is no nonatomic and regular residual measure. Proof. (i) Let P be a nonatomic residual measure. Since P is nonatomic, P ( x ) = 0 f g for all x X. In particular, if s is the countable dense subset of X which exists 2 by hypothesis, we have P (s) = x S P ( x ) = 0: Observe that, if there are isolated 2 f g points in X, they are all contained in s. In fact int(X s) = ?. We have seen in the P n proof of proposition 5 that all residual measures on a separable T3 space are regular. Therefore a reasoning similar to the one employed in the proof of proposition shows that P (int(X s)) = 0: n

9 (ii) The proof is similar to the one of point (i). (iii) Let P be a nonatomic residual measure. Clearly the cardinal number of each pairwise disjoint family of open subsets is at most Is(X) . By [2, proposition 2a] every j j residual measure on X is -additive. In particular, P is -additive. Let I Is(X)  with I = 0. From point (i), we know that P (I) = 0: Now suppose that I Is(X) j j @  with I = 1. Let us denote the ordinal numbers by Greek letters. It is known that j j @ the set I can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the ordinal numbers less than 1 so that can be written I = x : < 1 (see [16, proposition 3.27]). Set @ f @ g

h = x : < 1 : f  @ g [ The collection h : < 1 is a monotone increasing net with respect to set inclusion. f @ g Every isolated point is a clopen subset. So h is an open subset for every ordinal number . By de…nition, we have I = h : < 1 . Therefore it holds P (I) = f @ g sup P (h ): < 1) because P is -additive. From what we have already proved f @ S for I = 0, we can say that P (h ) = 0 for each < 1. Therefore P (I) = 0: This j j @ @ implies that every subset of Is(X) of cardinality 1 has measure zero. Using trans…nite @ induction, it is easy to extend this conclusion to all cardinals Is(X) . In particular @  j j P (Is(X)) = 0. Since Is(X) is a dense subset, we have int(X Is(X)) = ?. Since all n -additive measures on a T3 space are regular, a reasoning similar to the one employed in the proof of proposition 3 shows that P (int(X s)) = 0: n (iv) A compact regular Borel probability measure is -additive. Therefore the proof is similar to the one of point (iii). 

4 The existence of probability measures on Boolean algebras

The existence results proved in the previous section have interesting applications for the study of probability measures de…ned on Boolean algebras. We begin with a con- sequence of proposition 5.

Proposition 7 Let A be an atomless Boolean algebra with d(A) = 0. Then there is @ no nonzero probability measure on A.

10 Proof. Let Bai(Ult(A)) be the Baire -…eld of Ult(A). It is known that Bai(Ult(A)) coincides with the -…eld generated by Clop(Ult(A)), i.e. (Clop(Ult(A))). Then M 0 is the collection of all meager Baire subsets. Let P be a probability measure on A. Set 1 1 P = P  h : F [0; 1] and Ps = P s : Clop(Ult(A)) [0; 1]. By propositions   !  ! 1 and 2, Ps and P are probability measure, respectively, on Clop(Ult(A)) and on . # F Let P be the restriction of P to Clop(Ult(A)). If a A, we have: 2 # 1 P (s(a)) = P(s(a)) = P ( (h(s(a))) 1 = P ( ((a))) = P (a) = Ps(s(a)):

# Therefore P Ps, and P is the probability measure which extends Ps on .  F Clearly M 0 and it is easy to check that P(v) = 0 for all v M 0. From  F 2 the inclusions Clop(Ult(A)) F Bai(Ult(A)), it follows (F ) = Bai(Ult(A)).   By Caratheodory extension theorem there is a unique probability measure P 0 which extends Ps from Clop(Ult(A)) to Bai(Ult(A)). Clearly P 0 coincides with P on . F The Boolean algebra A satis…es the countable chain condition (c.c.c.). Suppose not.

Let ai i I A be a set of pairwise disjoint and nonzero elements with I > 0. f g 2  j j @ Then s(ai) i I is a set of pairwise disjoint elements in Ult(A). Moreover s(ai) = ? f g 2 6 for all i I since ai is nonzero. But Ult(A) is separable and so it satis…es the c.c.c. 2 for topological spaces. Since the s(ai) are clopen subsets, this implies that at most a countable number of the s(ai) are non-empty. This contradiction shows that A satis…es the c.c.c.. Therefore, by proposition 2, every nowhere dense subset in Ult(A) is -nowhere dense, i.e. it is contained in a closed nowhere dense subset c such that c = 1 ui for some ui Clop(A). Clearly c Bai(Ult(A)). Let a Ult(A) be a i=1 2 2  meager subset. Then a = 1 a , with a nowhere dense subsets. By proposition 2, T i=1 i i

S 1 1 a = ai ci i=1  i=1 [ [ where the ci are closed and Baire nowhere dense subsets. Since 1 ci Bai(Ult(A)), i=1 2 it follows that every meager subset is contained in a Baire meager subset. Let Bor(Ult(A)) S be the Borel -…eld of Ult(A). Since Ult(A) is compact and Hausdor¤, there exists a unique regular extension P 00 from Bai(Ult(A)) to Bor(Ult(A)) (see [3, p.183]). Let M be the -ideal of all meager Borel subsets of Ult(A). If a M, we know that there is 2 a subset a0 M 0 such that a a0. Since P 0(a0) = 0; it follows that P 00(a) = 0, i.e. P 00 2  11 is a residual measure. Furthermore, P 00 is just the unique extension of P 0. In fact, by now it is clear that every extension of P 0 is residual. And we have seen in the proof of proposition 5 that each residual measure on a -…eld like Bor(Ult(A)) is regular. But, there is a unique regular extension. To sum up, we have proved that the existence of a nonzero probability measure

P on A implies the existence of a unique nonzero residual and regular measure P 00 on

Bor(Ult(A)). However, by proposition 5 we have P 00 0: Therefore, by contraposition,  P 0:   In [9, theorem 3.2] it was proved that on a separable atomless Boolean algebra there is no nonzero probability measure. This result is now an easy consequence of our proposition 7, as shown by the next corollary.

Corollary 1 Let A be a separable atomless Boolean algebra. Then there is no nonzero probability measure on A.

Proof. In view of the proof of proposition 7, it su¢ ces to show that Ult(A) is separable. By hypothesis there exists a countable dense subset D of A. Let s : A Ult(A) be ! the Stone isomorphism. For every f Clop(Ult(A)) there exists a subset v s(D) 2 2 such that ? = v f. Since Clop(Ult(A)) is a base for Ult(A), it follows that s(D) 6  is a pseudobase for Ult(A). Let xv v for every v s(D). It is easy to check that 2 2 xv v s(D) is a countable dense subset of Ult(A).  f g 2 While [9, theorem 3.2] is a consequence of proposition 7, the following result shows that the converse is not true.

Proposition 8 There exists an atomless Boolean algebra A with d(A) = 0, but not @ separable.

I 0 Proof. Let us consider the generalized Cantor space 2 with I = 2@ . According

I 0 to [17, theorem 14.3] its dual …eld Clop(2 ) is a free Boolean algebra with 2@ free generators. So Clop(2I ) is atomless (cf. [10, proposition 9.11]) and has a separable Stone space ([10, corollary 9.7a] and [17, §14E]). However Clop(2I ) is not a separable Boolean algebra (cf. [9, p.479]).  Remark. As shown by corollary 1 and proposition 8, proposition 7 extends the result of Horn and Tarski. Moreover, the proof they gave was algebraic. Instead, our proof of proposition 7 is mainly of topological nature.

12 The next proposition shows a rather interesting fact. It says that we can keep the result of proposition 7 by replacing the atomlessness assumption on A with a nonatomicity assumption on the probability measure.

Proposition 9 Let A be a Boolean algebra with d(A) = 0. Then there is no nonzero @ nonatomic probability measure on A.

Proof. Suppose that P is a nonzero probability measure on A. From the proof of proposition 7 we know that this implies the existence of a nonzero, regular and residual 1 measure P 00 on Bor(Ult(A)). Now suppose that P is nonatomic. Set Ps = P s :  Clop(Ult(A)) [0; 1]. We already know that Ps coincides with the restriction of ! P 00 on Clop(Ult(A)). It is a simple matter to verify that Ps is nonatomic. Let g be a open subset of Ult(A). We have g = i I fi with fi Clop(Ult(A) because 2 2 Clop(Ult(A) is a base. Let g = f : and g . Since P 00 is -additive, f S  g we have P 00(g) = sup P 00(g ): g . If P 00(g) > 0; then a reasoning similar to f S g the one employed in the proof of proposition 6(iv) allows us to say that there is some fi Clop(Ult(A) such that Ps(fi) > 0: Since Ps is nonatomic, fi is not a Ps-atom. 2 A fortiori, fi is not a P 00-atom. Therefore g is not a P 00-atom. Let c be a closed subset of Ult(A). We have P 00(c) = P 00(int(c)) because the boundary b(c) is a nowhere dense Borel subset. Suppose P 00(c) > 0: Then P 00(int(c)) > 0 and c is not a P 00- atom. Let a Bor(Ult(A)). Since P 00 is regular we have P 00(A)= sup P 00(c): c a and 2 f  c Ult(A) . If P 00(a) > 0; then P 00(c) > 0 for some c. Therefore a is not a P 00-atom 2 g and this implies that P 00 is nonatomic. Hence, by proposition 6(i) we have P 00 0 and  so, by contraposition, P 0:   Proposition 9 shows a class of Boolean algebras which do not admit nonatomic probability measures. A special case of interest is now considered.

Corollary 2 Let A be an atomic Boolean algebra which satis…es the c.c.c.. Then there is no nonzero nonatomic probability measure on A.

Proof. It is known that if a Boolean algebra is atomic, then the subset of the isolated point is dense in the Stone space. Since A satis…es the c.c.c., then there are at most a countable number of isolated points. Therefore, Is(Ult(A)) is a countable dense subset of Ult(A), and so d(A) = 0. @ 

13 5 The range of a nonatomic probability measure

Let P be a nonatomic probability measure de…ned on a Boolean algebra which satis…es the c.c.c.. Using some constructions of the previous sections, we prove that the range R(P ) of P is a dense subset of the unit interval. To do this we need the following result, that can be proved with the techniques used in [11].

Proposition 10 Let X be a topological space on which the open Baire subsets G(X) form a base, and let 0 be a Baire measure which has a inner regular and weakly - additive Borel extension 00. Then R(G(X)) is dense in R(00).

The announced result is now an easy consequence of the last result.

Proposition 11 Let P be a nonatomic probability measure de…ned on a Boolean al- gebra A which satis…es the c.c.c.. Then R(P ) is a dense subset of [0; 1].

Proof. From the proof of proposition 9 we know that P implies the existence of a regular, nonatomic and residual probability measure P 00 on Bor(Ult(A)). Since X is compact, P 00 is also compact regular and so -additive. By proposition 10;R(P ) is dense in R(P 00). But, being P 00 nonatomic, it is known that R(P 00) = [0; 1].  Remarks. (i) In looking at this result it is important to keep in mind the distinc- tion between measures on Boolean algebras and measures on …elds outlined in section 2. In fact, the example given there shows that this result is not true for probability measures de…ned on …elds. (ii) Let Bor( ) be the Borel -…eld of the real line. Let < N be the -ideal of the subsets with Lebesgue measure zero. The quotient algebra Bor( )=N does not have a separable Stone space (cf. [17, p.95]). But Bor( )=N sat- < < is…es the c.c.c.. In fact, on Bor( )=N there exists a nonzero strictly positive -…nite < measure induced by the Lebesgue measure. This example shows that proposition 9 does not con‡ict with proposition 11.

References

[1] W. Adamski, Note on support-concentrated Borel measures, J. Austral. Math. Soc. (Series A) 29 (1980), 310-315.

14 [2] T.E. Armstrong and K. Prikry, Residual measures, Illinois J. Math. 22 (1978), 64-78

[3] R. Ash, Real analysis and probability, Academic Press, New York, 1972.

[4] G. Debreu, Economies with a …nite set of values, Econometrica 38 (1970), 387-392.

[5] B. Fishel and D. Papert, A note on hyperdi¤use measures, J. London Math. Soc. 39 (1964), 245-254.

[6] J. Flachsmeyer, Normal and category measures on topological spaces, in Gen. Top. and Relations, III, Prague, 1972, 109-116.

[7] R.J. Gardner, The regularity of Borel measures and Borel measure compactness, Proc. London Math. Soc. (3) 30 (1975), 95-113.

[8] E. Hewitt, A note on measures in Boolean algebras, Duke Math. J. 20 (1952), 253-256.

[9] A. Horn and A. Tarski, Measures in Boolean algebras, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 64 (1948), 467-497.

[10] S. Koppelberg, General theory of Boolean algebras, in Monk J.D. (ed.), Hanbook of Boolean algebras vol.1, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989.

[11] M. Marinacci, A note on comparative probability structures, mimeo, 1993.

[12] E. Marczewski and R. Sikorski, Measures in non-separable metric spaces, Coll. Math. 1 (1948), 133-139.

[13] E. Marczewski and R. Sikorski, Remarks on measure and category, Coll. Math. 2 (1949), 13-19.

[14] A. Mas-Colell, The theory of general economic equilibrium: a di¤erentiable ap- proach, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985.

[15] J.C. Oxtoby, Measure and category, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1971.

[16] J.R. Rosenstein, Linear orderings, Academic Press, New York, 1982.

15 [17] R. Sikorski, Boolean algebras, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1969.

[18] R. Sikorski, Distributivity and representability, Fund. Math. 48 (1960), 91-103.

[19] L.K. Simon and M.B. Stinchcombe, Equilibrium re…nement for in…nite normal form games, Econometrica 63 (1995), 1421-1443.

16