Deontic Modality and the Semantics of Choice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Deontic Modality and the Semantics of Choice Philosophers’ 1 volume 15, no. 28 1. Two Puzzles Imprint october 2015 Suppose I say to you (1) You may have the gin or the whiskey. may(G or W) As you help yourself to the latter, I cry, “Stop! You can’t have 2 DEONTIC whiskey.“ It seems that I have contradicted myself. For how, given (1), could your action have been impermissible? That we hear sentences like (1) MODALITY AND as communicating that you may have the gin, and you may have the 3 whiskey, is the puzzle, or paradox, of free choice permission. Free choice permission is usually glossed as a felt entailment from THE SEMANTICS OF a narrow-scope disjunction under may to a wide scope conjunction: (FC) may(f or y) ) (may f) ^ (may y) But more can be added to this characterization. Most speakers have the CHOICE strong intuition that while the permission in (1) communicates that one may choose the gin and one may choose the whiskey, it emphatically fails to communicate the permissibility of the corresponding narrow- scope conjunction, which would allow you to have both: (2) You may have the gin and the whiskey. Melissa Fusco may(G ^ W) . and perhaps even entails that (2) is false. This feature goes by the University of California, Berkeley name exclusivity: 1. Thanks to John MacFarlane, Seth Yalcin, Wes Holliday, Lara Buchak, Alex 2015 Kocurek, Stephen Darwall, Chris Barker, Jim Pryor, and two anonymous refer- © , Melissa Fusco ees at Philosophers’ Imprint for helpful feedback on this paper. For stimulating This work is licensed under a Creative Commons discussion, I am also indebted to audiences at UC Berkeley, UC Santa Cruz, New York University, and Magdalen College, Oxford. Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License 2. For readability, and where it causes no confusion, I will be loose with use <www.philosophersimprint.org/015028/> and mention. 3. See Hans Kamp, “Free Choice Permission,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 74 (1973) and G. H. von Wright, An Essay on Deontic Logic and the General Theory of Action (Amsterdam, North Holand, 1968). melissa fusco Deontic Modality and the Semantics of Choice 6 (Exclusivity) may(f or y) ; may(f ^ y) (5) I ought to post the letter or burn it. ought(P or B) This observation is embedded in the scholarship on free choice permis- 4 1 2 sion. The tension between ( ) and ( ) is usually glossed as a scalar Again, it appears that something has gone wrong. For (4) does not 5 implicature. seem to entail (5). That this entailment is classically valid, but feels 7 Here is a second puzzle. Consider a similar situation, in which I say intuitively invalid, is Ross’s Puzzle: to you (R) ought(f) ; ought(f or y) (3) You ought to post the letter. A straightforward explanation of what is wrong with the inference ought P from (4) to (5) is that the introduced disjunct (here, burning the letter) is You reason as follows: impermissible. Recent work on Ross’s puzzle has pursued this intuitive route, investigating various ways of working out the thought that a 4 ( ) I ought to post the letter. Ross sentence ought(f or y) entails that there must be something to ought 8 P be said, deontically speaking, for each of the embedded disjuncts. Therefore, (R+) ought(f or y) ) (may f) ^ (may y) This looks like a unification with free choice permission: disjunction under both ought and may carry what we can call an entailment to 9 4. Chris Barker (“Free Choice Permission as Resource-Sensitive Reasoning,” disjunct permissibility. Semantics and Pragmatics 3 (2010)) writes that FC sentences like (1) “never“ guarantee conjunctions like (2). The failure of (1) to entail (2) is also as- A simple variation on Ross’s puzzle, due to Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, sumed by Mandy Simons (“Dividing Things Up: The Semantics of Or and the suggests that there is yet more to say about Ross sentences. Sayre- 13 3 2005 Modal/Or Interaction,” Natural Language Semantics / ( )), who calls it McCord observes that, according to the hypothesis that disjunction a “consensus in the literature“. Danny Fox, an implicature theorist, makes his psychological explanation of free choice permission dependent on a hearer’s introduction is blocked in the scope of ought just in case the intro- 2 rejection of ( ) (“Free Choice and the Theory of Scalar Implicatures,” in duced disjunct is impermissible, it would follow that, if y is known to U. Sauerland and P. Stateva (eds.), Presupposition and Implicature in Composi- tional Semantics (New York, Palgrave Macmillan, 2007)). Fox’s official position be permissible, then thus includes an endorsement of the stronger inference we may call and-false: may(f or y) ): may(f ^ y). However, Fox expresses some reservations about this inference — and thus the fact that his explanation of free choice 6. The post-burn disjunction is Ross’s original. permission relies on it — in the last section of his paper. 7. Alf Ross, “Imperatives and Logic,” Theoria 7/1 (1941) 5. Both (FC) and (Exclusivity) have been analyzed as scalar implicatures, the 8. See especially Fabrizio Cariani, “‘Ought’ and Resolution Semantics,” Noûs former of an unusual, post-Gricean kind, in the wake of Kratzer & Shimoyama 47/3 (2013), and Daniel Lassiter, “Nouwen’s Puzzle and a Scalar Semantics (“Indeterminate Pronouns: The View from Japanese,” in Proceedings of the Third for Obligations, Needs, and Desires,” in Proceedings of SALT 21 (2011), and Tokyo Conference on Psycholinguistics (2002)); see especially Fox, op. cit., and Gen- Measurement and Modality: The Scalar Basis of Modal Semantics (Ph. D. diss.), New naro Chierchia, “Broaden Your Views: Implicatures of Domain Widening and York University, 2011. the ‘Logicality’ of Language,” Linguistic Inquiry 37/4 (2006). I present an ar- 9. This apparent connection between free choice and Ross is noted by, amongst gument analyses of (FC) in the Kratzer and Shimoyama vein elsewhere (“Free others, Kai von Fintel (“The Best We Can (Expect to) Get?: Challenges to the Choice Permission and the Counterfactuals of Pragmatics,” Linguistics and Phi- Classic Semantics for Deontic Modals“, 2012), Cariani, op. cit., pg. 20–21, and losophy 37/4 (2014)). von Wright himself (op. cit., pg. 22). philosophers’ imprint - 2 - vol. 15, no. 28 (october 2015) melissa fusco Deontic Modality and the Semantics of Choice ought f should entail ought(f or y) < ought f ^ ought y ought f or y ( ) both obligatory — too strong < may f ^ may y in context. But, Sayre-McCord argues, “ought(f or y) cannot legitimately be both (merely) permissible — too weak 10 < ought f ^ may y _ ought y ^ may f inferred from ought f even when y is perfectly permissible". His ( ) ( ) example is as follows: suppose it is taken for granted that it is perfectly one of each — (SM) fine for Ralph to go to the movies; The example suggests we should switch tracks, and try to directly (6) Ralph may go to the movies. characterize situations that are appropriately described by sentences may M of the form ought(f or y). Suppose that I have come down with a cold this morning and am too sick to host my housewarming party is true. It is also true that tomorrow night. It seems appropriate to say: (7) Ralph ought to pay back his loan. (9) I ought to cancel or postpone the party. ought L If (9) is true, then canceling the party has a certain deontic status (that Still, of being obligatory), provided that I do not postpone, and postponing the (8) Ralph ought to pay back his loan or go to the movies. party has a certain deontic status (that of being obligatory), provided 9 ought(M or L) that I do not cancel. That nothing at all is said by ( ) about the situation where I both postpone and cancel is shown by the fact that (9) can be sounds wrong; it does not seem to follow from (6) and (7). Call this true, even though the conjunction, postpone and cancel, has no positive normative status at all: it would be rude to my guests to postpone the (SM) may y ^ ought f ; ought(f or y) party only to cancel it later, and it’s impossible to cancel a party and Sometimes, disjunction introduction in the scope of a deontic modal then to postpone it. fails even when the introduced disjunct is permissible. I propose, then, to add to the data associated with Ross sentences Sayre-McCord’s observation seems to show that there is no para- like (9): the deontic status of the act described by each disjunct depends phrase for the ‘or’ in a Ross sentence in terms of the unconditional de- on whether the other one is performed. Starting with a Ross sentence ontic status of the disjuncts expressible in the object language — that as a premise, an agent can reason with future-directed conditionals is, in terms of the deontic status each disjunct has, considered indepen- like this: dently of the other one. (Conditionals-O) I ought to do (f or y) ) If I do not do f, I ought to do y; 10. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, “Deontic Logic and the Priority of Moral Theory,” Noûs 20/2 (1986), pg. 189. philosophers’ imprint - 3 - vol. 15, no. 28 (october 2015) melissa fusco Deontic Modality and the Semantics of Choice I ought to do (f or y) ) If I do not do y, I ought to do f. these modal environments. Table 1 gives an interim summary of the intuitions that constitute our data. In addition being a promising paraphrase of (9), (Conditionals-O) 8 helps us to precisify our discomfort with Sayre-McCord’s defective ( ), May: ought where disjunction introduction in the scope of is blocked, even (Failure of ‘or’ intro) may f ; may(f or y) though the introduced disjunct is permissible.
Recommended publications
  • An Ultra-Condensed Introduction to Discourse Analysis: Two-Hour Tutorial at NICTA (National Information and Communication Technologies Australia)
    An ultra-condensed introduction to Discourse Analysis: two-hour tutorial at NICTA (National Information and Communication Technologies Australia) Rogelio Nazar Pontificia Universidad Católica de Valparaíso [email protected] 23 October 2015 Abstract: Linguistics has historically been devoted to the study of language as a system rather than its manifestation in particular texts. In spite of this, Discourse Analysis (DA) has been established for more than 60 years as a place of convergence of many disciplines interested in discourse. This tutorial is aimed at people with little or no knowledge of linguistic terminology and its purpose is to offer a shallow introduction to DA. This tutorial will not specifically address computational procedures for text analysis. On the contrary, the analytical methods explained here are to be conducted manually, but with systematic and almost mechanical methods. This is mainly a practical tutorial and the focus will be on analysing a real text in English. The first part presents the theoretical principles and analytical tools, while the rest is devoted to practical exercises implementing the proposed method. Given the limitations of time, this tutorial only comments upon a short number concepts. 1. Introduction It is a real pleasure for me to be here today in this not very sunny day in Canberra and I am delighted to have all of you here. As you probably know, I have been entrusted with the impossible task of summarizing 60 years of research in discourse analysis (DA) in a couple of hours. Facing such challenge, what I am going to do is not really to offer a real introduction, because we would need a semester course just to cover the essential readings.
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Sense Classification at Large / 3 Most Prominently, Epistemic (3.A), Deontic/Bouletic (3.B) and Circum- Stantial/Dynamic (3.C) Modality
    LiLT volume 14, issue 3 August 2016 Modal Sense Classification At Large Paraphrase-Driven Sense Projection, Semantically Enriched Classification Models and Cross-Genre Evaluations Ana Marasovićz?, Mengfei Zhouy?, Alexis Palmer?y, Anette Frankz y ?, zResearch Training Group AIPHES yLeibniz ScienceCampus “Empirical Linguistics and Computational Language Modeling” ?Department of Computational Linguistics Heidelberg University Abstract∗ Modal verbs have different interpretations depending on their context. Their sense categories – epistemic, deontic and dynamic – provide im- portant dimensions of meaning for the interpretation of discourse. Previous work on modal sense classification achieved relatively high performance using shallow lexical and syntactic features drawn from small-size annotated corpora. Due to the restricted empirical basis, it is difficult to assess the particular difficulties of modal sense classification and the generalization capacity of the proposed models. In this work we create large-scale, high-quality annotated corpora for modal sense classification using an automatic paraphrase-driven projec- tion approach. Using the acquired corpora, we investigate the modal sense classification task from different perspectives. We uncover the difficulty of specific sense distinctions by investigat- ∗This article represents an extension of prior work reported in Zhou (2015) and Zhou et al. (2015). It includes material of the published version in Zhou et al. (2015), with minor modifications. 1 2 / LiLT volume 14, issue 3 August 2016 ing distributional bias and reducing the sparsity of existing small-scale corpora used in prior work. We build a semantically enriched model for modal sense classification by designing novel features related to lexical, proposition-level and discourse-level semantic factors. Besides improved classification performance, closer examination of interpretable feature sets unveils relevant semantic and contextual factors in modal sense classification.
    [Show full text]
  • Factors Determining the Development of Discourse Competence in Advanced Learners of English Author
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Title: Factors determining the development of discourse competence in advanced learners of English Author: Marcin Jaroszek Citation style: Jaroszek Marcin. (2008). Factors determining the development of discourse competence in advanced learners of English. Praca doktorska. Katowice : Uniwersytet Śląski MARCIN JAROSZEK FACTORS DETERMINING THE DEVELOPMENT OF DISCOURSE COMPETENCE IN ADVANCED LEARNERS OF ENGLISH A LONGITUDINAL STUDY Ph.D. Dissertation submitted in part fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the English Language Institute of the University of Silesia. Written under the supervision of prof. dr hab. Maria Wysocka UNIWERSYTET ŚLĄSKI 2008 MARCIN JAROSZEK CZYNNIKI OKREŚLAJĄCE ROZWÓJ KOMPETENCJI DYSKURSU U ZAAWANSOWANYCH UCZNIÓW JĘZYKA ANGIELSKIEGO BADANIE PODŁUŻNE Rozprawa doktorska napisana w Instytucie Języka Angielskiego Uniwersytetu Śląskiego pod kierunkiem prof. dr hab. Marii Wysockiej UNIWERSYTET ŚLĄSKI 2008 Table of contents INTRODUCTION 5 PART ONE: THEORETICAL ASPECTS OF DISCOURSE COMPETENCE 7 DEVELOPMENT 1. Discourse and Discourse Competence 7 1.1 Defining discourse 8 1.2 Discourse Competence and Communicative Competence 10 1.3 Discourse Devices 14 1.3.1 Interaction vs. intra-action in discourse construction 15 1.3.2 Turn-taking 17 1.3.3 Discourse markers 19 1.3.4 Back-channel responses 20 1.3.5 Grammatical cohesion and textuality 20 1.3.6 Lexis and discourse 24 1.3.7 Conjunction 27 1.3.8 Modality 28 1.4 Competence vs. Performance 32 2. Educational factors determining discourse competence development 35 2.1 The role of input in discourse competence development 35 2.2 Classroom discourse vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Grammar and Levels of Addressivity Exploring Ungarinyin Engagement Received May 4, 2018; Accepted Jan 21, 2020
    Open Linguistics 2020; 6:1–18 Research Article Stef Spronck* Grammar and levels of addressivity Exploring Ungarinyin engagement https://doi.org/10.1515/opli-2020-0001 Received May 4, 2018; accepted Jan 21, 2020 Abstract: Evans et al. (2018a,b) introduce the notion of ‘engagement’ as a new grammatical domain related to intersubjective coordination of knowledge. The present paper applies this notion to data from the Aus- tralian Aboriginal language Ungarinyin. It identifies three markers/construction types in the language as ex- pressions of engagement and develops a descriptive framework rooted in Bakhtinian Dialogism in order to demonstrate why these expressions represent the category. It is argued that the main problems that arise in the analysis of engagement are very similar to those that have been encountered in the description of (other) TAME-categories as well, and that these may be overcome by applying Mikhail Bakhtin’s idea of ‘addressivity’. It concludes that a better understanding of the category of engagement that explores its relation to addressiv- ity may contribute to the development of an approach to grammar in which sociality takes priority, a Dialogic linguistics. Keywords: Dialogic linguistics; epistemicity; intersubjectivity; Ungarinyin 1 Introduction: observing and interpreting engagement ‘To say that the human being behaves individually at one moment and socially at another is as absurd as to declare that matter follows the laws of chemistry at a certain time and succumbs to the supposedly different laws of atomic physics at another’ (Sapir, 1949, 545) In an agenda-setting discussion of epistemicity in grammar, Evans et al. (2018a,b) argue for the adoption of a new grammatical category, that of engagement.
    [Show full text]
  • A Linguistically-Motivated Annotation Model of Modality in English and Spanish: Insights from MULTINOT
    LiLT volume 14, issue (4) August 2016 A linguistically-motivated annotation model of modality in English and Spanish: Insights from MULTINOT Julia LAVID, Marta CARRETERO and Juan Rafael ZAMORANO-MANSILLA, Universidad Complutense de Madrid Abstract In this paper we present current work on the design and validation of a linguistically-motivated annotation model of modality in English and Spanish in the context of the MULTINOT project.1 Our annotation model captures four basic modal meanings and their subtypes, on the one hand, and provides a fine-grained characterisation of the syntactic realisations of those meanings in English and Spanish, on the other. We validate the modal tagset proposed through an agreement study per- formed on a bilingual sample of four hundred sentences extracted from original texts of the MULTINOT corpus, and discuss the difficult cases encountered in the annotation experiment. We also describe current steps in the implementation of the proposed scheme for the large-scale annotation of the bilingual corpus using both automatic and manual procedures. 1The MULTINOT project is financed by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness, under grant number FF2012-32201. We gratefully acknowledge the support provided by the Spanish authorities. We also thank the comments and suggestions provided by the anonymous reviewers which have helped to improve the current manuscript. 1 2 / LiLT volume 14, issue (4) August 2016 1 Introduction In this paper we describe the construction and empirical validation of a modality annotation scheme for English and Spanish in the context of the MULTINOT project, whose main aim is the development of a parallel English-Spanish corpus which is balanced – in terms of register diversity and translation directions – and whose design and enrichment with multiple layers of linguistic annotations focuses on quality rather than on quantity (see Lavid et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Affirmative and Negated Modality*
    Quaderns de Filologia. Estudis lingüístics. Vol. XIV (2009) 169-192 AFFIRMATIVE AND NEGATED MODALITY* Günter Radden Hamburg 0. INTR O DUCTI O N 0.1. Stating the problem Descriptions of modality in English often give the impression that the behaviour of modal verbs is erratic when they occur with negation. A particularly intriguing case is the behaviour of the modal verb must under negation. In its deontic sense, must is used both in affirmative and negated sentences, expressing obligation (1a) and prohibition (1b), respectively. In its epistemic sense, however, must is only used in affirmative sentences expressing necessity (2a). The modal verb that expresses the corresponding negated epistemic modality, i.e. impossibility, is can’t (2b). (1) a. You must switch off your mobile phone. [obligation] b. You mustn’t switch off your mobile phone. [prohibition] (2) a. Your mobile phone must be switched off. [necessity] b. Your mobile phone can’t be switched off. [impossibility] Explanations that have been offered for the use of epistemic can’t are not very helpful. Palmer (1990: 61) argues that mustn’t is not used for the negation of epistemic necessity because can’t is supplied, and Coates (1983: 20) suggests that can’t is used because mustn’t is unavailable. Both “explanations” beg the question: why should can’t be used to denote negated necessity and why should mustn’t be unavailable? Such questions have apparently not been asked for two interrelated reasons: first, the study of modality and negation has been dominated by logic and, secondly, since the modal verbs apparently do * An earlier version of this paper was published in Władysław Chłopicki, Andrzej Pawelec, and Agnieszka Pokojska (eds.), 2007, Cognition in Language: Volume in Honour of Professor Elżbieta Tabakowska, 224-254.
    [Show full text]
  • Modality and Factivity: One Perspective on the Meaning of the English Modal Auxiliaries
    MODALITY AND FACTIVITY: ONE PERSPECTIVE ON THE MEANING OF THE ENGLISH MODAL AUXILIARIES by NICOLA M,BREWER Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of PhD The University of Leeds Department of Linguistics and Phonetics December 1987 ii ABSTRACT This study concentrates on modality as expressed by the set of modal auxiliaries and seeks to establish that these verbs share semantic as well as syntactic properties by identifying a single core meaning which they share. The relationship between modality and factivity is examined with the aim of gaining an insight into the former, more complex concept. When viewed from this perspective, the defining characteristic of all the modal auxiliary verbs in almost all of their uses is found to be nonfactivity. The meanings expressed by this set of verbs are classified according to a framework derived from modal logic consisting of three basic types of modality each of which relates to a different set of laws or principles; the relative factivity associated with the modal auxiliaries is seen to vary with the nature of modality as defined and classified by this framework. Within each of the three types of modality, a semantic scale is identified and modality is described as a gradable concept for which scalar analysis is appropriate, both within and beyond these three scales. Relative factivity is also shown to vary according to the degree of modality expressed by each of the modal verbs. The nature and degree of modality expressed interact with features of the linguistic (and pragmatic) context to determine the particular factive or a contrafactive interpretation conveyed by a given modal auxiliary token.
    [Show full text]
  • MODULATING GRAMMAR THROUGH MODALITY: a DISCOURSE APPROACH* Francisco Gonzálvez García Universidad De Almería
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by idUS. Depósito de Investigación Universidad de Sevilla ELIA I, 2000 MODULATING GRAMMAR THROUGH MODALITY: A DISCOURSE APPROACH* Francisco Gonzálvez García Universidad de Almería This paper argues for a dynamic, discourse-based approach to modality which departs from the traditional, monolithic account of modality in a number of interesting respects: (i) modality is characterized as conveying the speaker’s involvement in the propositional content of a given utterance (either in the form of agency or subjectivity) (ii) modality can be said to ramify across the whole lexico-grammatical architecture of the language, (iii) many of the meanings usually ascribed to individual modal verbs are in fact derived either from the verb’s sentential environment or from some wider context of utterance, and (iv) modal meaning in discourse can be said to arise out of the interaction of two closely connected layers of meaning: one embracing the inherent linguistic meaning of the modal verb in conjunction with that of other neighbouring modal devices, and another concerned with principles connected with politeness and face-saving strategies. 1. Introduction Modality in English and other languages has been the focus of attention of scholars from distinct disciplines and approaches over the last thirty years. Within linguistics, the study of modality has witnessed a gradual shift from a monolithic, static conception to a more dynamic understanding of modality taking into account the relevance of linguistic and extralinguistic contextual factors in the production and interpretation of modal utterances in discourse (Bybee & Fleischman 1995) or the creation of modal textual * I would like to express my gratitude to Paul J.
    [Show full text]
  • Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science January 2000 Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts Rajesh Bhatt University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Bhatt, Rajesh, "Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts" (2000). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 32. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/32 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-00-01. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/32 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts Abstract This dissertation investigates the distribution and interpretation of covert modality. Three environments where covert modality appears are analyzed. These environments are infinitival relative clauses, infinitival questions, and ability modals. Infinitival relative clauses are shown to not form a unified class structurally. Subject infinitival relative clauses are assimilated to the class of reduced relative clauses. They lack a CP projection. Non-subject infinitival relative are assimilated to the class of full relative clauses. Like full relatives, they have a CP projection. The infinitival [+wh] Cº is argued to be the source of the modality in a non-subject infinitival relative clause. All nonsubject infinitival relative clauses and infinitival questions involve modality because of the obligatory presence of the infinitival [+wh] Cº. Since subject infinitival relative clauses do not involve the infinitival [+wh] Cº, they are not necessarily modal. If they are modal, the source of the modality lies within the infinitival clause. The conditions under which a subject infinitival relative can receive a non-modal interpretation are analyzed.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Modality and Deontic Modality at the Crossroads
    Proceedings of The 3rd Annual International Conference Syiah Kuala University (AIC Unsyiah) 2013 In conjunction with The 2nd International Conference on Multidisciplinary Research (ICMR) 2013 October 2-4, 2013, Banda Aceh, Indonesia EPISTEMIC MODALITY AND DEONTIC MODALITY AT THE CROSSROADS JUMINO SUHADI Department of English Literature, Faculty of LiteratureIslamic University of North Sumatra, Medan, Indonesia. Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT This article is a descriptive survey on the similarities and differences between epistemic and deontic modalities as introduced by Halliday (1994: )and Downing and Locke (199: 283) . Epistemic modality refers to the use of modality which is based on the speaker's evaluation and judgment in relation to the degree of confidence of the knowledge on the proposition. It functions to comment on and evaluate an interpretation of reality in carrying out speech functions. Deontic modality indicates whether the proposition expressed by a command is obligatory, advisable or permissible according to some normative backgroundsuch as law, morality, convention, etc. In many instances, the meanings of some modals are relative and complements to each other. The evidence of some extrinsic modalities such as must, should, may, and can indicates that they may fall under different types; thus, they are at the crossroads; two types of modality which may use the same realization but they goes to different meanings. Keywords:Systemic Functional Linguistics, epistemic modality, deontic modality, Introduction One of the three metafunctions of language in Systemic Functional Grammar pioneered by Halliday (1994) is the interpersonal function, in which language is used to express a speaker’s attitude and judgment for communicating with others.
    [Show full text]
  • Deontic Modality, Generically
    Deontic Modality, Generically Federico L. G. Faroldi Abstract This position paper aims to explore some preliminary suggestions to develop a theory of deontic modalities under a generic understanding. I suggest, for in- stance, that a sentence such as ‘Everyone ought to pay taxes’ is true just in case the generic (deontically relevant) individual pays taxes. Different degrees of generic- ity are explored, without assuming too much about a specific theory of genericity. I argue that such an analysis captures our intuitions about exceptions and the gen- eral character of deontic claims better than classical approaches based on possible- world semantics and than defeasibility-based approaches, while remaining within a broadly deductive framework. [...] law can never issue an injunction binding on all which really embodies what is best for each: it cannot prescribe with perfect accuracy what is good and right for each member of the community at any one time. The differences of human personality, the variety of men’s activities and the inevitable unsettlement attending all human experience make it impossible for any art whatsoever to issue unqualified rules holding good on all questions at all times [...] [one] will lay down laws in general form [for the majority, roughly meeting the cases of individuals [...] under average circumstances. Plato Politicus, 294a–b. [...] all law is universal but about some things it is not possible to make a universal statement which shall be correct. In those cases, then, in which it is necessary to speak universally, but not possible to do so correctly, the law takes the usual case, though it is not ignorant of the possibility of error.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic and Deontic Modality: a Linguistic Indicator of Disciplinary Variation in Academic English
    Epistemic and Deontic Modality: A Linguistic Indicator of Disciplinary Variation in Academic English Jordi Piqué-Angordans (Universitat de València, Spain) Santiago Posteguillo (Universitat Jaume I de Castelló, Spain) J.-Vicent Andreu-Besó (Universitat de València, Spain) 1. Modalization and disciplinary variation in academic English According to pragmatic linguistic analyses, language has to be analyzed and interpreted in relation to the social context which generates and uses it. Language is not to be considered an isolated system of either symbols or mental rules, but a system used in a specific setting and for specific communicative purposes. It is within this pragmatic paradigm that English for Specific Purposes (ESP) develops in the 60s and continues to the present. In this context, RAs are among the most widely researched genres, but most of these studies have focused on their structural organization (Crookes, 1986; Swales, 1990; Nwogu, 1990, 1991, 1997; Bhatia, 1993; Berkenkotter & Huckin, 1995; Posteguillo, 1996a-b, 1999; Estévez & Piqué, 1997; Piqué & Andreu-Besó, 2000), or on the structural organizations of individual sections within the RA itself (Swales, 1981; Dudley-Evans & Henderson, 1990; Brett, 1994; Holmes, 1997; Piqué & Andreu-Besó, 1998; Bloor, 1999). It is true that these macrostructural descriptions represent a major feature of RAs as a genre, but there are other linguistic and communicative phenomena which differentiate the RA from other genres which have not been analyzed in such detail, especially having in mind disciplinary variation. For instance, some other authors have studied alternative discourse functions of RAs, such as the use of citations and 49 references (Jordan, 1990), or the use of argumentation (Hyland, 1990; Thompson, 1993).
    [Show full text]