Baronett's Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Baronett's Logic Baronett’s Logic (4th ed.) Section Tips Chapter 8: Seven Tips 8B Implication Rules I Think of the first four rules of inference as rules allowing you to create complex statements (Hypothetical Syllogism), or break them apart (Modus Ponens, Modus Tollens, and Disjunctive Syllogism). 8D Implication Rules II The second four inference rules allow you to create complex statements (Conjunction and Addition), or break them apart (Constructive Dilemma and Simplification). Don’t be intimidated by the complexity of Constructive Dilemma. It’s basically two instances of Modus Ponens: Separate out the left side of dot in Premise 1, the left side of wedge in Premise 2, and the left side of wedge in the conclusion: p q p q Now do the same for the right side of the main operator in Premise 1, the right side of wedge in Premise 2, and the right side of wedge in the conclusion: r s r s In both cases, you’ve got Modus Ponens! Now, if it’s true that you have both p q and r s, and you have p or r, it follows that you have q or s. 8E Replacement Rules I and 8F Replacement Rules II Think about De Morgan’s as instances of “pushing the negation through” and swapping out wedge for dot or dot for wedge. Remember, logically equivalent statements are those that logically mean the same thing. So, for example, to assert one statement, p • q is to assert its logically equivalent statement, q • p. Association involves moving a pair of parentheses from one conjunction in a complex sentence to another conjunction in the same sentence. The same applies to a sentence involving more than one disjunction. If you’re uncertain about whether or not a replacement rule really reflects logical equivalence (and some may be counterintuitive), construct a truth table. Use your knowledge of logical equivalence from Chapter 7F. .
Recommended publications
  • 7.1 Rules of Implication I
    Natural Deduction is a method for deriving the conclusion of valid arguments expressed in the symbolism of propositional logic. The method consists of using sets of Rules of Inference (valid argument forms) to derive either a conclusion or a series of intermediate conclusions that link the premises of an argument with the stated conclusion. The First Four Rules of Inference: ◦ Modus Ponens (MP): p q p q ◦ Modus Tollens (MT): p q ~q ~p ◦ Pure Hypothetical Syllogism (HS): p q q r p r ◦ Disjunctive Syllogism (DS): p v q ~p q Common strategies for constructing a proof involving the first four rules: ◦ Always begin by attempting to find the conclusion in the premises. If the conclusion is not present in its entirely in the premises, look at the main operator of the conclusion. This will provide a clue as to how the conclusion should be derived. ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in the consequent of a conditional statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via modus ponens. ◦ If the conclusion contains a negated letter and that letter appears in the antecedent of a conditional statement in the premises, consider obtaining the negated letter via modus tollens. ◦ If the conclusion is a conditional statement, consider obtaining it via pure hypothetical syllogism. ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in a disjunctive statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via disjunctive syllogism. Four Additional Rules of Inference: ◦ Constructive Dilemma (CD): (p q) • (r s) p v r q v s ◦ Simplification (Simp): p • q p ◦ Conjunction (Conj): p q p • q ◦ Addition (Add): p p v q Common Misapplications Common strategies involving the additional rules of inference: ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in a conjunctive statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via simplification.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 10: Symbolic Trails and Formal Proofs of Validity, Part 2
    Essential Logic Ronald C. Pine CHAPTER 10: SYMBOLIC TRAILS AND FORMAL PROOFS OF VALIDITY, PART 2 Introduction In the previous chapter there were many frustrating signs that something was wrong with our formal proof method that relied on only nine elementary rules of validity. Very simple, intuitive valid arguments could not be shown to be valid. For instance, the following intuitively valid arguments cannot be shown to be valid using only the nine rules. Somalia and Iran are both foreign policy risks. Therefore, Iran is a foreign policy risk. S I / I Either Obama or McCain was President of the United States in 2009.1 McCain was not President in 2010. So, Obama was President of the United States in 2010. (O v C) ~(O C) ~C / O If the computer networking system works, then Johnson and Kaneshiro will both be connected to the home office. Therefore, if the networking system works, Johnson will be connected to the home office. N (J K) / N J Either the Start II treaty is ratified or this landmark treaty will not be worth the paper it is written on. Therefore, if the Start II treaty is not ratified, this landmark treaty will not be worth the paper it is written on. R v ~W / ~R ~W 1 This or statement is obviously exclusive, so note the translation. 427 If the light is on, then the light switch must be on. So, if the light switch in not on, then the light is not on. L S / ~S ~L Thus, the nine elementary rules of validity covered in the previous chapter must be only part of a complete system for constructing formal proofs of validity.
    [Show full text]
  • Argument Forms and Fallacies
    6.6 Common Argument Forms and Fallacies 1. Common Valid Argument Forms: In the previous section (6.4), we learned how to determine whether or not an argument is valid using truth tables. There are certain forms of valid and invalid argument that are extremely common. If we memorize some of these common argument forms, it will save us time because we will be able to immediately recognize whether or not certain arguments are valid or invalid without having to draw out a truth table. Let’s begin: 1. Disjunctive Syllogism: The following argument is valid: “The coin is either in my right hand or my left hand. It’s not in my right hand. So, it must be in my left hand.” Let “R”=”The coin is in my right hand” and let “L”=”The coin is in my left hand”. The argument in symbolic form is this: R ˅ L ~R __________________________________________________ L Any argument with the form just stated is valid. This form of argument is called a disjunctive syllogism. Basically, the argument gives you two options and says that, since one option is FALSE, the other option must be TRUE. 2. Pure Hypothetical Syllogism: The following argument is valid: “If you hit the ball in on this turn, you’ll get a hole in one; and if you get a hole in one you’ll win the game. So, if you hit the ball in on this turn, you’ll win the game.” Let “B”=”You hit the ball in on this turn”, “H”=”You get a hole in one”, and “W”=”you win the game”.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 109, Modern Logic Russell Marcus
    Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Hamilton College Fall 2014 Russell Marcus Reference Sheeet for What Follows Names of Languages PL: Propositional Logic M: Monadic (First-Order) Predicate Logic F: Full (First-Order) Predicate Logic FF: Full (First-Order) Predicate Logic with functors S: Second-Order Predicate Logic Basic Truth Tables - á á @ â á w â á e â á / â 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 0 1 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 1 1 0 1 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 Rules of Inference Modus Ponens (MP) Conjunction (Conj) á e â á á / â â / á A â Modus Tollens (MT) Addition (Add) á e â á / á w â -â / -á Simplification (Simp) Disjunctive Syllogism (DS) á A â / á á w â -á / â Constructive Dilemma (CD) (á e â) Hypothetical Syllogism (HS) (ã e ä) á e â á w ã / â w ä â e ã / á e ã Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic, Prof. Marcus; Reference Sheet for What Follows, page 2 Rules of Equivalence DeMorgan’s Laws (DM) Contraposition (Cont) -(á A â) W -á w -â á e â W -â e -á -(á w â) W -á A -â Material Implication (Impl) Association (Assoc) á e â W -á w â á w (â w ã) W (á w â) w ã á A (â A ã) W (á A â) A ã Material Equivalence (Equiv) á / â W (á e â) A (â e á) Distribution (Dist) á / â W (á A â) w (-á A -â) á A (â w ã) W (á A â) w (á A ã) á w (â A ã) W (á w â) A (á w ã) Exportation (Exp) á e (â e ã) W (á A â) e ã Commutativity (Com) á w â W â w á Tautology (Taut) á A â W â A á á W á A á á W á w á Double Negation (DN) á W --á Six Derived Rules for the Biconditional Rules of Inference Rules of Equivalence Biconditional Modus Ponens (BMP) Biconditional DeMorgan’s Law (BDM) á / â -(á / â) W -á / â á / â Biconditional Modus Tollens (BMT) Biconditional Commutativity (BCom) á / â á / â W â / á -á / -â Biconditional Hypothetical Syllogism (BHS) Biconditional Contraposition (BCont) á / â á / â W -á / -â â / ã / á / ã Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic, Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic
    An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic Rebeka Ferreira and Anthony Ferrucci 1 1An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. 1 Preface This textbook has developed over the last few years of teaching introductory symbolic logic and critical thinking courses. It has been truly a pleasure to have beneted from such great students and colleagues over the years. As we have become increasingly frustrated with the costs of traditional logic textbooks (though many of them deserve high praise for their accuracy and depth), the move to open source has become more and more attractive. We're happy to provide it free of charge for educational use. With that being said, there are always improvements to be made here and we would be most grateful for constructive feedback and criticism. We have chosen to write this text in LaTex and have adopted certain conventions with symbols. Certainly many important aspects of critical thinking and logic have been omitted here, including historical developments and key logicians, and for that we apologize. Our goal was to create a textbook that could be provided to students free of charge and still contain some of the more important elements of critical thinking and introductory logic. To that end, an additional benet of providing this textbook as a Open Education Resource (OER) is that we will be able to provide newer updated versions of this text more frequently, and without any concern about increased charges each time.
    [Show full text]
  • MGF1121 Course Outline
    MGF1121 Course Outline Introduction to Logic............................................................................................................. (3) (P) Description: This course is a study of both the formal and informal nature of human thought. It includes an examination of informal fallacies, sentential symbolic logic and deductive proofs, categorical propositions, syllogistic arguments and sorites. General Education Learning Outcome: The primary General Education Learning Outcome (GELO) for this course is Quantitative Reasoning, which is to understand and apply mathematical concepts and reasoning, and analyze and interpret various types of data. The GELO will be assessed through targeted questions on either the comprehensive final or an outside assignment. Prerequisite: MFG1100, MAT1033, or MAT1034 with a grade of “C” or better, OR the equivalent. Rationale: In order to function effectively and productively in an increasingly complex democratic society, students must be able to think for themselves to make the best possible decisions in the many and varied situations that will confront them. Knowledge of the basic concepts of logical reasoning, as offered in this course, will give students a firm foundation on which to base their decision-making processes. Students wishing to major in computer science, philosophy, mathematics, engineering and most natural sciences are required to have a working knowledge of symbolic logic and its applications. Impact Assessment: Introduction to Logic provides students with critical insight
    [Show full text]
  • Logic Informed by Justin Bledin a Dissertation Submitted in Partial
    Logic Informed By Justin Bledin A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Logic and the Methodology of Science in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor John MacFarlane, Chair Professor Niko Kolodny Professor Seth Yalcin Professor Paolo Mancosu Professor Hans Sluga Fall 2013 Abstract Logic Informed by Justin Bledin Doctor of Philosophy in Logic and the Methodology of Science University of California, Berkeley Professor John MacFarlane, Chair I develop an informational conception of logic as a science fundamentally concerned not with truth but with information. Facts about logical validity, on this conception, tell us about the structure of the bodies of information that we generate, encounter, absorb, and exchange as we interact with one another and learn about our world. I also investigate the normative role of logic in our epistemic practices. In particular, I argue against the widespread idea that there are rational requirements to have logically coherent beliefs that are not merely epiphenomenal on evidential norms. 1 Contents 1 Introduction: Rival Conceptions of Logic 1 2 The Truth Preservation View of Logic 6 3 Against Truth Preservation 13 3.1 |=T r Versus Good Argument . 13 3.2 Sophisticated Truth Preservation . 15 3.3 Truth Preservation Versus Good Argument . 19 3.3.1 Trouble With Descriptivism . 20 3.3.2 Expressivism . 22 3.3.3 Modality With Content . 25 4 The Informational View of Logic 29 4.1 Responses . 29 4.2 A Better Option . 32 5 Modus Ponens Defended 35 5.1 Kolodny and MacFarlane .
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Thinking
    Critical Thinking Mark Storey Bellevue College Copyright (c) 2013 Mark Storey Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License, Version 1.3 or any later version published by the Free Software Foundation; with no Invariant Sections, no Front-Cover Texts, and no Back-Cover Texts. A copy of the license is found at http://www.gnu.org/copyleft/fdl.txt. 1 Contents Part 1 Chapter 1: Thinking Critically about the Logic of Arguments .. 3 Chapter 2: Deduction and Induction ………… ………………. 10 Chapter 3: Evaluating Deductive Arguments ……………...…. 16 Chapter 4: Evaluating Inductive Arguments …………..……… 24 Chapter 5: Deductive Soundness and Inductive Cogency ….…. 29 Chapter 6: The Counterexample Method ……………………... 33 Part 2 Chapter 7: Fallacies ………………….………….……………. 43 Chapter 8: Arguments from Analogy ………………………… 75 Part 3 Chapter 9: Categorical Patterns….…….………….…………… 86 Chapter 10: Propositional Patterns……..….…………...……… 116 Part 4 Chapter 11: Causal Arguments....……..………….………....…. 143 Chapter 12: Hypotheses.….………………………………….… 159 Chapter 13: Definitions and Analyses...…………………...…... 179 Chapter 14: Probability………………………………….………199 2 Chapter 1: Thinking Critically about the Logic of Arguments Logic and critical thinking together make up the systematic study of reasoning, and reasoning is what we do when we draw a conclusion on the basis of other claims. In other words, reasoning is used when you infer one claim on the basis of another. For example, if you see a great deal of snow falling from the sky outside your bedroom window one morning, you can reasonably conclude that it’s probably cold outside. Or, if you see a man smiling broadly, you can reasonably conclude that he is at least somewhat happy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Deduction Theorem and Ecology
    The Deduction Theorem And Ecology By Edward M. Hulburt Woods Hole Oceanographic Institution Woods Hole, MA U.S.A. 02543 ABSTRACT The deduction theorem is based primarily on the formula [A⊃ (B⊃C)] ⊃ [(A⊃B) ⊃ (A⊃C)]. The fisheries of Newfoundland, Iceland, and west Greenland have three aspects, a first aspect of abundance of cod or herring, aspect A, a second aspect of overfishing or overfishing plus hydrographic change, aspect B, and a third aspect of collapse of the cod-herring fishery or shift to shrimp, aspect C. Each aspect implies, connects to the next either in [A⊃(B⊃C)] sequence or in the [(A⊃B) ⊃ (A⊃C)] double sequence. The Mississippi River system has three parts, the drainage area of the inner U.S.A., part A, the plankton-rich, low salinity plume to the west of the Mississippi delta, part B, and the oxygen-depleted near-bottom layer of the plume, part C. These parts are connected, as shown by the implication connective, ⊃. There are two indirect applications of the deduction theorem. The first is three aspects of hotspots, each hotspot being a region having a set of many indigenous species and having set of endangered species, the two sets being identical by having all the same species (the principle of extensionality). The second indirect application is three logically valid formulas that describe most of the natural world. A is contraposition, an example of which is: a vertebrate is adapted to year-round temperate temperature if it is functional (active) year- round; if and only if a vertebrate is not adapted to year-round temperate temperature only if it is not functional (not active) year-round.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Natural Deduction and Elementary Logic Textbooks
    A History of Natural Deduction and Elementary Logic Textbooks Francis Jeffry Pelletier 1 Introduction In 1934 a most singular event occurred. Two papers were published on a topic that had (apparently) never before been written about, the authors had never been in contact with one another, and they had (apparently) no common intellectual background that would otherwise account for their mutual interest in this topic. 1 These two papers formed the basis for a movement in logic which is by now the most common way of teaching elementary logic by far, and indeed is perhaps all that is known in any detail about logic by a number of philosophers (especially in North America). This manner of proceeding in logic is called ‘natural deduction’. And in its own way the instigation of this style of logical proof is as important to the history of logic as the discovery of resolution by Robinson in 1965, or the discovery of the logistical method by Frege in 1879, or even the discovery of the syllogistic by Aristotle in the fourth century BC.2 Yet it is a story whose details are not known by those most affected: those ‘or- dinary’ philosophers who are not logicians but who learned the standard amount of formal logic taught in North American undergraduate and graduate departments of philosophy. Most of these philosophers will have taken some (series of) logic courses that exhibited natural deduction, and may have heard that natural deduc- tion is somehow opposed to various other styles of proof systems in some number of different ways.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Logic a Proposition Is a Statement Or a Sentence That Is Either True Or False, but Not Both
    Propositional Logic A proposition is a statement or a sentence that is either true or false, but not both. See the examples below; each one of them is a proposition: • Earth is a planet. This proposition is always true. • The sun and the moon are the same objects. This proposition is always false. • All my students enjoy my course. The truth value of this proposition varies based on several conditions but it will have one of the two values true or false. • I will get `A' in this course. The reader is urged to find the truth value of this proposition. Propositions can be combined using one or more of the logical operators listed below. Symbol Name Synopsis : negation : p ^ conjunction p ^ q _ disjunction p _ q ) implication p ) q : p _ q , equivalence p , q (p ) q) ^ (q ) p) The synopsis in the above table uses variable names to indicate the whole proposition. For example, a variable p may indicate the proposition \My wallet was stolen". The truth value of a proposition involving logical operators can be evaluated using a truth table. See the example below: p q : p : q p ^ q : (p ^ q) : p _: q T T F F T F F T F F T F T T F T T F F T T F F T T F T T Two propositions are said to be logically equivalent if and only if they are evaluated to the same truth value. In the truth table shown above, the two propositions : (p ^ q) and : p _: q evaluate to the same truth values (see the two columns in the truth table corresponding to these two propositions) and hence they are logically equivalent.
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 245 F17, Exam 1 Solutions 1. Carefully Define the Following Terms
    MATH 245 F17, Exam 1 Solutions 1. Carefully define the following terms: ≤ (for integers, as defined in Chapter 1), factorial, Associativity theorem (for propositions), Distributivity theorem (for propositions). Let a; b be integers. We say that a ≤ b if b − a 2 N0. The factorial is a function from N0 to Z (or N), denoted by !, defined by: 0! = 1 and n! = (n − 1)! · n (for n ≥ 1). The Associativity theorem says: Let p; q; r be propositions. Then (p ^ q) ^ r ≡ p ^ (q ^ r) and also (p _ q) _ r ≡ p _ (q _ r). The Distributivity theorem says: Let p; q; r be propositions. Then p ^ (q _ r) ≡ (p ^ q) _ (p ^ r) and also p _ (q ^ r) ≡ (p _ q) ^ (p _ r). 2. Carefully define the following terms: Addition semantic theorem, Contrapositive Proof theorem, Direct Proof, converse. The Addition semantic theorem states that for any propositions p; q, we have p ` p _ q. The Contrapositive Proof theorem states that for any propositions p; q, if (:q) ` (:p) is valid, then p ! q is T The Direct Proof theorem states that for any propositions p; q, if p ` q is valid, then p ! q is T . The converse of conditional proposition p ! q is q ! p. 3. Let a; b be odd. Prove that 4a − 3b is odd. Because a is odd, there is integer c with a = 2c + 1. Because b is odd there is integer d with b = 2d + 1. Now, 4a − 3b = 4(2c + 1) − 3(2d + 1) = 8c + 4 − 6d − 3 = 2(4c − 3d) + 1.
    [Show full text]