Quantum Mechanics and Consciousness
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Prof. Beck Riassunto
John Eccles' Struggle for a Dualistic Mind-Brain Relation Friedrich Beck Darmstadt University of Technology Abstract We experience the world through our sensory organs, and translate these impressions into our ideas of nature's functional behaviour. Experience tells us that our actions lead to a unique and predetermined result: the thrown ball stays in its calculable trajectory which is determined by gravitation and air friction. Natural processes , e.g. earth quakes or volcanic eruptions, are, however, not always predictable. The reason is the complex situation in which many unknown parameters enter the game. Nevertheless, we believe that also such processes follow deterministic laws. This situation leads to the mind-brain problem. Even when the brain, this most complex structure of biological evolution, is non-calculable in its dynamical reaction on external stimuli, we believe that, contrary to the deterministic processes in nature, our will allows us free actions which we can freely impose on our brain: the self controls the brain! The struggle between determinism and self-consciousness marks the source of difficulties which occupied John Eccles throughout his scientific career, and which he saw coming to a wonderful solution during the last decade of his life. Descartes dualism, which was the first rational formulation of dualism and interactionism: 'cogito ergo sum' - I am thinking, so I am existing - run into a seemingly irresolvable contradiction when natural science succeeded to derive all processes in nature from deterministic and causal natural laws. How can the mind control the brain when this material entity underlies the causal dynamics of nature? Materialism has a quick answer at hand: the independent mind, or self, is nothing more than an artefact of the complex and non-calculable brain dynamics. -
The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle
University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department Classics and Religious Studies July 2007 The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle Thomas Nelson Winter University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub Part of the Classics Commons Winter, Thomas Nelson, "The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle" (2007). Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department. 68. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub/68 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Classics and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Th e Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle Th omas N. Winter Lincoln, Nebraska • 2007 Translator’s Preface. Who Wrote the Mechanical Problems in the Aristotelian Corpus? When I was translating the Mechanical Problems, which I did from the TLG Greek text, I was still in the fundamentalist authorship mode: that it survives in the corpus of Aristotle was then for me prima facie Th is paper will: evidence that Aristotle was the author. And at many places I found in- 1) off er the plainest evidence yet that it is not Aristotle, and — 1 dications that the date of the work was apt for Aristotle. But eventually, 2) name an author. I saw a join in Vitruvius, as in the brief summary below, “Who Wrote Th at it is not Aristotle does not, so far, rest on evidence. -
Abstract for Non Ideal Measurements by David Albert (Philosophy, Columbia) and Barry Loewer (Philosophy, Rutgers)
Abstract for Non Ideal Measurements by David Albert (Philosophy, Columbia) and Barry Loewer (Philosophy, Rutgers) We have previously objected to "modal interpretations" of quantum theory by showing that these interpretations do not solve the measurement problem since they do not assign outcomes to non_ideal measurements. Bub and Healey replied to our objection by offering alternative accounts of non_ideal measurements. In this paper we argue first, that our account of non_ideal measurements is correct and second, that even if it is not it is very likely that interactions which we called non_ideal measurements actually occur and that such interactions possess outcomes. A defense of of the modal interpretation would either have to assign outcomes to these interactions, show that they don't have outcomes, or show that in fact they do not occur in nature. Bub and Healey show none of these. Key words: Foundations of Quantum Theory, The Measurement Problem, The Modal Interpretation, Non_ideal measurements. Non_Ideal Measurements Some time ago, we raised a number of rather serious objections to certain so_called "modal" interpretations of quantum theory (Albert and Loewer, 1990, 1991).1 Andrew Elby (1993) recently developed one of these objections (and added some of his own), and Richard Healey (1993) and Jeffrey Bub (1993) have recently published responses to us and Elby. It is the purpose of this note to explain why we think that their responses miss the point of our original objection. Since Elby's, Bub's, and Healey's papers contain excellent descriptions both of modal theories and of our objection to them, only the briefest review of these matters will be necessary here. -
Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
Aristotle (384-322 BCE) The Pythagoreans, Socrates, and Plato attempted to reconcile an element of human freedom with material determinism and causal law. But the first major philosopher to argue convincingly for some indeterminism was probably Aristotle. This is despite the fact that he described a causal chain back to a prime mover or first cause, and he elaborated the four possible causes (material, efficient, formal, and final). In his Physics and Metaphysics Aristotle also said there were "accidents" caused by "chance(τυχή)." In his Physics, he clearly reckoned chance among the causes. Aristotle might have added chance as a fifth cause - an uncaused or self-caused cause - that happens when two causal chains come together by accident (συμβεβεκός). He noted that the early physicists found no place for chance among the causes. Aristotle knew that many decisions were quite predictable based on habit and character, but they were no less free if one's character itself and predictable habits were developed freely in the past and were changeable in the future. This was the view of Eastern philosophies and religions. Our karma has been determined by our past actions (even from past lives), and strongly influences our current actions, but we are free to improve our karma by future good actions. As a principal architect of the concept of causality, and the formulator of the four causes, Aristotle's statements on indefinite causes are perhaps his most significant contribution to freedom, in the world and in human decisions. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle makes the case for chance and uncaused causes (causa sui) and in the Nicomachean Ethics he shows our actions can be voluntary and "up to us" so that we can be morally responsible. -
Politics Aristotle
Politics Aristotle Translated by Benjamin Jowett Batoche Books Kitchener 1999 Contents BOOK ONE .............................................................................. 3 BOOK TWO ........................................................................... 22 BOOK THREE ....................................................................... 51 BOOK FOUR ......................................................................... 80 BOOK FIVE ......................................................................... 108 BOOK SIX ........................................................................... 140 BOOK SEVEN ..................................................................... 152 BOOK EIGHT ...................................................................... 180 BOOK ONE Part I Every state is a community of some kind, and every community is es- tablished with a view to some good; for mankind always act in order to obtain that which they think good. But, if all communities aim at some good, the state or political community, which is the highest of all, and which embraces all the rest, aims at good in a greater degree than any other, and at the highest good. Some people think that the qualifications of a statesman, king, house- holder, and master are the same, and that they differ, not in kind, but only in the number of their subjects. For example, the ruler over a few is called a master; over more, the manager of a household; over a still larger number, a statesman or king, as if there were no difference be- tween a great household and a small state. The distinction which is made between the king and the statesman is as follows: When the government is personal, the ruler is a king; when, according to the rules of the politi- cal science, the citizens rule and are ruled in turn, then he is called a statesman. But all this is a mistake; for governments differ in kind, as will be evident to any one who considers the matter according to the method which has hitherto guided us. -
5. the Eccles-Beck Approach. Sir John Eccles Suggested in 1990, In
5. The Eccles-Beck Approach. Sir John Eccles suggested in 1990, in the Proceedings of the Royal Society (Eccles 1990), that quantum theory plays a key role in the workings of the conscious brain. Based in part on his discussions with Henry Margenau (See Margenau 1984), Eccles noted that the statistical element in quantum theory allows an escape from the rigid determinism of classical physics that has plagued philosophy since the time of Isaac Newton. In his later book “How the self controls its Brain” Eccles (1994) notes that , “There is of course an entrenched materialist orthodoxy, both philosophic and scientific, that rises to defend its dogmas with a self-righteousness scarcely equaled in the ancient days of religious dogmatism.” He says at the outset that, “Following Popper (1968) I can say: I wish to confess, however, at the very beginning, that I am a realist: I suggest somewhat like a naïve realist that there is a physical world and a world of states of consciousness, and that these two interact.” Eccles gives “two most weighty reasons” for rejecting the classical- physics-based concept of materialism. (Eccles 1994, p,9) First, classical physics does not entail the existence or emergence of the defining characteristic of consciousness, namely “feelings,” and hence entails no theory of consciousness. Second, because the nature of the mapping between brain states and states of consciousness never enters into the behavior of an organism, there is no evolutionary reason for consciousness to be closely connected to behavior, which it clearly is. Eccles’ approach to the mind-brain problem has three main points. -
On Perfect Friendship: an Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship
Colby College Digital Commons @ Colby Honors Theses Student Research 2010 On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship Kristen Psaty Colby College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Other Philosophy Commons Colby College theses are protected by copyright. They may be viewed or downloaded from this site for the purposes of research and scholarship. Reproduction or distribution for commercial purposes is prohibited without written permission of the author. Recommended Citation Psaty, Kristen, "On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship" (2010). Honors Theses. Paper 589. https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses/589 This Honors Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Research at Digital Commons @ Colby. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Colby. ON PERFECT FRIENDSHIP: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship By Kristen Psaty Honors Thesis Philosophy Department © 2010 1 For Megan The one who brings out the best in me. To Kyle My other self . & to the ∆ΠΠ 2 “This has always been a man's world, and none of the reasons that have been offered in explanation have seemed adequate.” -Simone de Beauvoir Special Thanks to Lydia Moland, Valerie Dionne, Holly Moore and Thanks also to readers Amy Holmen and Elise Breed. 3 Table of Contents INTRODUCTION ………………………………………………. 6 CHAPTER I. ……………………………………………………. 13 An Introduction to Aristotle on Friendship CHAPTER II. -
Continuity and Discontinuity. an Epistemological Inquiry Based on the Use of Categories in History of Science*
ORGANON 41:2009 Raffaele Pisano (Nantes, France) - Ilaria Gaudiello (Paris, France) CONTINUITY AND DISCONTINUITY. AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL INQUIRY BASED ON THE USE OF CATEGORIES IN HISTORY OF SCIENCE* 1. Introduction Generally, historical inquiry proceeds according to different levels of knowledge, both scientific and humanist, and through particular methods and instruments of research, for example in the history of foundations, in the scientific-cultural attitude of a particular historical period rather than in the historical-social consequences in the history of technologies. In the last century research about the foundations of science seems to have been forwarded increasingly by programs of research more than through the implementation of a basic theory. Several competitive research programs have covered the period from the turn of the 19lh century to and throughout the 20th century. In the following we list some notes on Mach, Koyre and Kuhn to introduce the importance of the use of categories. Ernst Waldfried Josef Wenzel Mach (1838-1916) generated a radically new vision of foundations of physics'. This new vision implied a deep criticism2 toward Newton mechanics, particularly with regard to the metaphysical concepts of absolute space and time. Moreover, the concept of cause-force ultimately substituted the concept of work as the fundamental concept exploited by theoretical physics as well as the human mind to the extent it engages in related theorizing activity. Therefore, although mechanics is traditionally considered to be the basic theory in theoretical physics, thermodynamics should rather play this pivotal role. The contribution supplied by Mach can thus be considered especially relevant for the history of scientific thought. -
Craft As a Larger Pursuit of Human Happiness
CRAFT AS A LARGER PURSUIT OF HUMAN HAPPINESS Eva Perez de Vega May 2012 CRAFT AS A LARGER PURSUIT OF HUMAN HAPPINESS ABSTRACT p. 1 ARISTOTELIAN CONCEPTION OF HAPPINESS: CRAFT AND PRUDENCE p. 2 1.1 Happiness and human function 1.2 Aristotle’s concept of craft and prudence TOWARDS AN INTEGRATED VIEW OF CRAFT AND PRUDENCE p. 9 2.1 Shortcomings of Aristotle’s perspective 2.2 Craft, prudence and affordance CRAFT AND NECESSITY p. 15 3.1 Craft prior to use: invention 3.2 Craft after use: form follows function 3.3 Use embedded in craft: affordance CONCLUSION p. 21 4.1 Structure of argument 4.2 Appropriations and assumptions BIBLIOGRAPHY & ILLUSTRATIONS p. 23 Eva Perez de Vega ABSTRACT This paper aims to explore the concept of craft as it relates to the larger pursuit of human happiness. Starting with Aristotle’s conception of craft and prudence developed in the Nichomachian Ethics, we will see how they are critical to his overall view of human happiness, but also problematic when viewed in isolation. For Aristotle, craft is concerned solely with the thoughts and processes that go into making (production) while prudence deals with the thoughts and processes that go into determining its best use (activity). By providing specific examples and supported by the notion of affordance, the aim of this paper is to show that craft already embeds in its very making multiple possibilities of use, and thus encompasses a sense of prudence. The arguments presented also aim to show that Aristotle’s concept of craft and prudence recognize that human creative activity is indispensible towards achieving happiness. -
Physics and the Philosophy of Science at the Turn of the Twentieth Century
Physics and the Philosophy of Science at the Turn of the Twentieth Century (Forthcoming in the Enciclopedia Italiana di Storia della Scienza under the title, “Fisica e Filosofia della Scienza all’Alba del XX Secolo”) I believe that philosophy can be helped to its feet again only if it devotes itself seriously and fervently to investigations of cognitive processes and the methods of science. There it has a real and legitimate task . Philosophy has obviously come to a standstill because it . still has taken no new life from the vigorous development of the natural sciences. — Hermann von Helmholtz to Adolf Fick, ca. 1875 (as quoted in Koenigsberger 1902–1903, 243) Introduction: Disciplinary Symbiosis Theoretical physics and the philosophy of science are among the most important fields of research in the twentieth century, this as gauged both by their prominence within their respective disciplines and by their broader social and intellectual impact. Yet in 1850 neither field, as we know it today, would have been recognized in the academy or elsewhere as constituting an autonomous mode of inquiry with associated institutional structures. With hindsight, each might be glimpsed in germ. Some would read Hermann von Helmholtz’s 1847 lecture, Über die Erhaltung der Kraft (Helmholtz 1848) as marking the advent of the search for generalizable explanatory structures whose deployment is a distinguishing mark of theoretical physics. Some would read Auguste Comte’s Cours de philosophie positive (1830–1842) or William Whewell’s The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1840) as inaugurating the systematic study of those general questions about scientific method, the nature and limits of scientific knowledge, and the structure and interpretation of scientific theories whose focal significance later defined the field in the form made famous by the members of the Vienna Circle. -
Taking Aristotle Seriously: Republican-Oriented Legal Theory and The
Taking Aristotle Seriously: Republican- Oriented Legal Theory and the Moral Foundation of Deliberative Democracy Miriam Galston TABLE OF CONTENTS I. The Political Nature of Human Beings: Sacrifice or Self-Interest? ............. 339 A. Reliance on Aristotle's Statement About the Political Nature of Human Beings .............................. 340 B. The Meaning of "Nature" in Aristotle's Statement that Human Beings Are by Nature Political ................. 345 C. The Theoretical Basis for Aristotle's Statement that Human Beings Are by Nature Political ................. 349 D. Consequences of Aristotle's Interpretation of the Political Nature of Human Beings ...................... 353 II. Realizing Our Political Nature: The Approach of Contemporary Republican-Oriented Legal Theory ........... 354 A. Dialogue and the Scrutiny of Unexamined Opinion ..... 355 B. The Willingness to Talk, Listen, and Abide ............. 361 I. Realizing Our Political Nature: The Aristotelian Approach... 371 A. The Domain of Practical Reason for Aristotle and Contemporary Legal Theorists ......................... 371 B. The Dependency of Practical Reason on Character ...... 372 C. The Development of Good Character ................... 376 IV. The Consequences of Aristotle's Ideas for the Contemporary Deliberative Project ......................... 378 V. Aristotle's Reply to Contemporary Fears ................... 386 A. The Rational Capacity of Citizens ...................... 387 B. The Multiplicity of Human Types ...................... 391 Conclusion ..................................................... -
Bulletin of the German Historical Institute Washington DC 44
Bulletin of the German Historical Institute 44 | Spring 2009 5 Preface FEATURES 9 The Natural Sciences and Democratic Practices: Albert Einstein, Fritz Haber, and Max Planck Margit Szöllösi-Janze 23 Comment on Margit Szöllösi-Janze’s “The Natural Sciences and Democratic Practices” Cathryn Carson 29 Gender, Sexuality, and Belonging: Female Homosexuality in Germany, 1890-1933 Marti M. Lybeck 43 The Peaceful Revolution of the Fall of 1989 Marianne Birthler 59 Human Dignity and the Freedom of the Press Jutta Limbach GHI RESEARCH 71 Billy Graham’s Crusades in the 1950s: Neo-Evangelicalism between Civil Religion, Media, and Consumerism Uta Andrea Balbier CONFERENCE REPORTS 83 Proto-Eugenic Thinking before Galton Christoph Irmscher 89 Nature’s Accountability: Aggregation and Governmentality in the History of Sustainability Sabine Höhler and Rafael Ziegler 95 Trajectories of Decolonization: Elites and the Transformation from the Colonial to the Postcolonial Sönke Kunkel 100 Symposium in Memoriam of Gerald D. Feldman Uwe Spiekermann 104 Terrorism and Modernity: Global Perspectives on Nineteenth Century Political Violence Roni Dorot and Daniel Monterescu 112 A Whole New Game: Expanding the Boundaries of the History of Sports Christopher Young 118 Decoding Modern Consumer Societies: Preliminary Results, Ongoing Research, and Future Agendas Uwe Spiekermann 123 Global Migration Systems of Domestic and Care Workers Anke Ortlepp 128 17th Annual Symposium of the Friends of the GHI and Award of the Fritz Stern Dissertation Prize Richard F. Wetzell 130 Engineering Society: The “Scientifi cation of the Social” in Comparative Perspective, 1880-1990 Jochen F. Mayer 137 Writing East German History: What Difference Does the Cultural Turn Make? Heather L.