Taking Aristotle Seriously: Republican-Oriented Legal Theory and The
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle
University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department Classics and Religious Studies July 2007 The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle Thomas Nelson Winter University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub Part of the Classics Commons Winter, Thomas Nelson, "The Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle" (2007). Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department. 68. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub/68 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Classics and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Th e Mechanical Problems in the Corpus of Aristotle Th omas N. Winter Lincoln, Nebraska • 2007 Translator’s Preface. Who Wrote the Mechanical Problems in the Aristotelian Corpus? When I was translating the Mechanical Problems, which I did from the TLG Greek text, I was still in the fundamentalist authorship mode: that it survives in the corpus of Aristotle was then for me prima facie Th is paper will: evidence that Aristotle was the author. And at many places I found in- 1) off er the plainest evidence yet that it is not Aristotle, and — 1 dications that the date of the work was apt for Aristotle. But eventually, 2) name an author. I saw a join in Vitruvius, as in the brief summary below, “Who Wrote Th at it is not Aristotle does not, so far, rest on evidence. -
Abstract for Non Ideal Measurements by David Albert (Philosophy, Columbia) and Barry Loewer (Philosophy, Rutgers)
Abstract for Non Ideal Measurements by David Albert (Philosophy, Columbia) and Barry Loewer (Philosophy, Rutgers) We have previously objected to "modal interpretations" of quantum theory by showing that these interpretations do not solve the measurement problem since they do not assign outcomes to non_ideal measurements. Bub and Healey replied to our objection by offering alternative accounts of non_ideal measurements. In this paper we argue first, that our account of non_ideal measurements is correct and second, that even if it is not it is very likely that interactions which we called non_ideal measurements actually occur and that such interactions possess outcomes. A defense of of the modal interpretation would either have to assign outcomes to these interactions, show that they don't have outcomes, or show that in fact they do not occur in nature. Bub and Healey show none of these. Key words: Foundations of Quantum Theory, The Measurement Problem, The Modal Interpretation, Non_ideal measurements. Non_Ideal Measurements Some time ago, we raised a number of rather serious objections to certain so_called "modal" interpretations of quantum theory (Albert and Loewer, 1990, 1991).1 Andrew Elby (1993) recently developed one of these objections (and added some of his own), and Richard Healey (1993) and Jeffrey Bub (1993) have recently published responses to us and Elby. It is the purpose of this note to explain why we think that their responses miss the point of our original objection. Since Elby's, Bub's, and Healey's papers contain excellent descriptions both of modal theories and of our objection to them, only the briefest review of these matters will be necessary here. -
Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
Aristotle (384-322 BCE) The Pythagoreans, Socrates, and Plato attempted to reconcile an element of human freedom with material determinism and causal law. But the first major philosopher to argue convincingly for some indeterminism was probably Aristotle. This is despite the fact that he described a causal chain back to a prime mover or first cause, and he elaborated the four possible causes (material, efficient, formal, and final). In his Physics and Metaphysics Aristotle also said there were "accidents" caused by "chance(τυχή)." In his Physics, he clearly reckoned chance among the causes. Aristotle might have added chance as a fifth cause - an uncaused or self-caused cause - that happens when two causal chains come together by accident (συμβεβεκός). He noted that the early physicists found no place for chance among the causes. Aristotle knew that many decisions were quite predictable based on habit and character, but they were no less free if one's character itself and predictable habits were developed freely in the past and were changeable in the future. This was the view of Eastern philosophies and religions. Our karma has been determined by our past actions (even from past lives), and strongly influences our current actions, but we are free to improve our karma by future good actions. As a principal architect of the concept of causality, and the formulator of the four causes, Aristotle's statements on indefinite causes are perhaps his most significant contribution to freedom, in the world and in human decisions. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle makes the case for chance and uncaused causes (causa sui) and in the Nicomachean Ethics he shows our actions can be voluntary and "up to us" so that we can be morally responsible. -
Dædalus Coming up in Dædalus: Dædalus on Life Anthony Kenny, Thomas Laqueur, Shai Lavi, Lorraine Daston, Paul Rabinow, Robert P
Dædalus coming up in Dædalus: Dædalus on life Anthony Kenny, Thomas Laqueur, Shai Lavi, Lorraine Daston, Paul Rabinow, Robert P. George, Robert J. Richards, Nikolas Rose, John Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences Broome, Jeff McMahan, and Adrian Woolfson Fall 2007 on nature Leo Marx, William Cronon, Cass Sunstein, Daniel Kevles, Bill McKibben, Harriet Ritvo, Gordon Orians, Camille Parmesan, Margaret Schabas, and Philip Tetlock & Michael Oppenheimer 2007: on the public interest Fall on the E. J. Dionne Jr. Why the public interest matters now 5 on cosmopolitanism Martha C. Nussbaum, Margaret C. Jacob, A. A. Long, Pheng Cheah, public interest William A. Galston An old debate renewed 10 Darrin McMahon, Helena Rosenblatt, Samuel Scheffler, Arjun Adam Wolfson From James Madison to Abraham Lincoln 20 Appadurai, Rogers Smith, Peter Brooks, and Craig Calhoun Nathan Glazer Reflections on an elusive goal 30 plus poetry by Ted Richer, C. D. Wright &c.; ½ction by Chris Abani, Jagdish Bhagwati Some implications for economic policy 37 Wesley Brown, Alix Ohlin &c.; and notes by Phyllis Coley, Don Gary Hart The commonwealth ideal 45 Harrán, Richard Kraut, Ian Ayres &c. Christine Todd Whitman Governing in the public interest: then & now 51 Robert N. Bellah Ethical politics: reality or illusion? 59 Amy Gutmann The dangers of extremist rhetoric 70 Lance Taylor Economists & the wealth of nations 79 poetry Molly McQuade Spring’s So Sad, We Want to Know Why 88 ½ction Mary Gordon Dilly 89 dialogue Cornel West & D. Graham Burnett On Melville’s The Con½dence-Man 101 notes Omer Bartov on Eastern Galicia’s past & present 115 Harriet Ritvo on the animal turn 118 U.S. -
Book Review: Justice and Equality: Here and Now
University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1987 Book Review: Justice and Equality: Here and Now. Edited by Frank S. Lucash. David P. Bryden Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Bryden, David P., "Book Review: Justice and Equality: Here and Now. Edited by Frank S. Lucash." (1987). Constitutional Commentary. 234. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/234 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1987] BOOK REVIEW 493 IV In 1974, Charles H. Sheldon summed up a debate within the political science fraternity between "traditionalists" and "behavi oralists." The debate appears to have peaked during the 1960s. He wrote: This debate has been leveled at the question of the use of values in research and at the methodologies common to the behavioralists. The dialogue takes a scientific versus non- or antiscientific perspective, with the behavioralist claiming that the traditionalist fails to be scientific enough, and the traditionalist arguing that the behavioralist confuses science with methodology. Robert McCloskey has ob served " ... that the fraternity in general is now receptive to the methods and in sights ofbehavioralism in so far as it finds them helpful; ... and that the discipline is about ready for a new movement ...." The new movement is upon us. The post-behavioral revolution in political science demands that we be concerned for the contemporary world and its problems even if we must sacrifice some of our scientific rigor. -
Politics Aristotle
Politics Aristotle Translated by Benjamin Jowett Batoche Books Kitchener 1999 Contents BOOK ONE .............................................................................. 3 BOOK TWO ........................................................................... 22 BOOK THREE ....................................................................... 51 BOOK FOUR ......................................................................... 80 BOOK FIVE ......................................................................... 108 BOOK SIX ........................................................................... 140 BOOK SEVEN ..................................................................... 152 BOOK EIGHT ...................................................................... 180 BOOK ONE Part I Every state is a community of some kind, and every community is es- tablished with a view to some good; for mankind always act in order to obtain that which they think good. But, if all communities aim at some good, the state or political community, which is the highest of all, and which embraces all the rest, aims at good in a greater degree than any other, and at the highest good. Some people think that the qualifications of a statesman, king, house- holder, and master are the same, and that they differ, not in kind, but only in the number of their subjects. For example, the ruler over a few is called a master; over more, the manager of a household; over a still larger number, a statesman or king, as if there were no difference be- tween a great household and a small state. The distinction which is made between the king and the statesman is as follows: When the government is personal, the ruler is a king; when, according to the rules of the politi- cal science, the citizens rule and are ruled in turn, then he is called a statesman. But all this is a mistake; for governments differ in kind, as will be evident to any one who considers the matter according to the method which has hitherto guided us. -
Work and Family
Work and Family VOLUME 21 NUMBER 2 FALL 2011 3 Work and Family: Introducing the Issue 15 Changing Families, Changing Workplaces 37 Policies to Assist Parents with Young Children 69 Families with School-Age Children 91 Children with Health Issues 117 Families and Elder Care in the Twenty-First Century 141 Workplace Flexibility: From Research to Action 163 The Role of the Government in Work-Family Conflict 191 International Perspectives on Work-Family Policies: Lessons from the World’s Most Competitive Economies A COLLABORATION OF THE WOODROW WILSON SCHOOL OF PUBLIC AND INTERNATIONAL AFFAIRS AT PRINCETON UNIVERSITY AND THE BROOKINGS INSTITUTION The Future of Children seeks to translate high-level research into information that is useful to policy makers, practitioners, and the media. The Future of Children is a collaboration of the Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Affairs at Princeton University and the Brookings Institution. Senior Editorial Staff Journal Staff Sara McLanahan Kris McDonald Editor-in-Chief Associate Editor Princeton University Princeton University Director, Center for Research on Child Wellbeing, and William S. Tod Lauren Moore Professor of Sociology and Public Affairs Project Manager Princeton University Ron Haskins Senior Editor Brenda Szittya Brookings Institution Managing Editor Senior Fellow and Co-Director, Center on Princeton University Children and Families Martha Gottron Christina Paxson Managing Editor Senior Editor Princeton University Princeton University Lisa Markman-Pithers Dean, Woodrow Wilson -
On Perfect Friendship: an Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship
Colby College Digital Commons @ Colby Honors Theses Student Research 2010 On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship Kristen Psaty Colby College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Other Philosophy Commons Colby College theses are protected by copyright. They may be viewed or downloaded from this site for the purposes of research and scholarship. Reproduction or distribution for commercial purposes is prohibited without written permission of the author. Recommended Citation Psaty, Kristen, "On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship" (2010). Honors Theses. Paper 589. https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses/589 This Honors Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Research at Digital Commons @ Colby. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Colby. ON PERFECT FRIENDSHIP: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship By Kristen Psaty Honors Thesis Philosophy Department © 2010 1 For Megan The one who brings out the best in me. To Kyle My other self . & to the ∆ΠΠ 2 “This has always been a man's world, and none of the reasons that have been offered in explanation have seemed adequate.” -Simone de Beauvoir Special Thanks to Lydia Moland, Valerie Dionne, Holly Moore and Thanks also to readers Amy Holmen and Elise Breed. 3 Table of Contents INTRODUCTION ………………………………………………. 6 CHAPTER I. ……………………………………………………. 13 An Introduction to Aristotle on Friendship CHAPTER II. -
Liberalism, Community, and the Context of Choice
Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 2-8-1995 Liberalism, Community, and the Context of Choice Marta R. Colburn Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Political Science Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Colburn, Marta R., "Liberalism, Community, and the Context of Choice" (1995). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 4888. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.6764 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. THESIS APPROVAL The abstract and thesis of Marta R. Colburn for the Master of Science in Political Science were presented February 8th, 1995, and accepted by the thesis committee and the department. COMMITTEE APPROVALS : Craig cc;irr, Chair John Damis Sorca O'Connor Representative of the Office of Graduate Studies DEPARTMENT APPROVAL: Department of Political Science ************************************************************ ACCEPTED FOR PORTLAND STATE UNIVERSITY BY THE LIBRARY by on& /?f'&xa1{ /99~ ABSTRACT An abstract of the thesis of Marta R. Colburn for the Master of Science in Political Science presented February 8, 1995, and accepted by the thesis committee and the department. Title: Liberalism, Community, and the Context of Choice Issues of community have become an important focus in the field of political theory in North America. Critics of liberalism, the dominant American theoretical tradition, have charged that liberal theorists have misconceived the nature of community at the ontological and societal level. -
Hasidic Public Schools in Kiryas Joel
The Draw and Drawbacks of Religious Enclaves in a Constitutional Democracy: Hasidic Public Schools in Kiryas Joel JUDITH LYNN FAILER' INTRODUCTION Recent work in political and constitutional studies has celebrated the salutary effects of robust civil societies for democracies.' Robert Putnam, for example, has described how Italian communities with stronger civic traditions have political leaders who are less "elitist" and are "more enthusiastic supporters of political equality" while their citizens' political involvement is characterized by "greater social trust and greater confidence in the law-abidingness of their fellow citizens than... citizens in the least civic regions."' William Galston makes a case for how civic organizations in civil society can foster the development of liberal virtues Jean L. Cohen and Andrew Arato have argued that civil society is "the primary locus for the potential expansion of democracy under 'really existing' liberal-democratic regimes." 4 * Assistant Professor of Political Science and American Studies, Indiana University-Bloomington. Prepared for presentation at a symposium on Civil Society, Indiana University School of Law, March 29, 1996. Thank you to Fred Aman and Steve Conrad for their generous invitation. I am grateful to Jane Mansbridge for helping me think through the ways by which Kiryas Joel poses particular challenges in democratic theory as an enclave group. Thank you also to Mark Brandon, Dana Chabot, David Orentlicher, and Jean Robinson for helpful conversations in preparation of this article, and to Jeffrey Isaac and Sanford Levinson for their suggestions for revisions. 1. For the purposes of this paper, Iam following John Gray's definition of "civil society" as "that sphere of autonomous institutions, protected by a rule of law, within which individuals and communities possessing divergent values and beliefs may coexist in peace." JOHN GRAY, POST LIBERALISM: STUDIES IN POLITICAL THOUGHT 157 (1993). -
Continuity and Discontinuity. an Epistemological Inquiry Based on the Use of Categories in History of Science*
ORGANON 41:2009 Raffaele Pisano (Nantes, France) - Ilaria Gaudiello (Paris, France) CONTINUITY AND DISCONTINUITY. AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL INQUIRY BASED ON THE USE OF CATEGORIES IN HISTORY OF SCIENCE* 1. Introduction Generally, historical inquiry proceeds according to different levels of knowledge, both scientific and humanist, and through particular methods and instruments of research, for example in the history of foundations, in the scientific-cultural attitude of a particular historical period rather than in the historical-social consequences in the history of technologies. In the last century research about the foundations of science seems to have been forwarded increasingly by programs of research more than through the implementation of a basic theory. Several competitive research programs have covered the period from the turn of the 19lh century to and throughout the 20th century. In the following we list some notes on Mach, Koyre and Kuhn to introduce the importance of the use of categories. Ernst Waldfried Josef Wenzel Mach (1838-1916) generated a radically new vision of foundations of physics'. This new vision implied a deep criticism2 toward Newton mechanics, particularly with regard to the metaphysical concepts of absolute space and time. Moreover, the concept of cause-force ultimately substituted the concept of work as the fundamental concept exploited by theoretical physics as well as the human mind to the extent it engages in related theorizing activity. Therefore, although mechanics is traditionally considered to be the basic theory in theoretical physics, thermodynamics should rather play this pivotal role. The contribution supplied by Mach can thus be considered especially relevant for the history of scientific thought. -
Craft As a Larger Pursuit of Human Happiness
CRAFT AS A LARGER PURSUIT OF HUMAN HAPPINESS Eva Perez de Vega May 2012 CRAFT AS A LARGER PURSUIT OF HUMAN HAPPINESS ABSTRACT p. 1 ARISTOTELIAN CONCEPTION OF HAPPINESS: CRAFT AND PRUDENCE p. 2 1.1 Happiness and human function 1.2 Aristotle’s concept of craft and prudence TOWARDS AN INTEGRATED VIEW OF CRAFT AND PRUDENCE p. 9 2.1 Shortcomings of Aristotle’s perspective 2.2 Craft, prudence and affordance CRAFT AND NECESSITY p. 15 3.1 Craft prior to use: invention 3.2 Craft after use: form follows function 3.3 Use embedded in craft: affordance CONCLUSION p. 21 4.1 Structure of argument 4.2 Appropriations and assumptions BIBLIOGRAPHY & ILLUSTRATIONS p. 23 Eva Perez de Vega ABSTRACT This paper aims to explore the concept of craft as it relates to the larger pursuit of human happiness. Starting with Aristotle’s conception of craft and prudence developed in the Nichomachian Ethics, we will see how they are critical to his overall view of human happiness, but also problematic when viewed in isolation. For Aristotle, craft is concerned solely with the thoughts and processes that go into making (production) while prudence deals with the thoughts and processes that go into determining its best use (activity). By providing specific examples and supported by the notion of affordance, the aim of this paper is to show that craft already embeds in its very making multiple possibilities of use, and thus encompasses a sense of prudence. The arguments presented also aim to show that Aristotle’s concept of craft and prudence recognize that human creative activity is indispensible towards achieving happiness.