A Critical Overview of Plato's Epistemology in Dialectic of Meno

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Critical Overview of Plato's Epistemology in Dialectic of Meno ORIGINAL ARTICLE European Journal of Theology and Philosophy www.ej-theology.org A Critical Overview of Plato’s Epistemology in Dialectic of Meno Ven. Wadigala Samitharathana ABSTRACT Plato's epistemology precisely seems that a prospective analysis of human knowledge and virtue. The dialectic of Meno often has made up several Published Online: February 20, 2021 attempts to arrive at rather intellectual and ambiguous complexes. It worked ISSN: 2736-5514 on the following critical issues over the dialogue. Mainly, the methodology of DOI: 10.24018/ejtheology.2021.1.1.8 recollection and forms, immortality of the soul, concepts of real and reason have crucially discussed there. In particular, the above theoretical Ven. Wadigala Samitharathana approaches have fundamentally based on virtue and knowledge. Otherwise, Department of Philosophy a few technical terminologies have been utilised continuously in Faculty of Arts University of Peradeniya, the Meno like, 'epistêmê,' 'doxa.' The Meno's Paradoxa could tremendously Sri Lanka stimulate subjective morphemes. Meno's epistemology's succinct scope is that (e-mail: samitharathana23@ gmail.com) the contrasted conversation is constructed between metaphysical matters and facts of the knowledge, belief, or real opinion and other inevitable, formative elements during the acquisition of sensual perception. Keywords: belief, epistemology, knowledge, meno, virtue that it is the valid, reliable opinion and can therefore be I. INTRODUCTION acquired only by divine inspiration (Stone 2010, 1). Thus, the Here it would be hopeful to discuss in contrast Meno's eristic dilemma circumvented a few intellectual epistemology of Plato's Meno. This brief study ought to be aspects and attempted to consist of some epistemological revealed the contextual critique just towards only Meno issues. Insofar it looks forward to analysing how the Meno depicts Phaedo and Theaetetus, which were the most could be in progress theory of knowledge. significant dilemmas of Plato. Primarily, in the Meno and Phaedo, Plato has engaged with the theory of recollection, the II. DISCUSSION theory of forms, the immortality of the soul, and the concepts A. What is Epistêmê or Epistemology? "true opinion/judgement" and "an explanation of the reason At the whole dialogue of Meno, Plato exclusively used the why" to illustrate a complete epistemological system (Sheng technical terminology of ‘epistêmê.' However; it was always 2015, 1). Plato's Epistemology seems constructed on with some another morpheme called 'doxa’ (Moline 1981, something he interprets epistêmê, often translated 191).2 So this has conventionally been recognised and 1 'knowledge’ (Matthews 1972, 13). In the Meno, there are interpreted as ‘Meno’s Paradoxa’ by the post-commentators making some coherent differences between knowledge and (Suzuki 2011, 2). In the Meno, the proper answer would seem belief. It does mind it has indeed appeared as a central obvious: episteme or epistemology is the knowledge utilising interrogative fact here. Socrates and Meno arrive at two virtue that can teach. However, the platonic dialogues link up different hypotheses: in the first part of the dialogue, that with the theory that there are unchanging and eternal forms, virtue is knowledge and can therefore teach; in the second, which are the objects of knowledge, during the many DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24018/ejtheology.2021.1.1.8 Vol 1 | Issue 1 | February 2021 4 ORIGINAL ARTICLE European Journal of Theology and Philosophy www.ej-theology.org controversial perceptible particulars. It might also contrast recollection theory, which figures large in the Meno and with belief. Then the epistemology has been in a contrasted Phaedo, is near contributed to Plato to above intra- conversation between knowledge and belief. Herein taking a distinction. It is between necessary and contingent truths and few passages from the Meno: the intra-distinction between knowledge and belief he aligned 1) More valuable than Doxa (Meno 97d, Republic 476e) with it (Fine ([2009]-2010, 4).8 It did not pursue in later 2) Harder to achieve than Doxa (Meno 85c-d) (Moss 2020: dialogues, except the present acquisition of knowledge that 1) Plato considers always. Particular forms or images of knowledge is indeed By the above facts, it seems, of course, some more striking typically distinguishable from the belief by reference to their similarities on epistêmê. It does mind it is not a surprise to different objects and material facts. Then knowledge deems knowing that episteme is knowledge. The contemporary as necessarily true. In terms of ontological differences epistemologists tend to look at Plato as the founder of the between forms and particulars, timeless truths and shifting discipline. Moreover, even as the author of one of the contingencies, and corresponding different states of mind, but dominant knowledge theories, as justified true belief also in terms of a systematic body of knowledge, (Armstrong 1973, 137).3 Plato says about epistêmê may be hierarchically organised (Matthews 1972, 16-17), (Cornford rather difficult to reconcile with the knowledge as it is a 1935, 154-162).9 There seems no room left for Meno’s slave- variant topographical context. For some examples: boy coming to know what he now rightly believes nor much 1) Requires reasoning out of the cause or explanation (aitias room for being reminded of equality by seeing equal, or logismos, Meno 98a) unequal, sticks. Plato is as ruthless with his argument as with 2) It is more than a well-grounded true belief (Meno 85c-d) his prisoners. According to Meno’s dialogues, belief is at (Burnyeat 2015, 23)4 most the beginning of a long trek, which will take one through 3) Cannot be transmitted by testimony (Theaetetus 201c, all known and foreseeable mathematics towards the Meno passim, Rep. 518b-c) (Moss 2020, 2) philosophical goal and knowledge must be of what timeless These are the several clues which do indicate the and changeless, and must also have a particular starting point 10 epistemological configures in Plato’s Meno unavoidably. (Majeed 2014, 1), (Matthews 1972, 16-17). Now it has been a critical reason to concerning epistêmê in together with knowledge and belief. C. The judgment of Virtue | Virtue as Knowledge? In particular, Plato has acutely concerned with at least a Here the conversation of virtue would seem like the most few of the following philosophical approaches toward prominent and controversial argumentation fact undoubtedly. 5 epistêmê or epistemology in Meno (Matthews 1972). The reason for such a dilemma may probably be the necessity 1) How could it be different between knowledge and belief? of knowing and verifying what virtue is. Based on the Meno, 2) Are our knowledge and belief incompatible? first at foremost, it should precisely be known that (1) what 3) Is knowledge by acquaintance, or is the object of virtue is and (2) what teaching is (Stone 2010, 3). Socrates knowledge necessarily complex? observes that the question 'Is virtue teachable?' cannot be 4) If knowledge is concerned with the case, can a belief be answered until one knows what one means by virtue. In concerned with what is not the case? getting tried to answer the question, Meno a priori says a 5) How do we arrive at knowledge as distinct from belief? different approach to every individual or separate groups of people-men, women, young, old, and so far. The Meno B. The Key Contradictions between Knowledge and remarks that justice and temperance for all humankind are Belief necessary to indicate that at least all truth must be based on The Meno mainly shows that Plato has convinced a couple and comprehend the 'quiet' moral virtues (Bluck 1961, 4-5)11- of issues on this matter. (1) Getting tried to take a position on a hint as to the nature of virtue which Meno should have behalf of belief in between perfect knowledge and blank followed up. ignorance or sensory illusion (2) Getting tried to draw up Meno’s eristic dilemma may divide into the following criteria to differentiate between knowledge and true belief synthetic overview. It does mind help make comprehension (Matthews 1972, 14-15). Here the knowledge and belief of Meno’s epistemology in many perspective ways (Bluck should be identified by themselves in verifying the multiple 1961).12 branches occupied. It is possible to perceive and have beliefs 1) The question 'Is virtue teachable?' raises the foremost about a pair of sticks, whereas although supported to question 'What is virtue?' Then several attempts are made 'recollection' by particulars, it is occurring the mind alone that to define virtue. it already knows equality and the equality there may be 2) The question 'How can you look for something you do between sticks, gradually with other forms and forms-in- not know, or organise it if you find it out? objects.6 3) Meno again asks, 'Is virtue teachable?' Socrates Knowledge of forms recollected and unlike belief.7 That undertakes to investigate the question utilising links the ability to give an account of what is known. The hypothesis, a method used by geometricians: Let us DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24018/ejtheology.2021.1.1.8 Vol 1 | Issue 1 | February 2021 5 ORIGINAL ARTICLE European Journal of Theology and Philosophy www.ej-theology.org suppose that virtue is a kind of knowledge. If it is, it will interpreted to be a limiting condition for 'virtue is teachable': be teachable; otherwise, it will not. However, virtue is if the condition is satisfied, virtue will be teachable, but if it knowledge. Therefore virtue is teachable. is not, virtue will not be teachable (Bluck 1961, 17-18). 4) Socrates suggests that there is an objection to this According to Meno’s dialectic context, it has precisely conclusion. If a thing is teachable, there ought to be affiliated with the assumption of knowledge, which is the teachers of it.
Recommended publications
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Revised New Summary of Philebus
    New Summary of Philebus REVISED 1. (11) Philebus maintains that pleasure, enjoyment, rejoicing, and their kind, are the best things for all animals, while Socrates maintains, for those able to partake of them, wisdom, mind, memory, and their kind, are the best. Each side must agree that it is a condition and disposition of soul that produces happiness. Stipulation: if some other life superior to both is found, then the victor will be he whose champion is closer to this hypothetical best life. a. (12c) Problem: are pleasure and likewise knowledge, both like and unlike themselves, because they each have various aspects and shapes? And are some of these shapes bad and some good? b. (14c) We must investigate this question with the aid of the principle that the one is many and the many are one. This is obvious and common property when applied to things that come to be and perish, but when applied to things like man, ox, beauty, and good, there are perplexities. i. (15b) The perplexities (there is unclarity about exactly what these three questions are): 1. Do such unities exist? 2. How do they, while remaining themselves, enter the domain of becoming? 3. How are they both one and many? ii. (15d) The identification of the one with the many arises everwhere from the nature of discourse itself—it entrances the young. iii. (16c) A gift of the gods: all things contain limit and the unlimited. We must not pass from the one to the infinite too quickly or slowly, but instead note all the intermediate numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE and the IMPORTANCE of VIRTUE in the CONTEXT of the POLITICS and the NICOMACHEAN ETHICS and ITS RELATION to TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University
    Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses 2010 ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Anthony, Kyle Brandon, "ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY" (2010). Honors Theses. 21. https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses/21 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses at Bucknell Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Bucknell Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter 1 What does it mean to live a good life? 7 The virtuous life 8 Ethical virtue 13 Bravery as an ethical virtue 20 Justice 22 Chapter 2 The Politics and the ideal polis 28 Development of a polis 29 Features of an ideal polis 32 What does it mean to be a citizen of a polis? 40 Aristotle’s views on education 42 Social groups in a polis who are not recognized as citizens 45 Non-ideal political systems 51 Chapter 3 Connections between the Politics and the Ethics 57 Chapter 4 Difficulties in applying Aristotle’s theories to a modern setting 68 Conclusion Where do we go from here? 87 Bibliography 89 iv Acknowledgements First off, I have to thank God, as He helped me endure this project and gave me the courage to press on when I became frustrated, angry, and ready to quit.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata
    Plato’s Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata At Meno 86e2–4 Socrates proposes to Meno that they should consider the question whether virtue is teachable on a hypothesis. Partly because its concrete procedure is illustrated by a baffling geometrical example, there has still been wide disagreement among scholars as to how he actually carries out this hypothetical inquiry into virtue. The basic structure of the argument at 87b2–89a5 appears very simple: Socrates converts the original question whether virtue is teachable to the question whether it is knowledge, and then examines the latter on the basis of his agreement with Meno that virtue is good. Apart however from that agreement being, as it is explicitly called, a ‘hypothesis’, opinion is divided on what other hypothesis Socrates posited. Some think of it as the conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable’ or as ‘knowledge is teachable’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Wolfsdorf 2008, 44–6 and 58–60),1 and others as the bi-conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable, but if not, not’ or as ‘knowledge alone is teachable’ (Grgić 1999, 34–6; Weiss 2001, 131; Zyskind and Sternfeld 1976, 132). 2 But most scholars, in contrast, identify it with the simple proposition ‘virtue is knowledge’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Benson 2003, 107–25; Bluck 1961, 17–19 and 85–91; Bostock 1986, 165–6; Canto-Sperber 1991, 98–102; Cherniss 1947, 140; Hackforth 1955, 140–1; Kahn 1996, 310; Robinson 1953, 116–18; Rose 1970, 3–7; Sayre 1969, 29 n. 40; Scott 2006, 137–40 and 221–4; Sharples 1985, 167).3 It is also suggested that Socrates’ new philosophical tool does not involve any process of positing a hypothesis but only aims to establish the equivalence between teachability and knowledge (Ebrey 2013, 76 and 83–4).
    [Show full text]
  • Gregory Vlastos
    Gregory Vlastos: A Preliminary Inventory of His Papers at the Harry Ransom Center Descriptive Summary Creator: Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Title: Gregory Vlastos Papers Dates: circa 1930s-1991 Extent: 100 document boxes (42.00 linear feet) Abstract: The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos, a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities. Call Number: Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Language: English, with Ancient Greek, French, German, Italian, Latin, Modern Greek, and Spanish Access: Open for research Administrative Information Acquisition: Gifts, 1993-2010 (G9070, G9134, G9163, G9225, G9252, G9628, G9979, G9982, G10214, G10288, G11877, 10-03-014-G) Processed by: Hope Rider, 2006; updated by Joan Sibley, 2016 Repository: The University of Texas at Austin, Harry Ransom Center Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Scope and Contents The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos (1907-1991), a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities, especially Cornell, Princeton, and The University of California at Berkeley. The papers are arranged in six series: I. Correspondence and Offprint Files, II. Study, Lecture, and Teaching Files, III. Works, IV. Works by Others, V. Miscellaneous, and VI. Offprints Removed from Manuscripts. The Correspondence and Offprint Files (35 boxes) in Series I. represent Vlastos' extensive correspondence with other philosophers, classicists, former students, academics, and others. The files are arranged alphabetically by correspondent name, and generally include not only letters received, but copies of Vlastos' responses.
    [Show full text]
  • Justice As a Virtue
    Justice as a Virtue In sub-subunit 1.4.2, it is made clear that for Aristotle a crucial precondition of virtue is that actions must be intentional. For Aristotle, voluntary action—or intention—is required if praise or blame is to be appropriate. Praise and blame are important in that they testify to that which is virtuous in the polis, which substantiates the virtues among the citizenry and subsequent generations through habituation. Through praise and blame, we come to witness that to which we should aspire and that from which we should abstain, which in turn contributes to the kind of polis that makes for or perpetuates the right kind of habituation for both our peers and for the next generation. Praise and blame cannot apply to acts that are involuntary, and one criterion that can establish the involuntary character of an act is if it were undertaken in ignorance for which the agent is not responsible. However, as shown in sub-subunit 1.4.2, Aristotle sets the bar high for an act to be characterized as involuntary both on the basis of being associated with force or ignorance. Ample room is left available for acts to be understood as voluntary and hence potentially worthy of praise or blame. Aristotle’s concern with establishing the conditions necessary for praise and blame stand in sharp contrast to Plato, who takes the position that all wrongdoing is involuntary because it is necessarily done in ignorance. For Plato, we all want to do what is good, and whenever we do something, we do it for the sake of the good even if this is in fact not the case.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Phaedo As a Pedagogical Drama
    Ancient Philosophy 33 (2013) ©Mathesis Publications 333 Plato’s Phaedo as a Pedagogical Drama Sarah Jansen The Phaedo has long been recognized as dramatic in nature (see, e.g., Jowett 1892, 193). Indeed, the dialogue’s dramatic portrayal of a Herculean Socrates attacking the heads of a hydra naturally invites this assessment (89c). At the out- set of the dialogue Socrates and the fourteen named companions are juxtaposed with Theseus and the fourteen Athenian youth, on their way to defeat the Mino- taur (58a-c).1 Also, Socrates’ death scene is particularly dramatic. Fifteen com- panions, the exact number of a tragic chorus, surround the dying Socrates and lament (117c-d).2 Reflection on this scene has prompted scholars to speculate that it is intended to ‘lend moving force’ to the tragic perspective and to ‘rouse’ readers’ emotions (see Halliwell 1984, 57-58 and Crotty 2009, 87, respectively). Despite these scholarly observations and compelling evidence that the dia- logues were treated as dramatic performance literature in antiquity (see Charal- abopoulos 2012), a number of key questions have yet to be satisfactorily and systematically answered: What is drama?; What is the Phaedo a drama about?; What is the function, if any, of the dramatic elements of the Phaedo? I undertake to answer these questions. I conclude with some thoughts about Plato’s purpose in writing dramatic dialogues and Plato’s attitude toward poetry. One of my aims throughout will be to demonstrate how a proper understanding of the literary dimension of the Phaedo sheds light on the philosophical content of the dialogue.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantic Development of Virtue
    Hugvísindasvið The semantic development of virtue Philosophical comparison Ritgerð til B.A.–prófs í ensku Arnhildur G. Guðmundsdóttir Maí 2014 University of Iceland School of Humanities Department of English The semantic development of virtue Philosophical comparison B.A. Essay Arnhildur G. Guðmundsdóttir Kt.: 221069-3829 Supervisor: Þórhallur Eyþórsson May 2014 Abstract The concept of virtue is everywhere to be found in societies, from the ancient scriptures of yoga philosophy to Plato and Socrates, to modern day scrutiny. It has caused religious traditions, anthropologists and philosophers to have carefully contemplated what the term entails, its different aspects and how to interpret the virtues. The aim of this thesis is to illustrate and support the claim that the virtues are a part of the innate nature of human beings, and the key to happiness and prosperity in life. It examines the concept of virtue and its semantic development by studying and comparing the virtues of yoga philosophy, the yamas, to the ancient Greek philosophers, especially Socrates’s hypothesis of virtue being knowledge, and contemporary moral philosophy. History reveals that the semantic development of the concept of virtue remains relatively unchanged. It is therefore a reason to believe that the virtues are a subject to continual study and interpretation of good qualities in various societies because they are an internal natural part of human beings. They appear to be dormant until systematically awakened through practice where the aim is prosperity and lasting happiness in life. Only through an inner journey of self-scrutiny and dedication, which will lead to sharp objectivity and the willpower to practice the virtues, will they be activated and rendered a part of a person’s prosperous life and lasting happiness.
    [Show full text]
  • On Perfect Friendship: an Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship
    Colby College Digital Commons @ Colby Honors Theses Student Research 2010 On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship Kristen Psaty Colby College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Other Philosophy Commons Colby College theses are protected by copyright. They may be viewed or downloaded from this site for the purposes of research and scholarship. Reproduction or distribution for commercial purposes is prohibited without written permission of the author. Recommended Citation Psaty, Kristen, "On Perfect Friendship: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship" (2010). Honors Theses. Paper 589. https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/honorstheses/589 This Honors Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Research at Digital Commons @ Colby. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Colby. ON PERFECT FRIENDSHIP: An Outline and a Guide to Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship By Kristen Psaty Honors Thesis Philosophy Department © 2010 1 For Megan The one who brings out the best in me. To Kyle My other self . & to the ∆ΠΠ 2 “This has always been a man's world, and none of the reasons that have been offered in explanation have seemed adequate.” -Simone de Beauvoir Special Thanks to Lydia Moland, Valerie Dionne, Holly Moore and Thanks also to readers Amy Holmen and Elise Breed. 3 Table of Contents INTRODUCTION ………………………………………………. 6 CHAPTER I. ……………………………………………………. 13 An Introduction to Aristotle on Friendship CHAPTER II.
    [Show full text]
  • What's Justice Got to Do With
    International Journal of Philosophy and Theology December 2014, Vol. 2, No. 4, pp. 45-59 ISSN: 2333-5750 (Print), 2333-5769 (Online) Copyright © The Author(s). 2014. All Rights Reserved. Published by American Research Institute for Policy Development DOI: 10.15640/ijpt.v2n4a3 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.15640/ijpt.v2n4a3 What’s Justice got to do with it? Douglas Langston1 Abstract Contrary to the common view that the four cardinal virtues are interconnected such that anyone possessing one must possess the others, I argue that there is an asymmetry betweenjustice and theother three. While temperance, fortitude, and prudence are required for justice, justice is not requiredfor any of the other three. This asymmetry occurs not only because justice is a motivational virtue while the other three are structural (or both structural and motivational) but also because justice must be seen in terms of right actions rather than good actions. While it is the case that prudence, temperance, and courage make an agent a good agent, one can be just without being good. Keywords: Justice; Cardinal Virtues; Structural Virtues; Motivational Virtues; Unity of the Virtues; Virtue Ethics Thomas Aquinas, among others, held that there are four cardinal virtues: prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance. They are cardinal in the sense that the other virtues hang on them. Since ‘cardo’ in Latin translates as ‘hinge’, they are aptly named because Aquinas believes that the other virtues hinge on the four.1 That is to say, in order to possess any of the other moral virtues, one needs aspects of the four cardinal virtues.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Oklahoma Graduate College
    UNIVERSITY OF OKLAHOMA GRADUATE COLLEGE SOCRATIC DEFINITION IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES: CONDITIONS ON AN ADEQUATE ANSWER TO “WHAT IS F-NESS?” A Dissertation SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE FACULTY in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By ELLIOT C. WELCH Norman, Oklahoma 2007 UMI Number: 3275085 UMI Microform 3275085 Copyright 2007 by ProQuest Information and Learning Company. All rights reserved. This microform edition is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest Information and Learning Company 300 North Zeeb Road P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, MI 48106-1346 SOCRATIC DEFINITION IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES: CONDITIONS ON AN ADEQUATE ANSWER TO “WHAT IS F-NESS?” A DISSERTATION APPROVED FOR THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY ____________________________ Hugh H. Benson ____________________________ Monte Cook ____________________________ Reinaldo Elugardo ____________________________ Ellen Greene ____________________________ James Hawthorne © Copyright by ELLIOT C. WELCH 2007 All Rights Reserved. CONTENTS ABSTRACT. viii CHAPTER I. Introduction. .1 A. Socratic A.1. Stylometry A.2. Aristotle’s Testimony B. Definition B.1. Formal and Material Conditions C. In Plato’s Dialogues C.1. The Textual Objection C.2. The Cross-Dialogue Objection C.2.a. F-ness C.2.b. What is F-ness? C.2.c. Context D. Structure of the Dissertation II. An Overview of Socratic Definition. 34 A. Definitional Conditions to Which Socrates Is Committed A.1. The Unity Condition (UC) A.2. The Extensional Equivalence Condition (EE) A.3. The Property Sameness Condition (PS) A.4. The Non-difference Condition (ND) A.4.a. Relationship among UC, EE, PS A.4.b.
    [Show full text]
  • Pleasure As the Standard of Virtue in Hume's Moral Philosophy
    Running:left: PACIFIC PLEASURE PHILOSOPHICAL AS THE STANDARD QUARTERLY OF VIRTUE IN HUME’S PLEASURE AS THE STANDARD OF VIRTUE IN HUME’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY1 by JULIA DRIVER Abstract: David Hume provides several accounts of moral virtue, all of which tie virtue to the experience of pleasure in the spectator. Hume believed that the appropriate pleasure for determinations of virtue was pleasure corrected by “the general point of view.” I argue that common ways of spelling this out leave the account open to the charge that it cannot account adequately for mistaken judgments of virtue. I argue that we need to see Hume as offering both a metaphysics and an epistemology of virtue, and that Hume’s account of virtue can adequately account for mistakes if he is understood as offering a definition of virtue tied to pleasure, but pleasure understood externally. But in many orders of beauty, particularly those of the finer arts, it is requisite to employ much reasoning, in order to feel the proper sentiment; and a false relish may frequently be corrected by argument and reflection. There are just grounds to conclude, that moral beauty partakes much of this latter species, and demands the assistance of our intellectual faculties, in order to give it a suitable influence on the human mind (EPM, 173).2 David Hume provides several distinct definitions of moral virtue: (V1) “. whatever mental action or quality gives to a spectator the pleasing sentiment of approbation” (EPM, 289). And, (V2) “. virtue . is a quality of the mind agreeable to or approved of by every one, who considers or con- templates it” (EPM, 261n) Even more simply, (V3) “.
    [Show full text]