The 0.999…=1 Fallacy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The 0.999…=1 Fallacy The 0.999…=1 fallacy. This fallacy has its origins in Euler’s wrong ideas. The only support comes from Euler’s definition of infinite sum, which is both illogical and spurious. Ignorant academics have unfortunately subscribed to Euler’s wrong ideas and a sewer load of theory has arisen therefrom. But what can one expect from a man who believed that = 0 ? After the advent of Georg Cantor’s poisonous ideas on set theory and non-existent real numbers, things grew progressively worse. A proof for simpletons: Consider that if ≠ 0.333 … , then 0.999 … ≠ 1. The support for the = 0.333 … equality comes from ignorance. However, for this short proof I will assume that it is correct. After I debunk the equality, I will proceed to show that non-terminating decimals are a fallacy that is based on incorrect logic (more like the lack of it). Proof: We know that: 3 1 1 = () = 1 − 10 3 10 Now followers of Euler (academic morons) like to think that 3 1 = 10 3 In which case, the direct implication is that (∞) = , but as we already know, (∞) does not exist as a well-defined concept. If indeed (∞) were possible, then the graph of () = 1 − would have no asymptote. In fact, the concept of limit in this respect, would also not exist. Therefore, the equality = 0.333 … is ill-formed and false. Radix representation: Representing numbers in radix systems is just a way of finding another equivalent fraction in that radix system. For example: to represent in base 10, we write 0.25 which means + = = . It is impossible to find an equivalent fraction for in base 10, because 3 is not one of the prime factors of 10. To argue ignorantly that + + + ⋯ = , is claiming that this statement regarding prime factors is FALSE. + + + ⋯ is not an equivalent fraction because the ellipsis is meaningless nonsense. Infinity is an ill-formed concept that has no place in rational thought and is not required in any mathematics. Debunking the popular notion that = . … because of long division. I begin this proof by stating that the belief that = 0.333 … has absolutely nothing to do with long division. I suppose that it would be helpful to see why long division works in the first place. Almost all mathematics professors have no idea why it works. So they should pay careful attention to this proof. The long division algorithm has its origins in Euclid’s Algorithm. Assume that and are two integers greater than 0. Furthermore, let denote the quotient and the remainder (if any). For long division to work, we must have: = ( × )10 + ( × )10 + ( × )10 + ⋯ + ( × )10 + ( × ) + So, = × … + = + where 0 ≤ < This last statement is exactly Euclid’s Algorithm. So how do we apply it to ? 1 = (3 × 0) + 1 Now, where in the previous statement do you see anything resembling that process mathematicians use to find 0.333 … , that is, the so-called long division algorithm? Nowhere! You might be tempted to argue as follows: = × + 1 = × 3 + = × 3 + = × 3 + where the quotient is given in red, the divisor in green, the remainder in light brown and the dividend in blue. Whence, 1 = + + + . Observe that = 3, and is always greater than . Furthermore, no stopping condition exists because is never equal to 0. The reason for this, is that long division has nothing to do with the process ignorant academics refer to in arriving at the fallacy = 0.333 … The process used to arrive at the ill-formed conclusion that = 0.333 … is as follows: 1 1 10 10 1 = × = × 3 3 10 3 10 1 1 1 = 3 + × 3 3 10 1 1 1 1 = 3 × + × 3 10 3 10 1 1 1 1 10 = 3 × + × × 3 10 3 10 10 1 1 10 1 1 = 3 × + × × 3 10 3 10 10 1 1 10 1 = 3 × + × 3 10 3 10 1 1 1 1 = 3 × + 3 + × 3 10 3 10 1 1 1 1 1 = 3 × + 3 × + × 3 10 10 3 10 So, we can continue in this fashion or notice that the 3s repeat. Or we can be smart and simply write: = 0.3( ) + × where is an integer greater than or equal to 0. The method just described has ABSOLUTELY NOTHING to do with long division. Yet idiot academics have been claiming this for the last few hundred years. Strange? You decide. Representing magnitudes and numbers: Since is a well-defined number, one ignorantly supposes that it can be represented in any radix system, in particular base 10 as 0.333 … This assertion is false because placing an ellipsis (…) behind the last 3 does not make it valid or meaningful. Infinity does not belong in well-defined concepts. In fact, infinity has no place in mathematics. 1 We can well define 3 as follows in base 10: 1 1 1 0.3(n times) n 3 3 10 [Well defined] Now if one puts any of n 1,2,3,4,5,... into [Well defined] and uses the same common false proof, that is, x0.999... 10 x 9.999... 9 x 9 x 1, then choosing n 7 gives: 1 1 1. x 0.3333333 7 3 10 1 2. 3x 0.9999999 10,000,000 9999999 1 10,000,000 3. 3x 10,000,000 10,000,000 10,000,000 4. 3x 1 1 5. x 3 1 1 0.9999999 3x 1 Observe from step 2 that 10,000,000 because , 1 x so 3 . Now, let's choose n ( is an ill-defined concept) and repeat the process: 1 1 1. x 0.333... 3 10 1 2. 3x 0.999... 10 999... 1 999... 1 10 3. 3x 10 10 10 10 4. 3x 1 1 5. x 3 And once again, even by using the ill-defined concept of infinity, we have the same 1 3x 1 x result, that is, 3 which is what we started out with. Euler incorrectly defined an infinite sum to be: a arn a a S lim lim 0 n1r n 1 r 1 r 1 r Where does Euler go wrong in his definition of infinite sum? a arn a1 a S lim lim lim 0101 n1r n 1 r 1 r n 10 1 r a 1 1 But we know that the difference 1 0.999..., 1 r 10 10 1 1 that is, 1 0.999... 1 0.999... , therefore 1 0.999... 10 10 1 Step 2 reveals Euler's error. In his definition, he simply discards , that is, Euler 10 treats this as zero, but it is not zero! This misconception arises from the fact that 1 lim 0 n . n 10 However, mathematicians don't really understand limits that well. In fact all of them don't know what is a number. What the last expression means is: 1 As n increases without bound, the least value (greatest lower bound) that 10n cannot attain is 0 . 1 This is the correct interpretation of limn 0 . n 10 When one uses well-defined objects, the results are always consistent. Note that step 2 proves 0.999... 1. Yet another proof: 1 1 1 0.3(n times) n Take the limit of both sides of 3 3 10 : 1 1 1 lim lim 0.3(n times) lim n n3 n n 3 10 The previous statement is equivalent to: 1 1 1 lim 0.333... lim n n3 n 3 10 [E] According to Euler's formula for an infinite sum: 3 1 1 n 3 3 3 10 10 0.333... lim lim 2 ... n n9 n 10 10 10 10 1 1 1 0.333... lim lim n n3 n 3 10 Putting this in [E]: 1 1 1 1 1 1 lim lim lim n lim n n3 n 3 n 3 10 n 3 10 [CR] 1 1 3 3 1 It can be seen that discarding the portion of 3 , that cannot be measured exactly in 1 1 lim n base 10, that is, n 3 10 , would have prevented us from reaching the correct conclusion of the RHS of [CR]. 1 1 lim n 0 Simply replacing n 3 10 with is therefore incorrect, that is, Euler's definition of infinite sum is flawed. A lesson on fractions. After several discussions with academics on Space time and the Universe forum: What does it mean to represent rational numbers in radix systems? I realized that all of them did not understand what it means for a rational number to be represented in a radix system. So I decided to include this section to clarify some of these details. The long division algorithm was used by mathematicians to facilitate the conversion of a rational numbers of the form into some radix form b n n1 b1 b 2 b3 bn an10 a n1 10 ...10 a 1 a 0 ... . 10 102 10 3 10n It was soon discovered that rational numbers whose denominator was not a factor of the radix could not be represented finitely in that radix system, that is, it was not a possible to represent the remainder of , because it cannot be measured by b the finite sum ONLY of the products of integers and reciprocal powers of that radix. 1 A common misconception is that 0.333... 3 1 It is easy to convert to base 10 if we use the following definition: 3 1 1 1 0.3(n times)... n 3 3 10 where n and n 1. The problem occurs when one tries to have n : 1 1 1 0.333..
Recommended publications
  • A Guide to Topology
    i i “topguide” — 2010/12/8 — 17:36 — page i — #1 i i A Guide to Topology i i i i i i “topguide” — 2011/2/15 — 16:42 — page ii — #2 i i c 2009 by The Mathematical Association of America (Incorporated) Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 2009929077 Print Edition ISBN 978-0-88385-346-7 Electronic Edition ISBN 978-0-88385-917-9 Printed in the United States of America Current Printing (last digit): 10987654321 i i i i i i “topguide” — 2010/12/8 — 17:36 — page iii — #3 i i The Dolciani Mathematical Expositions NUMBER FORTY MAA Guides # 4 A Guide to Topology Steven G. Krantz Washington University, St. Louis ® Published and Distributed by The Mathematical Association of America i i i i i i “topguide” — 2010/12/8 — 17:36 — page iv — #4 i i DOLCIANI MATHEMATICAL EXPOSITIONS Committee on Books Paul Zorn, Chair Dolciani Mathematical Expositions Editorial Board Underwood Dudley, Editor Jeremy S. Case Rosalie A. Dance Tevian Dray Patricia B. Humphrey Virginia E. Knight Mark A. Peterson Jonathan Rogness Thomas Q. Sibley Joe Alyn Stickles i i i i i i “topguide” — 2010/12/8 — 17:36 — page v — #5 i i The DOLCIANI MATHEMATICAL EXPOSITIONS series of the Mathematical Association of America was established through a generous gift to the Association from Mary P. Dolciani, Professor of Mathematics at Hunter College of the City Uni- versity of New York. In making the gift, Professor Dolciani, herself an exceptionally talented and successfulexpositor of mathematics, had the purpose of furthering the ideal of excellence in mathematical exposition.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis 11
    AN INTRODUCTION TO NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS ISAAC DAVIS Abstract. In this paper we give an introduction to nonstandard analysis, starting with an ultrapower construction of the hyperreals. We then demon- strate how theorems in standard analysis \transfer over" to nonstandard anal- ysis, and how theorems in standard analysis can be proven using theorems in nonstandard analysis. 1. Introduction For many centuries, early mathematicians and physicists would solve problems by considering infinitesimally small pieces of a shape, or movement along a path by an infinitesimal amount. Archimedes derived the formula for the area of a circle by thinking of a circle as a polygon with infinitely many infinitesimal sides [1]. In particular, the construction of calculus was first motivated by this intuitive notion of infinitesimal change. G.W. Leibniz's derivation of calculus made extensive use of “infinitesimal” numbers, which were both nonzero but small enough to add to any real number without changing it noticeably. Although intuitively clear, infinitesi- mals were ultimately rejected as mathematically unsound, and were replaced with the common -δ method of computing limits and derivatives. However, in 1960 Abraham Robinson developed nonstandard analysis, in which the reals are rigor- ously extended to include infinitesimal numbers and infinite numbers; this new extended field is called the field of hyperreal numbers. The goal was to create a system of analysis that was more intuitively appealing than standard analysis but without losing any of the rigor of standard analysis. In this paper, we will explore the construction and various uses of nonstandard analysis. In section 2 we will introduce the notion of an ultrafilter, which will allow us to do a typical ultrapower construction of the hyperreal numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • A Functional Equation Characterization of Archimedean Ordered Fields
    A FUNCTIONAL EQUATION CHARACTERIZATION OF ARCHIMEDEAN ORDERED FIELDS RALPH HOWARD, VIRGINIA JOHNSON, AND GEORGE F. MCNULTY Abstract. We prove that an ordered field is Archimedean if and only if every continuous additive function from the field to itself is linear over the field. In 1821 Cauchy, [1], observed that any continuous function S on the real line that satisfies S(x + y) = S(x) + S(y) for all reals x and y is just multiplication by a constant. Another way to say this is that S is a linear operator on R, viewing R as a vector space over itself. The constant is evidently S(1). The displayed equation is Cauchy's functional equation and solutions to this equation are called additive. To see that Cauchy's result holds, note that only a small amount of work is needed to verify the following steps: first S(0) = 0, second S(−x) = −S(x), third S(nx) = S(x)n for all integers, and finally that S(r) = S(1)r for every rational number r. But then S and the function x 7! S(1)x are continuous functions that agree on a dense set (the rationals) and therefore are equal. So Cauchy's result follows, in part, from the fact that the rationals are dense in the reals. In 1875 Darboux, in [2], extended Cauchy's result by noting that if an additive function is continuous at just one point, then it is continuous everywhere. Therefore the conclusion of Cauchy's theorem holds under the weaker hypothesis that S is just continuous at a single point.
    [Show full text]
  • First-Order Continuous Induction, and a Logical Study of Real Closed Fields
    c 2019 SAEED SALEHI & MOHAMMADSALEH ZARZA 1 First-Order Continuous Induction, and a Logical Study of Real Closed Fields⋆ Saeed Salehi Research Institute for Fundamental Sciences (RIFS), University of Tabriz, P.O.Box 51666–16471, Bahman 29th Boulevard, Tabriz, IRAN http://saeedsalehi.ir/ [email protected] Mohammadsaleh Zarza Department of Mathematics, University of Tabriz, P.O.Box 51666–16471, Bahman 29th Boulevard, Tabriz, IRAN [email protected] Abstract. Over the last century, the principle of “induction on the continuum” has been studied by differentauthors in differentformats. All of these differentreadings are equivalentto one of the arXiv:1811.00284v2 [math.LO] 11 Apr 2019 three versions that we isolate in this paper. We also formalize those three forms (of “continuous induction”) in first-order logic and prove that two of them are equivalent and sufficiently strong to completely axiomatize the first-order theory of the real closed (ordered) fields. We show that the third weaker form of continuous induction is equivalent with the Archimedean property. We study some equivalent axiomatizations for the theory of real closed fields and propose a first- order scheme of the fundamental theorem of algebra as an alternative axiomatization for this theory (over the theory of ordered fields). Keywords: First-Order Logic; Complete Theories; Axiomatizing the Field of Real Numbers; Continuous Induction; Real Closed Fields. 2010 AMS MSC: 03B25, 03C35, 03C10, 12L05. Address for correspondence: SAEED SALEHI, Research Institute for Fundamental Sciences (RIFS), University of Tabriz, P.O.Box 51666–16471, Bahman 29th Boulevard, Tabriz, IRAN. ⋆ This is a part of the Ph.D. thesis of the second author written under the supervision of the first author at the University of Tabriz, IRAN.
    [Show full text]
  • General Topology
    General Topology Tom Leinster 2014{15 Contents A Topological spaces2 A1 Review of metric spaces.......................2 A2 The definition of topological space.................8 A3 Metrics versus topologies....................... 13 A4 Continuous maps........................... 17 A5 When are two spaces homeomorphic?................ 22 A6 Topological properties........................ 26 A7 Bases................................. 28 A8 Closure and interior......................... 31 A9 Subspaces (new spaces from old, 1)................. 35 A10 Products (new spaces from old, 2)................. 39 A11 Quotients (new spaces from old, 3)................. 43 A12 Review of ChapterA......................... 48 B Compactness 51 B1 The definition of compactness.................... 51 B2 Closed bounded intervals are compact............... 55 B3 Compactness and subspaces..................... 56 B4 Compactness and products..................... 58 B5 The compact subsets of Rn ..................... 59 B6 Compactness and quotients (and images)............. 61 B7 Compact metric spaces........................ 64 C Connectedness 68 C1 The definition of connectedness................... 68 C2 Connected subsets of the real line.................. 72 C3 Path-connectedness.......................... 76 C4 Connected-components and path-components........... 80 1 Chapter A Topological spaces A1 Review of metric spaces For the lecture of Thursday, 18 September 2014 Almost everything in this section should have been covered in Honours Analysis, with the possible exception of some of the examples. For that reason, this lecture is longer than usual. Definition A1.1 Let X be a set. A metric on X is a function d: X × X ! [0; 1) with the following three properties: • d(x; y) = 0 () x = y, for x; y 2 X; • d(x; y) + d(y; z) ≥ d(x; z) for all x; y; z 2 X (triangle inequality); • d(x; y) = d(y; x) for all x; y 2 X (symmetry).
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 3210 Metric Spaces
    MATH 3210 Metric spaces University of Leeds, School of Mathematics November 29, 2017 Syllabus: 1. Definition and fundamental properties of a metric space. Open sets, closed sets, closure and interior. Convergence of sequences. Continuity of mappings. (6) 2. Real inner-product spaces, orthonormal sequences, perpendicular distance to a subspace, applications in approximation theory. (7) 3. Cauchy sequences, completeness of R with the standard metric; uniform convergence and completeness of C[a; b] with the uniform metric. (3) 4. The contraction mapping theorem, with applications in the solution of equations and differential equations. (5) 5. Connectedness and path-connectedness. Introduction to compactness and sequential compactness, including subsets of Rn. (6) LECTURE 1 Books: Victor Bryant, Metric spaces: iteration and application, Cambridge, 1985. M. O.´ Searc´oid,Metric Spaces, Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series, 2006. D. Kreider, An introduction to linear analysis, Addison-Wesley, 1966. 1 Metrics, open and closed sets We want to generalise the idea of distance between two points in the real line, given by d(x; y) = jx − yj; and the distance between two points in the plane, given by p 2 2 d(x; y) = d((x1; x2); (y1; y2)) = (x1 − y1) + (x2 − y2) : to other settings. [DIAGRAM] This will include the ideas of distances between functions, for example. 1 1.1 Definition Let X be a non-empty set. A metric on X, or distance function, associates to each pair of elements x, y 2 X a real number d(x; y) such that (i) d(x; y) ≥ 0; and d(x; y) = 0 () x = y (positive definite); (ii) d(x; y) = d(y; x) (symmetric); (iii) d(x; z) ≤ d(x; y) + d(y; z) (triangle inequality).
    [Show full text]
  • Euclidean Space - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Page 1 of 5
    Euclidean space - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Page 1 of 5 Euclidean space From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In mathematics, Euclidean space is the Euclidean plane and three-dimensional space of Euclidean geometry, as well as the generalizations of these notions to higher dimensions. The term “Euclidean” distinguishes these spaces from the curved spaces of non-Euclidean geometry and Einstein's general theory of relativity, and is named for the Greek mathematician Euclid of Alexandria. Classical Greek geometry defined the Euclidean plane and Euclidean three-dimensional space using certain postulates, while the other properties of these spaces were deduced as theorems. In modern mathematics, it is more common to define Euclidean space using Cartesian coordinates and the ideas of analytic geometry. This approach brings the tools of algebra and calculus to bear on questions of geometry, and Every point in three-dimensional has the advantage that it generalizes easily to Euclidean Euclidean space is determined by three spaces of more than three dimensions. coordinates. From the modern viewpoint, there is essentially only one Euclidean space of each dimension. In dimension one this is the real line; in dimension two it is the Cartesian plane; and in higher dimensions it is the real coordinate space with three or more real number coordinates. Thus a point in Euclidean space is a tuple of real numbers, and distances are defined using the Euclidean distance formula. Mathematicians often denote the n-dimensional Euclidean space by , or sometimes if they wish to emphasize its Euclidean nature. Euclidean spaces have finite dimension. Contents 1 Intuitive overview 2 Real coordinate space 3 Euclidean structure 4 Topology of Euclidean space 5 Generalizations 6 See also 7 References Intuitive overview One way to think of the Euclidean plane is as a set of points satisfying certain relationships, expressible in terms of distance and angle.
    [Show full text]
  • สมบัติหลักมูลของฟีลด์อันดับ Fundamental Properties Of
    DOI: 10.14456/mj-math.2018.5 วารสารคณิตศาสตร์ MJ-MATh 63(694) Jan–Apr, 2018 โดย สมาคมคณิตศาสตร์แห่งประเทศไทย ในพระบรมราชูปถัมภ์ http://MathThai.Org [email protected] สมบตั ิหลกั มูลของฟี ลดอ์ นั ดบั Fundamental Properties of Ordered Fields ภัทราวุธ จันทร์เสงี่ยม Pattrawut Chansangiam Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, King Mongkut’s Institute of Technology Ladkrabang, Ladkrabang, Bangkok, 10520, Thailand Email: [email protected] บทคดั ย่อ เราอภิปรายสมบัติเชิงพีชคณิต สมบัติเชิงอันดับและสมบัติเชิงทอพอโลยีที่สาคัญของ ฟีลด์อันดับ ในข้อเท็จจริงนั้น ค่าสัมบูรณ์ในฟีลด์อันดับใดๆ มีสมบัติคล้ายกับค่าสัมบูรณ์ของ จ านวนจริง เราให้บทพิสูจน์อย่างง่ายของการสมมูลกันระหว่าง สมบัติอาร์คิมีดิสกับความ หนาแน่น ของฟีลด์ย่อยตรรกยะ เรายังให้เงื่อนไขที่สมมูลกันสาหรับ ฟีลด์อันดับที่จะมีสมบัติ อาร์คิมีดิส ซึ่งเกี่ยวกับการลู่เข้าของลาดับและการทดสอบอนุกรมเรขาคณิต คำส ำคัญ: ฟิลด์อันดับ สมบัติของอาร์คิมีดิส ฟีลด์ย่อยตรรกยะ อนุกรมเรขาคณิต ABSTRACT We discuss fundamental algebraic-order-topological properties of ordered fields. In fact, the absolute value in any ordered field has properties similar to those of real numbers. We give a simple proof of the equivalence between the Archimedean property and the density of the rational subfield. We also provide equivalent conditions for an ordered field to be Archimedean, involving convergence of certain sequences and the geometric series test. Keywords: Ordered Field, Archimedean Property, Rational Subfield, Geometric Series วารสารคณิตศาสตร์ MJ-MATh 63(694) Jan-Apr, 2018 37 1. Introduction to those of
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter P Prerequisites Course Number
    Chapter P Prerequisites Course Number Section P.1 Review of Real Numbers and Their Properties Instructor Objective: In this lesson you learned how to represent, classify, and Date order real numbers, and to evaluate algebraic expressions. Important Vocabulary Define each term or concept. Real numbers The set of numbers formed by joining the set of rational numbers and the set of irrational numbers. Inequality A statement that represents an order relationship. Absolute value The magnitude or distance between the origin and the point representing a real number on the real number line. I. Real Numbers (Page 2) What you should learn How to represent and A real number is rational if it can be written as . the ratio classify real numbers p/q of two integers, where q ¹ 0. A real number that cannot be written as the ratio of two integers is called irrational. The point 0 on the real number line is the origin . On the number line shown below, the numbers to the left of 0 are negative . The numbers to the right of 0 are positive . 0 Every point on the real number line corresponds to exactly one real number. Example 1: Give an example of (a) a rational number (b) an irrational number Answers will vary. For example, (a) 1/8 = 0.125 (b) p » 3.1415927 . II. Ordering Real Numbers (Pages 3-4) What you should learn How to order real If a and b are real numbers, a is less than b if b - a is numbers and use positive. inequalities Larson/Hostetler Trigonometry, Sixth Edition Student Success Organizer IAE Copyright © Houghton Mifflin Company.
    [Show full text]
  • Topology - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Page 1 of 7
    Topology - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Page 1 of 7 Topology From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Topology (from the Greek τόπος , “place”, and λόγος , “study”) is a major area of mathematics concerned with properties that are preserved under continuous deformations of objects, such as deformations that involve stretching, but no tearing or gluing. It emerged through the development of concepts from geometry and set theory, such as space, dimension, and transformation. Ideas that are now classified as topological were expressed as early as 1736. Toward the end of the 19th century, a distinct A Möbius strip, an object with only one discipline developed, which was referred to in Latin as the surface and one edge. Such shapes are an geometria situs (“geometry of place”) or analysis situs object of study in topology. (Greek-Latin for “picking apart of place”). This later acquired the modern name of topology. By the middle of the 20 th century, topology had become an important area of study within mathematics. The word topology is used both for the mathematical discipline and for a family of sets with certain properties that are used to define a topological space, a basic object of topology. Of particular importance are homeomorphisms , which can be defined as continuous functions with a continuous inverse. For instance, the function y = x3 is a homeomorphism of the real line. Topology includes many subfields. The most basic and traditional division within topology is point-set topology , which establishes the foundational aspects of topology and investigates concepts inherent to topological spaces (basic examples include compactness and connectedness); algebraic topology , which generally tries to measure degrees of connectivity using algebraic constructs such as homotopy groups and homology; and geometric topology , which primarily studies manifolds and their embeddings (placements) in other manifolds.
    [Show full text]
  • Section 27. Compact Subspaces of the Real Line
    27. Compact Subspaces of the Real Line 1 Section 27. Compact Subspaces of the Real Line Note. As mentioned in the previous section, the Heine-Borel Theorem states that a set of real numbers is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded. When reading Munkres, beware that when he uses the term “interval” he means a bounded interval. In these notes we follow the more traditional analysis terminology and we explicitly state “closed and bounded” interval when dealing with compact intervals of real numbers. Theorem 27.1. Let X be a simply ordered set having the least upper bound property. In the order topology, each closed and bounded interval X is compact. Corollary 27.2. Every closed and bounded interval [a,b] R (where R has the ⊂ standard topology) is compact. Note. We can quickly get half of the Heine-Borel Theorem with the following. Corollary 27.A. Every closed and bounded set in R (where R has the standard topology) is compact. Note. The following theorem classifies compact subspaces of Rn under the Eu- clidean metric (and under the square metric). Recall that the standard topology 27. Compact Subspaces of the Real Line 2 on R is the same as the metric topology under the Euclidean metric (see Exam- ple 1 of Section 14), so this theorem includes and extends the previous corollary. Therefore we (unlike Munkres) call this the Heine-Borel Theorem. Theorem 27.3. The Heine-Borel Theorem. A subspace A of Rn is compact if and only if it is closed and is bounded in the Euclidean metric d or the square metric ρ.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology
    2.1. METRIC SPACES 29 Definition 2.1.29. The function f is called uniformly continuous if it is continu- ous and, for all > 0, the δ > 0 can be chosen independently of x0. In precise mathematical notation, one has ( > 0)( δ > 0)( x X) ∀ ∃ ∀ 0 ∈ ( x x0 X d (x , x0) < δ ), d (f(x ), f(x)) < . ∀ ∈ { ∈ | X 0 } Y 0 Definition 2.1.30. A function f : X Y is called Lipschitz continuous on A X → ⊆ if there is a constant L R such that dY (f(x), f(y)) LdX (x, y) for all x, y A. ∈ ≤ ∈ Let fA denote the restriction of f to A X defined by fA : A Y with ⊆ → f (x) = f(x) for all x A. It is easy to verify that, if f is Lipschitz continuous on A ∈ A, then fA is uniformly continuous. Problem 2.1.31. Let (X, d) be a metric space and define f : X R by f(x) = → d(x, x ) for some fixed x X. Show that f is Lipschitz continuous with L = 1. 0 0 ∈ 2.1.3 Completeness Suppose (X, d) is a metric space. From Definition 2.1.8, we know that a sequence x , x ,... of points in X converges to x X if, for every δ > 0, there exists an 1 2 ∈ integer N such that d(x , x) < δ for all i N. i ≥ 1 n = 2 n = 4 0.8 n = 8 ) 0.6 t ( n f 0.4 0.2 0 1 0.5 0 0.5 1 − − t Figure 2.1: The sequence of continuous functions in Example 2.1.32 satisfies the Cauchy criterion.
    [Show full text]