The Relative Interior of the Base Polyhedron and the Core*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Relative Interior of the Base Polyhedron and the Core* Forthcoming in Economic Theory The Relative Interior of the Base Polyhedron and the Core* Jingang Zhao Department of Economics Iowa State University 260 Heady Hall Ames, Iowa 50011-1070 USA Fax: (515) 294-0221 Tel: (515) 294-5245 (Email: [email protected]) Summary: This note provides two necessary and sufficient conditions for the relative interior of the core (and the base polyhedron) to be non-empty: (i) the second largest excess of the prenucleolus is negative; (ii) the grand coalition's payoff is greater than the minimum no-blocking payoff. Such conditions imply an intuitive method in proving core existence, they also imply results on the sensitivity of the base polyhedron and the core. Keywords: Base polyhedron, core, minimum no-blocking payoff, nucleolus, sensitivity analysis. JEL Classification Number: C62, C71, D71 AMS#: 05B35, 52B40, 90C31, 90D12. Running Head: The Interior of Base Polyhedron and Core * The author would like to thank Rick Percy, David Schmeidler, Lin Zhou, an anonymous referee, and the editor for valuable comments and suggestions. All errors, of course, are my own. An earlier version of the paper was circulated with the title "The comparative statics of the core and new conditions for core existence." 1. Introduction The core of a convex game and the base polyhedron of a submodular set function are dual to each other. This note provides two necessary and sufficient conditions for their relative interior (R-interior henceforth) to be non-empty. The first condition relies on a new property of the prenucleolus: the core has a non-empty R-interior if and only if the second component in the excess vector of the prenucleolus is negative. The second condition uses the new concept of the minimum no-blocking payoff (MNBP, i.e., the minimum payoff needed to satisfy all proper subcoalitions): the core has a non-empty R-interior if and only if the grand coalition's payoff is greater than the MNBP. The second condition is based on the intuition that the core of a game or a surplus-sharing problem is non-empty (empty) whenever the grand coalition has enough (too little) to split. This argument provides a new and intuitive method in proving core existence, which has at least two advantages over the balancedness method: the concept of balancedness is quite abstract and unfamiliar to most applied scholars, while the MNBP method is intuitive and can be readily used by applied scholars; the balanced approach tells nothing about the R-interior of the core, while the MNBP method automatically reveals the status of the core's R-interior. The conditions have applications in the sensitivity of the core, in general, and in cartel stability, in particular. The core with a non-empty R-interior remains non-empty against small perturbations. Consequently, a cartel agreement will be stable against small shocks if it specifies an allocation that is in the R-interior of the core. On the other hand, a non-empty core with an empty R-interior could be made empty by certain perturbations. Therefore, a cartel agreement will be unstable if the cartel has an empty core or has a non-empty core with an empty interior. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 describes the problem and definitions; Section 3 establishes two conditions on the R-interior of the core and the base polyhedron, and discusses their implications. Section 4 studies the geometric structure of the core. Section 5 concludes, and the appendix provides all proofs. 2 2. Description of the Problem Let N = {1, 2, ..., n} be a finite set, and N = 2N denote the collection of subsets of N. A set function v: N ®R+ with v(Æ) = 0 is submodular if v(S) + v(T) ³ v(SÈT) + v(SÇT) for every S, T Î N , and it is supermodular (or a convex game) if the inequality is reversed. A submodular function defines a cost-sharing (CS) problem, which characterizes those situations like carpooling in which the costs exhibit scale/scope economies: for any partition D = {S1, S2, ..., Sk }of S Î N, it costs $v(Si) for the travelers in a coalition Si to take a taxicab alone, it costs only k v(S) £ S i=1v(Si) if all travelers in S share one taxicab. On the other hand, a supermodular function (or a convex game in coalition value form) defines a surplus-sharing (SS) problem, which characterizes those situations like networks in which returns exhibit scale/scope economies: for any partition D = {T1, ...,Tk} of T Î N, the network providers in a coalition Ti alone can generate a revenue of $v(Ti), the full cooperation by k all providers in T can generate v(T) ³ Si=1v(Ti). In both CS and SS problems, it is assumed that the gains (savings) of full cooperation are k positive. Precisely, we assume v(N) > Si=1v(Ti) for any non-trivial partition {T1, ...,Tk} of N in a k SS problem, and v(N) < Si=1v(Si) for any non-trivial partition {S1, ..., Sk } of N in a CS problem. How to split the joint returns (costs) v(N) is the main subject in cooperative game theory, and the core (base polyhedron) provides a natural solution to the SS (CS) problems. Now, interpret the set function v as a general SS problem without requiring the supermodularity, let it be given as a TU (transferable utility) game in coalition value form (1) G = {N, v(.)}, or alternatively, as a (2n-1)–dimensional non-negative vector i 2n–1 (2) t = {t = v(S) | S ¹ Æ and S Í N}Î R+ , 3 where the components are arranged decreasingly by coalition size and then lexicographically decreasing by player indices1. For example, for n = 3, t = {t1, t2, …, t7} = {v(123), v(23), v(13), v(12), v(3), v(2), v(1)}. Thus, one always has ti = v(N) for i = 1, and ti = v(1) for i = 2n-1. 1 n n i A payoff vector is any x = (x ,…, x )Î R+ specifying a payoff x ³ 0 to each player i n n S i Î N. An allocation of v(N) is any x Î D (v(N)) = {x Î R+ | iÎNx = v(N)}. The base polyhedron and the core are defined below: Definition 1: The base polyhedron of a set function v (or the vector (2)) is given by (3) n i i B(v) = B(t) = {yÎR+ | S iÎTy £ v(T) for all T ¹ Æ, T Í N, SiÎNy = v(N)}; the core of the game (1) (or the vector (2)) is given by n S i S i (4) C(G) = C(t) = {xÎR+ | iÎS x ³ v(S) for all S ¹ Æ, S Í N, iÎN x = v(N)}. An allocation y in the base polyhedron splits the total costs v(N) in such a way that no coalition T pays more than its own cost v(T), while a core allocation x splits the total payoff v(N) in such a way that no coalition S receives less than its own payoff v(S). Because no coalition alone can do better than the proposed allocations, coalitional rationality is satisfied for all coalitions, so the allocations in the core and base polyhedron are socially stable. Since base polyhedron and core (and CS and SS problems) are dual to each other, we shall focus the discussions, like the literature in economics and game theory, on the core of a SS problem and will not repeat the dual results for base polyhedron. It has been shown that the core (base polyhedron) of a convex game (submodular function) is always non-empty (see Edmonds, 1970; Shapley, 1971; Fujishige, 1991). However, the core of a general game (1) (the base polyhedron of a general set function) might be empty or non-empty. As already discussed, the characterizations of the core's R-interior provides a new 1 i j n Let |S| denote the number of players in S, and t = v(Si), t = v(Sj) for any 1 £ i < j £ 2 -1, then |Si| ³ |Sj|, and the sum of the entries of Si is lexigraphically greater than that of Sj if |Si| = |Sj|. 4 method of proving core existence, which is more intuitive than the balanced2 method (Bondareva, 1962; Shapley, 1967). n 2 n 2 n For any xÎ R , let ||x|| = Si=1 xi , Bd(x) = {yÎ R | ||x–y|| < d} be its open d- n n S i neighborhood (d > 0). Recall that D (v(N)) = {x Î R+ | iÎNx = v(N)} is the set of all allocations for v(N). The R-interior of C(t) can be given as n R.IntC(t) = {xÎC(t) | Bd(x)ÇD (v(N)) Ì C(t) for some small d>0}. The first condition for R.IntC(t) ¹ Æ uses the concept of prenucleolus defined below: given a payoff vector x in the game (1), the excess of a coalition S against x is the difference between its payoff v(S) and those allocated by x: i (5) e(S, x) = v(S) – SiÎS x . Let q(x) denote the (2n-1)–dimensional excess vector whose components are arranged in a decreasing order, i.e., (6) qi(x) = e(Si, x) for some Si ¹ Æ, Si ÎN , and n qi(x) ³ qj(x), 1 £ i < j £ 2 -1. The tie-breaking rule is the same as the earlier "decreasing by coalition size and then lexicographically decreasing by player indices" of (2). In other words, if qi(x) = e(Si, x) = e(Sj, x) = qj(x) for some i < j, then |Si| ³ |Sj|, and the sum of the entries of Si is lexicographically greater than that of Sj if |Si| = |Sj|.
Recommended publications
  • Viable Nash Equilibria: Formation and Defection (Feb 2020)
    VIABLE NASH EQUILIBRIA: FORMATION AND DEFECTION (FEB 2020) EHUD KALAI In memory of John Nash Abstract. To be credible, economic analysis should restrict itself to the use of only those Nash equilibria that are viable. To assess the viability of an equilibrium , I study simple dual indices: a formation index, F (), that speci…es the number of loyalists needed to form ; and a defection index, D(), that speci…es the number of defectors that can sustain. Surprisingly, these simple indices (1) predict the performance of Nash equilibria in social systems and lab experiments, and (2) uncover new prop- erties of Nash equilibria and stability issues that have so far eluded game theory re…nements. JEL Classi…cation Codes: C0, C7, D5, D9. 1. Overview Current economic analysis often relies on the notion of a Nash equilibrium. Yet there are mixed opinions about the viability of this notion. On the one hand, many equilibria, referred to as viable in this paper, play critical roles in functioning social systems and perform well in lab and …eld experiments. Date: March 9, 2018, this version Feb 24, 2020. Key words and phrases. Normal form games, Nash equilibrium, Stability, Fault tolerance, Behavioral Economics. The author thanks the following people for helpful conversations: Nemanja Antic, Sunil Chopra, Vince Crawford, K…r Eliaz, Drew Fudenberg, Ronen Gradwohl, Yingni Guo, Adam Kalai, Fern Kalai, Martin Lariviere, Eric Maskin, Rosemarie Nagel, Andy Postlewaite, Larry Samuelson, David Schmeidler, James Schummer, Eran Shmaya, Joel Sobel, and Peyton Young; and seminar participants at the universities of the Basque Country, Oxford, Tel Aviv, Yale, Stanford, Berkeley, Stony Brook, Bar Ilan, the Technion, and the Hebrew University.
    [Show full text]
  • Updating Beliefs When Evidence Is Open to Interpretation: Implications for Bias and Polarization∗
    Updating Beliefs when Evidence is Open to Interpretation: Implications for Bias and Polarization∗ Roland G. Fryer, Jr., Philipp Harms, and Matthew O. Jacksony This Version: October 2017 Forthcoming in Journal of the European Economic Association Abstract We introduce a model in which agents observe signals about the state of the world, some of which are open to interpretation. Our decision makers first interpret each signal and then form a posterior on the sequence of interpreted signals. This `double updating' leads to confirmation bias and can lead agents who observe the same information to polarize. We explore the model's predictions in an on-line experiment in which individuals interpret research summaries about climate change and the death penalty. Consistent with the model, there is a significant relationship between an individual's prior and their interpretation of the summaries; and - even more striking - over half of the subjects exhibit polarizing behavior. JEL classification numbers: D10, D80, J15, J71, I30 Keywords: beliefs, polarization, learning, updating, Bayesian updating, biases, dis- crimination, decision making ∗We are grateful to Sandro Ambuehl, Ken Arrow, Tanaya Devi, Juan Dubra, Jon Eguia, Ben Golub, Richard Holden, Lawrence Katz, Peter Klibanoff, Scott Kominers, Franziska Michor, Giovanni Parmigiani, Matthew Rabin, Andrei Shleifer, and Joshua Schwartzein for helpful comments and suggestions. Adriano Fernandes provided exceptional research assistance. yFryer is at the Department of Economics, Harvard University, and the NBER, ([email protected]); Jackson is at the Department of Economics, Stanford University, the Santa Fe Institute, and CIFAR (jack- [email protected]); and Harms is at the Department of Mathematical Stochastics, University of Freiburg, ([email protected]).
    [Show full text]
  • (Eds.) Foundations in Microeconomic Theory Hugo F
    Matthew O. Jackson • Andrew McLennan (Eds.) Foundations in Microeconomic Theory Hugo F. Sonnenschein Matthew O. Jackson • Andrew McLennan (Eds.) Foundations in Microeconomic Theory A Volume in Honor of Hugo F. Sonnenschein ^ Springer Professor Matthew O. Jackson Professor Andrew McLennan Stanford University School of Economics Department of Economics University of Queensland Stanford, CA 94305-6072 Rm. 520, Colin Clark Building USA The University of Queensland [email protected] NSW 4072 Australia [email protected] ISBN: 978-3-540-74056-8 e-ISBN: 978-3"540-74057-5 Library of Congress Control Number: 2007941253 © 2008 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the German Copyright Law of September 9,1965, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer. Violations are liable to prosecution under the German Copyright Law. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. Cover design: WMX Design GmbH, Heidelberg Printed on acid-free paper 987654321 spnnger.com Contents Introduction 1 A Brief Biographical Sketch of Hugo F. Sonnenschein 5 1 Kevin C. Sontheimer on Hugo F.
    [Show full text]
  • The Case of the Market for Non-Prime Mortgage-Based Securities Br
    Made centro de pesquisa em macroeconomia das desigualdades Working Paper 18.01.2021 nº 003 Conventions and the process of market formation: the case of the market for non-prime mortgage-based securities Bruno Höfig Abstract 18.01.2021 nº 003 The article develops the hypothesis that conventions can be key to the development of markets for previously untraded financial assets. It argues that the absence of historical data on the performance of Bruno Höfig Ph.D. in Economics - SOAS, assets may induce agents to form beliefs in ways that University of London preclude the formation of markets for certain financial bhofi[email protected] instruments. Conversely, in the absence of trading, the data on the basis of which agents could revise their The author would like to thank Alfredo Saad-Filho, Pedro beliefs will not be produced, giving rise to a feedback Mendes Loureiro, Camila Alves loop that hinders the process of market-formation. de André, Leonardo Müller, The article contends that one of the ways of Tomás Gotta and Matías Vernengo for comments on overcoming this state is the development of earlier drafts of this article. The conventions about the distribution of future payofs. It usual disclaimers apply. then shows that the emergence of the conventions that credit rating agencies could reliably measure the riskiness of non-prime residential mortgage-securities (RMBSs), and that the FICO score could reliably give a quantitative expression of the creditworthiness of individual borrowers was a crucial enabling condition of the formation of a market for RMBSs in the United States. Keywords: conventional valuation, probability, mortgage-backed securities, credit rating agencies, credit scores.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae 03/97
    CURRICULUM VITAE April 2006 Ehud Kalai, Ph.D. Home Office 1110 N. Lake Shore Dr., Apt. 23S Department of Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences Chicago, IL 60611 Kellogg School of Management Phone: (847) 571-1097 Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois, 60208 Fax: (312) 482-9772 (847) 491-7017; fax (847) 467-3646 e-mail: [email protected] Born, December 7, 1942, Tel Aviv, Israel Education Cornell University, Ithaca, New York: Ph.D. in Mathematics (1972); MS in Statistics (1971). University of California, Berkeley: A.B. in Mathematics (1967). Permanent Academic Positions 09/75-present Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University: Visiting Assistant Professor (9/75-9/76), Associate Professor (9/76-9/78), Professor (9/78-9/82), The Charles E. Morrison Professor of Decision Sciences (9/82-9/2001); The James J. O'Connor Distinguished Professor of Decision and Game Sciences (9/2001 - present). 03/90-present Professor of Mathematics (courtesy), Department of Mathematics, CAS, Northwestern University. 10/72-9/75 Assistant Professor, Department of Statistics, Tel Aviv University. Editorial Positions Editor and founder, Games and Economic Behavior, Academic Press, 1988- . Member of the Editorial Board of the International Journal of Game Theory, Physica Verlag, 1984- . Member of the Editorial Board of Mathematical Social Sciences, North-Holland, 1980-1993. Associate Editor, The Journal of Economic Theory, Academic Press, Inc., 1980-1988. Other Positions President of the Game Theory Society, 2003-2006 Co Founder and Executive Vice President of the Game Theory Society, 1998-2003 Director of the Kellogg Center for Strategic Decision-Making, 1995- . Founding organizer of the Nancy L.
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Choice As a Toolbox for the Economist: an Interview with Itzhak Gilboa
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 7, Issue 2, Autumn 2014, pp. 116-141. http://ejpe.org/pdf/7-2-int.pdf Rational choice as a toolbox for the economist: an interview with Itzhak Gilboa CATHERINE HERFELD Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München Itzhak Gilboa (Tel Aviv, 1963) is currently professor of economics at the Eitan Berglas School of Economics at Tel-Aviv University and professor of economics and decision sciences at the Hautes Études Commerciales (HEC) in Paris. He earned undergraduate degrees in mathematics and in economics at Tel Aviv University, where he also obtained his MA and PhD in economics under the supervision of David Schmeidler. Before joining Tel Aviv University in 2004 and the HEC in 2008, Gilboa taught at the J. L. Kellogg Graduate School of Management at Northwestern University, the University of Pennsylvania, and Boston University. Gilboa’s main area of interest is decision-making under uncertainty, focusing on the definition of probability, notions of rationality, non- Bayesian decision models, and related issues. He has published broadly in areas such as decision and game theory, microeconomics, philosophy, social choice theory, and applied mathematics. He has written over 90 articles in these fields. Gilboa has furthermore written a textbook entitled Rational choice (Gilboa 2010a), in which he lays out what he takes to be the main toolbox for studying and improving human decision-making. Additional books include A theory of case-based decisions (Gilboa and Schmeidler 2001), Theory of decision under uncertainty (Gilboa 2009), Making better decisions (Gilboa 2010b), and Case-based predictions (Gilboa and Schmeidler 2012).
    [Show full text]
  • Chronology of Game Theory
    Chronology of Game Theory http://www.econ.canterbury.ac.nz/personal_pages/paul_walker/g... Home | UC Home | Econ. Department | Chronology of Game Theory | Nobel Prize A Chronology of Game Theory by Paul Walker September 2012 | Ancient | 1700 | 1800 | 1900 | 1950 | 1960 | 1970 | 1980 | 1990 | Nobel Prize | 2nd Nobel Prize | 3rd Nobel Prize | 0-500AD The Babylonian Talmud is the compilation of ancient law and tradition set down during the first five centuries A.D. which serves as the basis of Jewish religious, criminal and civil law. One problem discussed in the Talmud is the so called marriage contract problem: a man has three wives whose marriage contracts specify that in the case of this death they receive 100, 200 and 300 respectively. The Talmud gives apparently contradictory recommendations. Where the man dies leaving an estate of only 100, the Talmud recommends equal division. However, if the estate is worth 300 it recommends proportional division (50,100,150), while for an estate of 200, its recommendation of (50,75,75) is a complete mystery. This particular Mishna has baffled Talmudic scholars for two millennia. In 1985, it was recognised that the Talmud anticipates the modern theory of cooperative games. Each solution corresponds to the nucleolus of an appropriately defined game. 1713 In a letter dated 13 November 1713 Francis Waldegrave provided the first, known, minimax mixed strategy solution to a two-person game. Waldegrave wrote the letter, about a two-person version of the card game le Her, to Pierre-Remond de Montmort who in turn wrote to Nicolas Bernoulli, including in his letter a discussion of the Waldegrave solution.
    [Show full text]
  • A Personal Tribute to David Schmeidler's Influence
    A Personal Tribute to David Schmeidler’s Influence Peter P. Wakker* UN HOMMAGE PERSONNEL À L’INFLUENCE DE DAVID SCHMEIDLER Keywords: Choquet expected utility, uncertainty, nucleolus Mots clés: espérance d’utilité à la Choquet, incertitude, nucleolus Document téléchargé depuis www.cairn.info - 145.5.176.10 28/02/2020 16:23 © Presses de Sciences Po JEL Codes: D91, C81. This paper describes my relationship with David Schmeidler and how he ins- pired me. My first meeting with David was on August 29, 1984, in a conference on Operations Research in Osnabrück in Germany. Two positive impressions preceded it. First, my colleague PhD student Jean Derks in Nijmegen had once told me enthusiastically about David’s nucleolus cooperative game solution (Schmeidler [1969]). Second, and I could not anticipate how this would change my life, my supervisor and mentor Stef Tijs had given me a copy, that is, a paper copy (of copy of copy of . in those days), of Schmeidler [1982], later published as Schmeidler [1986], [1989]. Stef introduced me to David on August 29, 1984, suggesting I might visit David. David suggested that that might be but kept it short. He was a man of few words, even more then than nowadays. He later attended my lecture on a part of my PhD thesis that led to Wakker [1993], and I guessed that he liked it. Then a 6-week visit was arranged, which took place early 1985. With my Bayesian sympathies I had been learning, the hard way, what a cle- ver and diplomatic Econometrica referee stated as follows: “I urge the author to turn his talents toward nonexpected utility.” My despair had reached a level by that time making me willing to work on just any nonexpected utility model that would come by.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae 03/97
    April 2007 CURRICULUM VITAE Ehud Kalai, Ph.D. Office Department of Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois, 60208 Office: (847) 491-7017; Fax (847) 467-3646 ; Cell (847) 571-1097; [email protected] Born: December 7, 1942, Tel Aviv, Israel Education Cornell University, Ithaca, New York: Ph.D. in Mathematics (1972); MS in Statistics (1971) University of California, Berkeley: A.B. in Mathematics (1967) Permanent Academic Positions The James J. O'Connor Distinguished Professor of Decision and Game Sciences, Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, 9/2001 - present. (Past positions: The Charles E. Morrison Professor of Decision Sciences (9/82-9/01); Professor (9/78-9/82), Associate Professor (9/76-9/78), Visiting Assistant Professor (9/75-9/76) Professor of Mathematics (courtesy), Department of Mathematics, CAS, Northwestern University, 03/90-present Assistant Professor, Department of Statistics, Tel Aviv University, 10/72-9/75 Editorial Positions Editor and founder, Games and Economic Behavior, Elsevier, 1988- Member of the Editorial Board of the International Journal of Game Theory, Physica Verlag, 1984- Member of the Editorial Board of Mathematical Social Sciences, North-Holland, 1980-93 Associate Editor, The Journal of Economic Theory, Academic Press, Inc., 1980-88 Other Positions The Game Theory Society, Past President, 2006-present President of the Game Theory Society, 2003-06 Founder and Executive Vice President of the Game Theory
    [Show full text]
  • The Nucleolus, the Kernel, and the Bargaining Set: an Update∗
    The Nucleolus, the Kernel, and the Bargaining Set: An Update∗ Elena I˜narra,† Roberto Serrano,‡ and Ken-Ichi Shimomura§ June 2019 Abstract One of the many important contributions in David Schmeidler’s distinguished career was the introduction of the nucleolus. This paper is an update on the nucleolus and its two related supersolutions, i.e., the kernel and the bargaining set. JEL classification numbers: C71, C72. Keywords: nucleolus, kernel, bargaining set. ∗We thank Antoine Billot and Tzachi Gilboa for kindly inviting us to participate in the special issue of La Revue Economique in honor of David Schmeidler. This paper is an out- growth of four lectures delivered by Serrano at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 10th Summer School in Economic Theory, in June 1999. Part of section 5 is based on Shimomura (2015). We thank Zeky Murra and Xu Zhang for terrific research assistance. I˜narra ac- knowledges research support from the Spanish Government grant ECO2015-67519-P, and Shimomura from Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research (A)18H03641 and (C)19K01558. †University of the Basque Country, Bilbao, Spain; [email protected] ‡Brown university, Providence, RI, U.S.A.; roberto [email protected] §Kobe University, Kobe, Japan; [email protected] 1 Introduction One of David Schmeidler’s many important contributions in his distinguished career was the introduction of the nucleolus, one of the central single-valued solution concepts in cooperative game theory. This paper is an updated survey on the nucleolus and its two related supersolutions, i.e., the kernel and the bargaining set. As a first approach to these concepts, we refer the reader to the great survey by Maschler (1992); see also the relevant chapters in Peleg and Sudholter (2003).
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Economics
    Prof. Daniel L. Chen, JD, PhD http://nber.org/~dlchen/ Law and Economics Readings: Topic I: Consequences of Normative Commitments 1. Theory: Design of Legal Institutions • Ian Ayres and Robert Gertner. Filling gaps in incomplete contracts: An economic theory of default rules. The Yale Law Journal, 99(1):87{130, October 1989 • Lucian Arye Bebchuk. Litigation and settlement under imperfect information. The RAND Journal of Economics, 15(3):404{415, 1984 • Gary S. Becker. Crime and punishment: An economic approach. Journal of Political Economy, 76(2):169{217, 1968 • Roland B´enabou and Jean Tirole. Laws and norms. Discussion Paper series 6290, Institute for the Study of Labor (IZA), Bonn, Germany, January 2012 • Daniel L. Chen. Gender violence and the price of virginity: Theory and evidence of incom- plete marriage contracts. Mimeo, University of Chicago, 2004 • Daniel L. Chen. Mechanism design theory. University of Chicago Lecture Notes, 2005 • Ronald H. Coase. The problem of social cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3:1{44, October 1960 • Robert Cooter. Unity in tort, contract, and property: The model of precaution. California Law Review, 73(1):1{51, January 1985 • Robert Cooter and Thomas Ulen. Law and Economics. Pearson Education, 6 edition, 2011 • Harold Demsetz. Toward a theory of property rights. The American Economic Review, 57(2):347{359, 1967 • Aaron S. Edlin and Stefan Reichelstein. Holdups, standard breach remedies, and optimal investment. The American Economic Review, 86(3):478{501, 1996 • Jan Eeckhout, Nicola Persico, and Petra E. Todd. A theory of optimal random crackdowns. The American Economic Review, 100(3):1104{1135, 2010 • Sanford J.
    [Show full text]
  • David Schmeidler, Professor
    David Schmeidler, Professor List of Publications and Discussion Papers: Articles in Journals David Schmeidler, Competitive equilibria in markets with a continuum of traders and incomplete preferences, Econometrica, Vol. 37, 578-86 (1969). David Schmeidler, The nucleolus of a characteristic function game, SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, Vol. 17, 1163-70 (1969). David Schmeidler, Fatou's Lemma in several dimensions, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., Vol. 24, 300-6 (1970). David Schmeidler, A condition for the completeness of partial preference relations, Econometrica, Vol. 39, 403-4 (1971). David Schmeidler, Cores of exact games, I, J. Math. Anal. and Appl., Vol. 40, 214- 25 (1972). David Schmeidler, On set correspondences into uniformly convex Banach spaces, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., Vol. 34, 97-101(1972). David Schmeidler, A remark on the core of an atomless economy, Econometrica, Vol. 40, 579-80 (1972). David Schmeidler and Karl Vind, Fair net trades, Econometrica, Vol. 40, 637-42 (1972). Jaques Dreze, Joan Gabszewicz, David Schmeidler and Karl Vind, Cores and prices in an exchange economy with an atomless sector, Econometrica, Vol. 40, 1091-108 (1972). David Schmeidler, Equilibrium points of non-atomic games, Journal of Statistical Physics, Vol. 7, 295-301 (1973). Werner Hildenbrand, David Schmeidler and Shmuel Zamir, Existence of approximate equilibria and cores, Econometrica, Vol. 41, 1159-66 (1973). Elisha A. Pazner and David Schmeidler, A difficulty in the concept of fairness, Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 41, 441-3 (1974). Elisha A. Pazner and David Schmeidler, Competitive analysis under complete ignorance, International Economic Review, Vol. 16, 246-57 (1975). Elisha A. Pazner and David Schmeidler, Social contract theory and ordinal distributive equity, Journal of Public Economics, Vol.
    [Show full text]