Evolutionary Psychology and Human Reasoning: Testing the Domain-Specificity Hypothesis Through Wason Selection Task
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Evolutionary Psychology and Human Reasoning: Testing the Domain-Specificity Hypothesis through Wason Selection Task Fabrizio Ferrara ([email protected])* Amedeo Esposito ([email protected])* Barbara Pizzini ([email protected])* Olimpia Matarazzo ([email protected])* *Department of Psychology - Second University of Naples, Viale Ellittico 31, Caserta, 81100 Italy Abstract during phylogenetic development. Both these approaches, albeit based on a different conception of the human mind, The better performance in the selection task with deontic rules, compared to the descriptive version, has been share the assumption that it is better equipped for reasoning interpreted by evolutionary psychologists as the evidence that with general (e.g. Cummins 1996, 2013) or specific (e.g. human reasoning has been shaped to deal with either global or Cosmides, 1989; Cosmides & Tooby, 2013) deontic norms specific deontic norms. An alternative hypothesis is that the rather than with epistemic concepts (i.e. the concepts related two types of rules have been embedded in two different forms to knowledge and belief). of reasoning, about and from a rule, the former demanding Experimental evidence achieved mainly by means of the more complex cognitive processes. In a between-subjects study with 640 participants we manipulated the content of the selection task (Wason, 1966) is thought to support this rule (deontic vs. social contract vs. precaution vs. descriptive) claim. In the original formulation, this task consists in and the type of task (reasoning about, traditionally associated selecting the states of affairs necessary to determine the to indicative tasks, vs. reasoning from, traditionally associated truth-value of a descriptive (or indicative) rule expressed to deontic tasks). Results showed that the better performance through the conditional statement "if p then q". Four double- is independent of the content of the rule and is associated to sided cards are presented, conveying on one face the the "reasoning from" task. information of presence/absence of the antecedent (p or not- Keywords: selection task; deontic reasoning; domain-general p) and on the other face the same information about the reasoning; domain-specific reasoning; evolutionary consequent (q or not-q). The cards are shown only by one psychology. side (the visible faces are p, not-p, q, not-q) and participants have to indicate which ones need to be turned over to Introduction determine whether the rule is true or false. According to The “easiness” to reason with deontic norms (i.e. the norms propositional logic, the correct response is to select only that establish what is required, prohibited or allowed to do those cards that would entail the combination apt to make in certain circumstances) has been largely used as a piece of the rule false, i.e. p and not-q. Selecting other cards is evidence supporting the idea of the domain-specific nature insufficient or useless. of mind. This hypothesis has been strongly sustained, The percentages of correct solutions with the original among others, by evolutionary psychologists, according to formulation of the task are very low, between 4% and 30%, which the development of highly specialized cognitive regardless of the abstract/thematic content of the rule and its abilities have improved the environmental fitness and familiarity/unfamiliarity. A great improvement, between phylogenetic evolution of human species. Some scholars 65% and 80%, has been documented when conditional rules (e.g. Barrett & Kurzban, 2006; Cosmides, 1989; Cosmides express deontic norms and it is required to identify potential & Tooby, 2013) posit that such abilities are managed by violators (see for review, Beller, 2008; Cosmides & Tooby, modules, i.e. computational units that process domain- 2013; Cummins, 1996; Stenning & Lambalgen, 2008). The specific information, and claim that the human mind is enduring debate about the implications of these findings massively modular. Other scholars (e.g. Ariew, 1999; regards the legitimacy to infer specific mental structures Cummins 1996, 2013) sustain that domain-specific abilities devoted (e.g. Cosmides 1989; Cummins, 1996) or are not predetermined by modular activity, but by developed (e.g. Cheng & Holyoak, 1985) to process classes canalization, a process which biologically prepares the of rule-governed actions. From an opposed perspective, the human mind to be particular sensitive to specific supposed content-sensitiveness of human reasoning is environmental stimulations and favors the acquisition of instead ascribed to the formal differences between deontic solutions and expertise that have been particularly adaptive and epistemic reasoning (e.g. Buller, 2005; Chater & 216 Oaksford, 1996; Oaksford and Chater, 1994; Perham & (Oda, Hiraishi, & Matsumoto-Oda, 2006; Thompson at al. Oaksford, 2005; Stenning & Lambalgen, 2008). 2015). Although the domain specificity hypothesis had been On the opposite side, a large number of scholars, sharing advanced from an ontogenetic perspective by Cheng & a domain-general conception of human reasoning, have Holyoak (1985) with the pragmatic reasoning schemas advanced alternative hypotheses to account for the different theory, it has been strongly advocated by the evolutionary performance in descriptive and deontic selection tasks, perspective. Cummins (1996, 2003, 2013) postulates the grounded on the consideration that the two tasks have a existence of a specific deontic reasoning, evolutionarily dissimilar structure and rely on different inferential canalized and responsible for the management of any rule processes. that constrains social behavior. Deontic reasoning emerges According to Fodor (2000) and Buller (2005), indicative early in development and seems to be ubiquitous. However, and deontic conditionals have different logical operators some findings (e.g. Dack & Astington, 2011) question this (dyadic vs. monadic) and consequently entail different assertion. inferences. Indeed, in the deontic rule "If you want p, then On the contrary, the followers of the massive modularity you must do q", the non-compliance of not-q cases is hypothesis (e.g. Cosmides, 1989; Fiddik, Cosmides & implicitly conveyed by the mandatory requirement of action Tooby, 2000) posit that neurocognitive modules are q, given the occurrence of p. Instead, the selection of non-q specialized to reason only about specific deontic domains in indicative selection tasks, requires a more complex that particularly favored human evolution, like social falsificationist strategy grounded on the inference that "If p exchange and hazard management. According to these then q" is false when the negation of consequent implies the authors, social exchange, or reciprocation, is the foundation affirmation of antecedent. of social cooperation and is common in all cultures. From a Bayesian approach, the optimal data selection theory Reciprocation is expressed through social contracts, (Chater & Oaksford, 1996; Oaksford & Chater, 1994; conditional rules of the form "If you take benefit P, then you Perham & Oaksford, 2005) also posits that descriptive and must satisfy requirement Q". Selection tasks embedded in deontic selection tasks are solved by using different social exchange scenarios, requiring to detect violators of strategies that rely on distinct probabilistic models. In social contracts, produce very high rates (up to 80%) of descriptive tasks the most rational answer consists in selecting p and not-q cards. Nevertheless, according to selecting p and q cards because, under the assumption that social exchange theory (SET), the selection of these cards is these instances are more rare than their respective contrast not the result of formal logical inferences, but of a "look for classes not-p and not-q (rarity assumption), they convey the cheaters" algorithm, a subroutine of the social exchange bigger expected information gain to establish the truth value module, that identifies those who take the benefit (p card) of the rule. Instead, in deontic tasks participants choose the without satisfying the requirement (not-q card) as potential cards maximizing expected utility. Depending on the violators of the social contract. Empirical evidence of this perspective participants are requested to assume, the most claim is that, presenting switched social contract rules of the useful cards are p and not-q or not-p and q. Deontic tasks form "If you satisfy requirement P, then you are entitled to are less complex in mathematical terms than descriptive receive benefit Q", participants continue to select the cards ones and therefore are simpler to resolve. corresponding to potential cheaters, in this case, not-p and q Other researchers (Jackson & Griggs, 1990; Noveck & (Cosmides, 1989; Gigerenzer & Huge, 1992). Some O'Brien, 1996; Stenning & Lambalgen, 2008) focus on the empirical evidence (see for a review Cosmides & Tooby different status of the rules presented in descriptive or in 2013) documents that the ability to detect cheaters is already deontic tasks, entailing two different forms of reasoning. In present in 3-4 year old children, is cross-cultural, and descriptive tasks, it is required to settle the uncertainty of discerns between unintentional and intentional violations the rule: participants don't know whether the rule is true or (Cosmides, Barrett & Tooby, 2010), but the latter finding is false, and have to reason about it, by selecting instances at least questionable (Matarazzo & Ferrara,