Sociology As a Vocation 1 MICHAEL BURAWOY University of California-Berkeley [email protected]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sociology As a Vocation 1 MICHAEL BURAWOY University of California-Berkeley Burawoy@Berkeley.Edu Ó American Sociological Association 2016 DOI: 10.1177/0094306116653958 http://cs.sagepub.com FEATURED ESSAY Sociology as a Vocation 1 MICHAEL BURAWOY University of California-Berkeley [email protected] What does it mean to live for sociology, two spheres that must be kept apart. Weber today? In attempting to answer this question failed to grasp sociology’s place between I return to Max Weber’s famous lectures science and politics for two reasons: first, delivered toward the end of his life—one sociology as a discipline was still embryonic on science as a vocation and the other on pol- and pre-professional. It needed to be safe- itics as a vocation. He presented ‘‘Science as guarded from politics. Second, he had not a Vocation’’ in November 1917 toward the developed a coherent view of civil society end of World War I and the more pessimistic populated by institutions that could ground ‘‘Politics as a Vocation’’ in January 1919 a standpoint between science and politics.3 after Germany’s defeat.2 The essays them- Yet, and here is the paradox, his concep- selves exemplify Weber’s methodology— tion of sociology as an interpretive under- interpreting social action within the external standing of value-oriented social action calls conditions that shape it. Weber not only for its own value standpoint since sociology explicates the meaning of ‘‘vocation’’— cannot be its own exception. As a form of what it means to ‘‘live for’’ as well to ‘‘live social action it too must be impelled by value off’’ science and politics—but situates their commitments. Weber fully understood this. pursuit within historical and national Indeed, he was so insistent on the ethos of contexts. He explores the possibilities of an science precisely because he feared that soci- ‘‘inner devotion’’ to science or politics in ology might be overrun by arbitrary value Germany as compared to the United States commitments, commitments that are never- and Britain. Yet neither here nor elsewhere theless essential to its pursuit. The tension does Weber turn his sociology of vocation between science and politics was, therefore, back on to sociology itself. He does not complicated by a second tension, that advance from sociology of vocation to sociology between fact and value, or more broadly as a vocation, which is the endeavor of this between instrumental rationality and its essay, an endeavor that draws on but leads underpinnings in value rationality. But with- us beyond Weber. out a conception of civil society, he had no Consonant with Weber’s own life, I shall way of collectively mooring those values, argue that sociology sits uncomfortably and so they are instead reduced to an indi- between science and politics. Twisting vidual existential choice. The completion of between science and politics—since he could Weber’s program and the sustainability of not marry the two—he presented them as sociology depend on its connection to civil society. 1 This essay went through the wringer of my dissertation group: Herbert Docena, Fidan El- cioglu, Zach Levenson, Josh Seim, and Ben 3 One should note, however, that in 1909 Weber Shestakovsky. Thanks to them as well as Dylan submitted a proposal for sociological research Riley, Peter Evans, Black Hawk Hancock, Ca- into three areas: the press, voluntary associa- therine Bolzendahl, and Erik Wright for push- tions, and the relations between technology ing me in new directions. and culture, which suggests he did have an 2 For the dating of the lectures and their biogra- interest in both the public sphere and civil phical and historical situation, see Schluchter society, even if he didn’t use such terms (1968: Chapters 1 and 2). (MW:420). 379 Contemporary Sociology 45, 4 Downloaded from csx.sagepub.com at ASA - American Sociological Association on June 27, 2016 380 Featured Essay Irreducible to economy and polity, civil have to reassert our roots in civil society. society is the institutional birthplace and This is a moment defined by Bourdieu, support for diverse values. It is the stand- Polanyi, and Du Bois—the first defending point from which sociology evaluates the the autonomy of the academy and sociology world, just as the market is the standpoint in particular, the second providing the tools of economics and the state the standpoint to analyze the epic battle between society of political science. Sociology arises with civ- and the market, while the third helps us il society and dissolves when civil society place sociology in its global context. recedes. But civil society is not some harmo- Weber’s admonition to insulate science nious antidote to the colonizing powers of from politics reflects sociology’s period of state and market. It is itself the site of divi- inception and has to be reconsidered in sub- sions, exclusions, and dominations, reaction- sequent periods and in other places. To reify ary as well as progressive movements, all of insulation as though it has universal and which is reflected in the plurality of sociolo- unchanging validity—a sort of sociological gies. Civil society grounds two types of val- ‘‘originalism’’—is to contravene Weber’s ue commitments: anti-utopian sociology root- sociological method that instructs us to delin- ed in a critique of the over-extension of state eate the particular context within which his (totalitarianism) and market (neoliberalism) prescriptions hold, and imaginatively recon- and a utopian sociology that projects a vision struct them for the present. It is necessary to of a collectively organized society. The histo- examine how the relation between politics ry of sociology can be seen as a fluctuating and science shifts and with it, sociology. debate between its utopian and anti-utopian Thus, I will argue with Weber against tendencies, classically represented by Marx Weber. That is to say, the meaning of sociol- and Weber. ogy as a vocation actually changes with the Weber’s view of sociology reflects the context of its pursuit: in the period of incep- specific circumstances of the academic field tion it meant the defense of its autonomy; in and civil society of his time. A very different the second, self-confident period, it assumed perspective emerges with the opening up of an almost religious character; while in the the university and the consolidation of a present period, when sociology finds itself conformity-producing civil society, some- under assault, it calls for engagement. Before times called mass society. We may say that proceeding to these periods, however, sociology’s point of arrival—its golden we must first define ‘‘vocation’’ and then years—came after World War II, particularly ‘‘sociology’’—what it is that continues in in the United States. As a new and optimistic and through variation. science it flowered with the expansion of higher education. This was sociology’s mes- sianic moment captured, on the one side, by The Meaning of Vocation the utopian structural functionalism and In Weber’s view being in the modern world modernization theory that regarded the requires us to face two inexorable condi- United States as the promised land and, on tions: the advance of the division of labor the other side, by its anti-utopian critics and a plurality of incommensurable values. who condemned U.S. imperialism, class Durkheim’s response was to reconcile these domination, racism, and patriarchy. conditions by showing how the perfection of Today we live in a different epoch when the division of labor calls forth and in turn the university and civil society are in retreat, is driven by a specific collective conscious- assailed by neoliberal rationality (Brown ness. Marx, on the other hand, demands 2015). Sociology finds itself embattled in the abolition of the division of labor as inim- ways reminiscent of the world of Max ical to human freedom. Weber. It is swimming against the tide of Weber accepts neither solution: the divi- marketization that is flooding the university. sion of labor is debilitating, but it is here to Retreating into a professional cocoon or ser- stay. The best we can do is imbue specialized vicing the new economy would falsify our occupations with some immanent meaning traditions of anti-utilitarianism and threaten through passionate commitment. In other our utopian imagination. To survive we words, we turn it into a vocation, pursuing Contemporary Sociology 45, 4 Downloaded from csx.sagepub.com at ASA - American Sociological Association on June 27, 2016 Featured Essay 381 it as an end in itself. The prototype is the The same is true of the politician who is Calvinist entrepreneur devoted to the driven by devotion to a cause, knowing ‘‘irrational’’ pursuit of profit for profit’s that ‘‘the final result of political action often, sake. Unlike Lutherans who find it sufficient no, even regularly, stands in completely to passively accept their calling, the Calvin- inadequate and often even paradoxical rela- ist is consumed by the anxiety of not know- tion to its original meaning’’ (PV:117). So ing whether he or she is saved or damned. ‘‘passionate devotion’’ to a cause must be Fate is predetermined but unknown, leading balanced by a ‘‘feeling of responsibility’’ to a desperate search for signs of salvation in and ‘‘sense of proportion.’’ Like scientists the striving for profit and ever-increasing politicians have to comprehend the struc- profit, which is the source of the spirit of cap- tures within which they act—the legislature, italism. The elusiveness of success does not bureaucracy, and party organization. Com- lead to resignation but to the redoubling of paring the institutional configurations in efforts. Hence the meaning of vocation— the United States, Germany, and Britain, commitment without guarantees. Weber recognizes the limits of each: leader- Equally, for the scientist, ‘‘passionate ship democracy with a machine (U.S.) or devotion’’ to the rigors of scholarly pursuit leaderless democracy ruled by professional is a necessary but not sufficient condition politicians without a calling (Germany).
Recommended publications
  • MWS 20.1 (2020) 5] ISSN 1470-8078 Doi: 10.15543/Maxweberstudies.20.1.5
    Max Weber Studies Download Charlemagne font to printer before printing this (use Adobe Downloader). NB. This note will not show up as the text is white—do not delete. MAX WEBER STUDIES Editor Professor Sam Whimster (London) Associate Editors: Dr Austin Harrington (Leeds), Prof Duncan Kelly (Cambridge) Review Editor: Associate Professor Joshua Derman (Hong Kong) Editorial Board Professor Martin Albrow (London), Professor Peter Baehr (Hong Kong), Professor Hinnerk Bruhns (Paris), Professor Hans Henrik Bruun (Copenhagen), Professor David Chalcraft (Liverpool), Dr Xiangqun Chang (London), Professor Sven Eliæson (Uppsala), Dr A’gnes Erde’lyi (Budapest), Dr Jean-Pierre Grossein (Marseille), Dr Edith Hanke (Munich), Professor Dirk Kaesler (Marburg), Pro- fessor S tephen Kalberg (Boston, MA), Professor Thomas Kemple (Vancouver, BC), Professor Sung Ho Kim (Seoul), Professor Rainer Lepsius† (Heidelberg), Professor Klaus Lichtblau (Frankfurt), Sérgio da Mata (Ouro Preto, Brazil), Álvaro Morcillo Laiz (Berlin), Professor Masahiro Noguchi (Tokyo), D r Dr David Owen (Southampton, UK), Professor Kari Palonen (Jyväskylä, Finland), Professor Gian- franco Poggi (Trento, Italy), Professor Larry Ray (Canterbury, UK), Professor Guenther Roth† (New York), Professor Lawrence Scaff (Detroit), Professor Ralph Schroeder (Oxford), Professor Wolfgang Schwentker (Osaka), Professor Alan Scott (New South Wales), Professor Alan Sica (Pennsylvania), Victor Strazzeri (Bern), Professor Richard Swedberg (Ithaca), Dr Keith Tribe (Worcester, UK), Pro- fessor Stephen Turner
    [Show full text]
  • From Max Weber to Public Sociology Michael Burawoy1
    From Max Weber to Public Sociology Michael Burawoy1 Growing up in a political as well as an intellectual environment, Max Weber not only sought to comprehend the world but also to change it. Arguably, he took Karl Marx’s 11th. Thesis on Feuerbach that “philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the point, however, is to change it,” far more seriously than its author. Marx, after all, did not reflect, in any systematic fashion, on the place of intellectuals and their ideas in history. Equally, Emile Durkheim – perhaps because he saw sociology as a deeply moral science, devoted to deriving what ought to be from what is – did not seriously concern himself with political engagement. Among these three founding figures of sociology, it was only Weber, who paid sustained attention to science and politics both in his life and in his writing. He strove to fathom the relation between sociology of society and sociology in society, between theory and practice. Although the notion of public sociology was absent from his conceptual armory, of the three Weber offers the greatest contribution, albeit indi- rectly, to the meaning, challenges and possibilities of public sociology. In, thus, fill- ing out Weber’s reflexive sociology with the notion of public sociology, I show the continuing relevance of his framework for the problems facing sociology and soci- ety today. Instrumental and Value Rationality One hundred years ago the Deutsche Gesellschaft für Soziologie (German Socio- logical Society, DGS for short) held its inaugural meeting in Frankfurt. Max Weber had been a driving force behind its foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • About Modern Society and Culture
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) The problem of disenchantment: scientific naturalism and esoteric discourse, 1900-1939 Asprem, E. Publication date 2013 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Asprem, E. (2013). The problem of disenchantment: scientific naturalism and esoteric discourse, 1900-1939. General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:03 Oct 2021 1 The Intellectual Sacrifice You need to beware of the word Entzauberung as cautiously as you beware of the word secularization. Both describe processes where it is easy to have fanciful pictures of an earlier age, and as easy to have illusions of our own generation. We got rid of imps and demons but we pushed them into the subconscious and called them by different names.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Meanings of Disenchantment: Sociological Condition Vs
    Philosophy & Th eology 17, 1 & 2 51 TWO MEANINGS OF DISENCHANTMENT: SOCIOLOGICAL CONDITION VS. PHILOSOPHICAL ACT— REASSESSING MAX WEBER’S THESIS OF THE DISENCHANTMENT OF THE WORLD Jeffrey E. Green Harvard University Abstract Although the primary meaning of Max Weber’s concept of dis- enchantment is as a sociological condition (the retreat of magic and myth from social life through processes of secularization and rationalization), as Weber himself makes clear in his address, “Sci- ence as a Vocation,” disenchantment can also be a philosophical act: an unusual form of moral discourse that derives new ethical direction out of the very untenability of a previously robust moral tradition. The philosophical variant of disenchantment is significant both because it contradicts numerous elements of the sociological version and because it suggests there are forms of cognition unique to moral philosophy (insofar as the derivation of a moral teaching from the very absence of one is foreign to both a religious and a scientific mindset). “Que sommes-nous donc sans le secours de ce qui n’existe pas?” —Paul Valéry For Anthony Kronman According to the biographical account of Max Weber written by his wife, the most fundamental animating concern underlying Weber’s vast body of research was the following dynamic: “He was moved, 52 Green: Two Meanings of Disenchantment above all, by the fact that on its earthly course an idea always and everywhere operates in opposition to its original meaning and thereby destroys itself” (Weber 1975, 337).1 This dialectic between an idea’s intended meaning and the effective truth of it actual implementation can be found in a variety of places within the Weberian corpus.
    [Show full text]
  • Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism 1St Edition Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    PROTESTANT ETHIC AND THE SPIRIT OF CAPITALISM 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Max Weber | 9780024248602 | | | | | Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism 1st edition PDF Book Detailed explanations, analysis, and citation info for every important quote on LitCharts. Zur Geschichte der Handelsgesellschaften im Mittelalter. Goodreads is the world's largest site for readers with over 50 million reviews. To view the craft as an end in itself, or as a "calling" would serve this need well. Interviewed Guest. Since this is true, then the rise of capitalism cannot be attributed to Adam Smith , the Protestant Reformation, etc. Religious Affiliation and Social Stratification 2. REL Soc. Distinction Pierre Bourdieu. Peter Ghosh at the University of Oxford. It is well known that the factory has taken its skilled labour to a large extent from young men in the handicrafts; but this is much more true of Protestant than of Catholic journeymen. With his contemporary, the French sociologist Emile Durkheimthey seem not to have known each other's workhe created modern sociology. The Catholics of France are, in their lower ranks, greatly interested in the enjoyment of life, in the upper directly hostile to religion. The results were supported even under a concentric diffusion model of Protestantism using distance from Wittenberg as a model. LSE Impact Blog. Designing Social Inquiry. When he discussed it in the Protestant Ethic , he used Lutheranism as the chief example of the unio mystica that contrasted sharply with the ascetic posture. In , the International Sociological Association listed this work as the fourth most important sociological book of the 20th century.
    [Show full text]
  • Weber's Science As a Vocation
    JCS0010.1177/1468795X19851408Journal of Classical SociologyShapin 851408research-article2019 Article Journal of Classical Sociology 1 –18 Weber’s Science as a © The Author(s) 2019 Article reuse guidelines: Vocation: A moment in the sagepub.com/journals-permissions https://doi.org/10.1177/1468795X19851408DOI: 10.1177/1468795X19851408 history of “is” and “ought” journals.sagepub.com/home/jcs Steven Shapin Harvard University, USA Abstract This essay situates Weber’s 1917 lecture Science as a Vocation in relevant historical contexts. The first context is thought about the changing nature of the scientific role and its place in institutions of higher education, and attention is drawn to broadly similar sentiments expressed by Thorstein Veblen. The second context is that of scientific naturalism and materialism and related sentiments about the “conflicts” between natural science and religion. Finally, there is the context of Weber’s lecture as a performance played out before a specific academic audience at the University of Munich, and the essay suggests the pertinence of that performance to an appreciation of the lecture’s meaning. Keywords Max Weber, vocation, science, Thorstein Veblen, scientific naturalism, scientific materialism Science as a vocation: Its past and present Here are several things typical of modern academic performances, whether written or oral. First, there is a display of efforts to get the facts right, to show that matters are indeed as they are said to be. Second, there is an expectation that at least some of those facts are, to a degree, novel, non-obvious, worth pointing out, and that the interpretations or explanations in which the facts are enlisted are plausible, similarly novel, and meriting consideration.
    [Show full text]
  • Science As a Vocation, Philosophy As a Religion
    Flashback: Max Weber’s “Science as a Vocation” Sociologica. V.12 N.1 (2018) Edited by Paul du Gay and José Ossandón ISSN 1971-8853 https://doi.org/10.6092/issn.1971-8853/8436 https://sociologica.unibo.it/ Science as a Vocation, Philosophy as a Religion Ian Hunter Published: July 26, 2018 Abstract When Max Weber delivered his “Science as a Vocation” lecture in 1917, it was to an audience of students facing war and political conflict, and shaped by its membership of activist youth groups whose ideologies were informed by left-Hegelianism. Resisting the clamor for a political message that would light the path to a progressive future, Weber told the students that such philosophical prophecy betrayed the office of the scholar. This consisted in transmitting the “value free” methods that characterized empirical fields, and the ethical disciplines that students had to undergo in order to master these methods. The paper argues that when the Frankfurt School rejected Weber’s approach it did so on the basis of a critique that amounted to a cultural-political attack grounded in the left-Hegelianism that he had repudiated. Keywords: Weber; Frankfurt School; scholarship; ethics; Hegelianism. Ian Hunter: Institute for Advanced Studies in the Humanities, University of Queensland (Australia) [email protected]; https://iash.uq.edu.au/profile/118/emeritus-professor-ian-hunter-faha Ian Hunter is an emeritus professor in the Institute for Advanced Studies in the Humanities, University of Queens- land. He is the author of a number of studies in the history of philosophical, political, and religious thought, including Rival Enlightenments: Civil and Metaphysical Philosophy in Early Modern Germany (Cambridge University Press, 2001), and The Secularization of the Confessional State (Cambridge University Press, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Afterword on Social Epistemology's Special Issue on 100 Years of Max Weber's 'Science As a Vocation' Mark Erickson
    http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 Afterword on Social Epistemology’s Special Issue on 100 Years of Max Weber’s ‘Science as a Vocation’ Mark Erickson, University of Brighton, [email protected] –––––––––––––––––– Erickson, Mark. 2020. “Afterword on Social Epistemology’s Special Issue on 100 Years of Max Weber’s ‘Science as a Vocation’.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 9 (3): 18-24. https://wp.me/p1Bfg0-4T1. 9 (3): 18-24. 2020. https://wp.me/p1Bfg0-4T1 In his scientific work [Max Weber] always remained dedicated to purely theoretical, that is, strictly conceptual, work. In this respect he was a shining example for all who are engaged in science, and so he will remain. On the other hand, it cannot be denied that Weber occasionally expressed his view on the vocation of science in a very abrupt manner that provoked contradiction. This is particularly true of his lecture, ‘Science as a Vocation’, which he delivered a year before his death to students in Munich and subsequently published in pamphlet form. As this talk can indeed give rise to misunderstandings, it is worth considering in some detail —Heinrich Rickert ([1920] 1989, 80). Max Weber’s ‘Science as a Vocation’ caused considerable controversy in the early 1920s across German academe. Significant critics weighed in on all sides including Ernst Curtius, a leading philologist, philosopher Heinrich Rickert (a close personal friend of the Webers), Arthur Salz, a leading political economist, Ernst Troeltsch, a member of the Bavarian parliament, and phenomenologist Max Scheler all of whom wrote extended articles—and in Erich von Kahler’s case an entire book Der Beruf der Wissenschaft [The Vocation of Science] (Berlin: Bondi 1920)—addressing the issues raised by the lecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Sociology As a Vocation 1 MICHAEL BURAWOY University of California-Berkeley [email protected]
    Ó American Sociological Association 2016 DOI: 10.1177/0094306116653958 http://cs.sagepub.com FEATURED ESSAY Sociology as a Vocation 1 MICHAEL BURAWOY University of California-Berkeley [email protected] What does it mean to live for sociology, two spheres that must be kept apart. Weber today? In attempting to answer this question failed to grasp sociology’s place between I return to Max Weber’s famous lectures science and politics for two reasons: first, delivered toward the end of his life—one sociology as a discipline was still embryonic on science as a vocation and the other on pol- and pre-professional. It needed to be safe- itics as a vocation. He presented ‘‘Science as guarded from politics. Second, he had not a Vocation’’ in November 1917 toward the developed a coherent view of civil society end of World War I and the more pessimistic populated by institutions that could ground ‘‘Politics as a Vocation’’ in January 1919 a standpoint between science and politics.3 after Germany’s defeat.2 The essays them- Yet, and here is the paradox, his concep- selves exemplify Weber’s methodology— tion of sociology as an interpretive under- interpreting social action within the external standing of value-oriented social action calls conditions that shape it. Weber not only for its own value standpoint since sociology explicates the meaning of ‘‘vocation’’— cannot be its own exception. As a form of what it means to ‘‘live for’’ as well to ‘‘live social action it too must be impelled by value off’’ science and politics—but situates their commitments.
    [Show full text]
  • Max Weber and the Moral Dimensions of Politics As a Vocation
    Max Weber and the Moral Dimensions of Politics as a Vocation Genevieve Brassard Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master’s degree in Philosophy School of Philosophy Faculty of Arts University of Ottawa © Genevieve Brassard, Ottawa, Canada, 2012 ABSTRACT Weber’s discussion of ethics in his famous lecture (and then essay) Politics as a Vocation (1919) clearly indicates that two possible ethical stances, the ethic of conviction and the ethic of responsibility, are rooted in ‘distinct and irreconcilably opposed principles’. Throughout Politics as a Vocation, it is the ethic of responsibility that appears to be endorsed by Weber as suited for political life. Yet, Weber concludes his essay by claiming that a combined ethic is ideal for a political vocation. This makes Weber’s position regarding the ideal ethical stance for a man who has a ‘true political calling’ appear contradictory: the ethics are opposites but somehow to be combined. Commentators have mostly concluded that, for Weber, the ethic of responsibility is the ideal ethic for politics. That appears further in accord with the fact that a key concern of the speech in its historical context was to warn political students of the dangers associated with an ethic of conviction. Weber, as a realist, was especially critical of a stance that disregarded the corrupted nature of the world, which the ethic of responsibility alone seems to accept. Politicians with single-minded convictions were responsible for Germany’s political stalemate, supporting the fact that the ethic of conviction should not be deemed acceptable in politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Max Weber, “Science As a Vocation” 'Wissenschaft Als Beruf,' from Gesammlte Aufsaetze Zur Wissenschaftslehre (Tubingen, 1922), Pp
    Max Weber, “Science as a Vocation” 'Wissenschaft als Beruf,' from Gesammlte Aufsaetze zur Wissenschaftslehre (Tubingen, 1922), pp. 524‐55. Originally delivered as a speech at Munich University, 1918. Published in 1919 by Duncker & Humblodt, Munich. You wish me to speak about 'Science as a Vocation.' Now, we political economists have a pedantic custom, which I should like to follow, of always beginning with the external conditions. In this case, we begin with the question: What are the conditions of science as a vocation in the material sense of the term? Today this question means, practically and essentially: What are the prospects of a graduate student who is resolved to dedicate himself professionally to science in university life? In order to understand the peculiarity of German conditions it is expedient to proceed by comparison and to realize the conditions abroad. In this respect, the United States stands in the sharpest contrast with Germany, so we shall focus upon that country. Everybody knows that in Germany the career of the young man who is dedicated to science normally begins with the position of Privatdozent. After having conversed with and received the consent of the respective specialists, he takes up residence on the basis of a book and, usually, a rather formal examination before the faculty of the university. Then he gives a course of lectures without receiving any salary other than the lecture fees of his students. It is up to him to determine, within his venia legendi, the topics upon which he lectures. In the United States the academic career usually begins in quite a different manner, namely, by employment as an 'assistant.' This is similar to the great institutes of the natural science and medical faculties in Germany, where usually only a fraction of the assistants try to habilitate themselves as Privatdozenten and often only later in their career.
    [Show full text]
  • Max Weber's Types of Rationality: Cornerstones for the Analysis of Rationalization Processes in History
    Max Weber's Types of Rationality: Cornerstones for the Analysis of Rationalization Processes in History Author(s): Stephen Kalberg Source: The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 85, No. 5 (Mar., 1980), pp. 1145-1179 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2778894 Accessed: 15/12/2010 10:12 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Journal of Sociology. http://www.jstor.org Max Weber'sTypes of Rationality:Cornerstones forthe Analysisof RationalizationProcesses in History' StephenKalberg UniversitdtTiubingen Rationalityhas been recognizedas perhaps the major theme in Max Weber's oeuvre.
    [Show full text]