Full Thesis FINISHED 4-20-09

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Full Thesis FINISHED 4-20-09 BEING IN PLACE: ON UNITY AND BODY IN ATISTOTLE A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Robert Samuel Leib May, 2009 i Thesis written by Robert Samuel Leib B.A., Mount St. Mary’s University, 2005 M.A., St. John’s College, Annapolis, 2007 M.A., Kent State University, 2009 Approved by _______________Gina Zavota_____________, Advisor _______________Polycarp Ikuenobe________, Acting Chair, Department of Philosophy _______________Timothy Moerland________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS…………………………………………………………...iv INTRODUCTION……………………………………………..…………………….1 Chapter I. Context...………...........................................................................................8 1. The Physics: Nature and Change…………………………………..8 2. The Task of the Physicist………………………………………….16 3. Place and Things…………………………………………………..19 4. The Boat Puzzle……………………………………………………23 II. Benjamin Morison’s On Location...............................................................33 1. Kinds of Containment……………………………………………...33 2. The Maximal Surrounder……………...…………………………..37 3. Problems with Morison’s Interpretation…………………………...41 4. Place is Not Location…………………...…….……………………45 III. Unity and Body..........................................................................................54 1. Is the Universe a Body?...................................................................54 2. Oneness, Unity, and Parts………………………..………………..61 3. Heaps, Wholes, and Physical Unity……………...………………..67 4. Definitional Unity………………………………...…………….....75 5. Ontological Unity…………………………………..……………..80 6. The Universe is Not a Body………………………...……………..86 IV. Place...........................................................................................................90 1. Telos and Eidos………………………………………..…………..90 2. The Forms of the Elements……………………………..….………94 3. Necessity and Function…………………………………...………106 4. Place and Actuality………………………………………...……...113 5. Vessels…………………………………………………….……...117 6. Answering the Boat Puzzle………………………………….……123 WORKS CITED………………………………………………….…………………129 iii Acknowledgments I would most of all like to thank Amber for her support and understanding during the time in which I carried this project around with me like a great weight. She, more than anyone, shared that weight with me, and I love her for that. I would also like to thank my advisor, Gina Zavota, for her support and guidance during the process, but perhaps, even more, for the freedom she granted me to follow my lines of thought to their conclusions. iv Introduction 1. Motivation My motivation for a study of Aristotle’s Physics can be summed up nicely by a passage from Edward Schiappa’s work, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric. The passage occurs at the point where he is attempting to parse out the various viewpoints from which contemporary scholars can approach the ancient Greek worldview through a study of their texts. Concerning the assertion made by certain scholars that the fifth-century Sophists’ primary concern was an understanding and dissemination of ‘rhetoric,’ Schiappa says: Such interpretations of the Sophists are misleading because they assume that the status and function of rhetoric was as obvious and given in the fifth century as some might believe it is today. Not only is the conceptual creativity and intellectual breadth of the Sophists thereby missed or underestimated, but whatever picture of the Sophists is left is prejudiced by pejorative preconceptions concerning the value of rhetoric.1 The term ‘rhetoric,’ he argues, was, in fact, a neologism coined by Plato to describe what he saw as the common concern among the teachers of speech who lived a generation before his time, with whose projects his own teacher, Socrates, took great issue.2 Thus, this retroactive history fails to give us a good understanding of what the Sophists 1 Edward Schiappa. Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric. 2nd ed., (Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 55. 2 Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, 45. 1 2 themselves may have seen themselves doing. Therefore, Schiappa argues, a more legitimate and ultimately more fruitful approach to understanding the character of this varied group of men would be to look at the way in which they tended to understand their work through the words of which they made the most use. He comes to the conclusion that, “[s]ophistic theorizing about [what we now call] rhetoric is best understood not as a collective answer to the question “What is rhetoric?” but as a process of asking questions about logos and the world.”3 Quoting Eric Havelock, Schiappa goes on to assert that, “[m]uch of early Greek philosophy so-called is a story not of systems of thought but of a search for a primary language in which any system could be expressed.”4 Contemporary scholars within the context of a much more highly developed and specialized dialogue about the nature of those matters that were first expressed in ancient Greece around the fifth and fourth centuries BCE are constantly in danger of projecting both the concepts and vocabulary of their contemporary discussion back onto these originary thinkers in a way that threatens to obscure the struggle those thinkers underwent to speak about the world in a new way. Despite the fact that it is widely accepted that these ancient Greek thinkers are the progenitors of many of the discussions we regard as residing at the very heart of philosophy today, accepting this lineage is no guarantee that we continue to speak their language, as it were. This is particularly true, I think, in the realm of so-called ‘natural philosophy,’ which, since the time of Aristotle, 3 Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, 71. Emphasis added. 4 Eric A. Havelock, “The Linguistic Task of the Presocratics,” Language and Thought in Early Greek Philosophy, ed. Kevin Robb (LaSalle, IL: Hegeler Institute, 1983), quoted in Edward Schiappa. Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric. 2nd ed., (Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 71. 3 has undergone a tremendous metamorphosis, becoming, if anything, the discipline of modern science. Thus, I believe that the contemporary scholar of Aristotle, even more so perhaps than the contemporary scholar of ancient rhetoric, can easily fall into the mindset of thinking of Aristotle’s Physics as a first attempt at a subject that has since outgrown him in very nearly every respect. Assuming the continuity of ‘natural philosophy’ from Aristotle down to the more recent centuries, however, might tend to give one the impression that Aristotle was, through his discussion of ‘nature,’ anticipating what has come to greater fruition, for instance, in the works of the fathers of modern science, such Francis Bacon and Isaac Newton. However, to view Aristotle, as some have, as a sort of proto-Newtonian has the effect of obscuring many of the assumptions under which Aristotle labored but which have since been disregarded under more modern systems of physics. Aristotle’s notion of change, for instance, is widely thought to refer really to locomotion. His notion of body is thought to refer to really mere extension, or magnitude. But perhaps what is most important for our purposes here, however, is that his notion of place has been frequently made subject to the language of Newtonian space as re-cast as really a concept of location. This need not be the case, however, and I will argue that reading the history of natural philosophy/science retroactively in this way is counter-productive for achieving an understanding of Aristotle’s philosophy in general. Through a careful study of his works on nature, and by refusing the temptation to equate Aristotle’s notions with their (distantly related) cousins within more modern scientific discourse, we can, I think, attain toward an understanding and recovery of the worldview 4 that Aristotle was encountering when he wrote that “it is owing to their wonder that men both now begin and at first began to philosophize” (Met. 982b11).5 In fact, it from this very passage near the beginning of Aristotle’s Metaphysics that we find, perhaps, the greatest affirmation of our assertion that there exists a merely distant relationship between how Aristotle viewed natural philosophy and the way in which those concerned with the natural world in more contemporary settings approach science. He continues several lines later, “a man who is puzzled and wonders thinks himself ignorant…therefore, since [the first philosophers] philosophized in order to escape from ignorance, evidently they were pursuing science in order to know, and not for any utilitarian end” (Met. 982b17). Simply put, Aristotle did not assume, as we do today, that our engagement with the natural world ought to be an essentially practical, or productive, endeavor. Rather, he saw the study of nature [φύσις] as theoretical in that it 5 Aristotle, “Metaphysica,” Trans. W.D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 682-926. See also AP I.3 (72b18). Met. hereafter. All passages from Met. are from this edition. A note about citing Aristotle: Because Aristotle has been published in so many editions over time, passages in Aristotle’s works are cited using their “Bekker numbers” rather than pages numbers. Bekker numbers remain constant throughout all editions and allow even scholars reading Aristotle in different languages to refer
Recommended publications
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(S): Brad Mcadon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol
    Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(s): Brad McAdon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol. 23, No. 1 (2004), pp. 21-39 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20176594 Accessed: 22/09/2010 21:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=taylorfrancis. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Rhetoric Review. http://www.jstor.org Brad McAdon University of Memphis Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the Phaedrus Contrary to a prevailing view within rhetoric and composition circles thatfinds a positive view of rhetoric in the Phaedrus, / contend that Plato mockingly de nounces rhetoric in the Phaedrus.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle-Rhetoric.Pdf
    Rhetoric Aristotle (Translated by W. Rhys Roberts) Book I 1 Rhetoric is the counterpart of Dialectic. Both alike are con- cerned with such things as come, more or less, within the general ken of all men and belong to no definite science. Accordingly all men make use, more or less, of both; for to a certain extent all men attempt to discuss statements and to maintain them, to defend themselves and to attack others. Ordinary people do this either at random or through practice and from acquired habit. Both ways being possible, the subject can plainly be handled systematically, for it is possible to inquire the reason why some speakers succeed through practice and others spontaneously; and every one will at once agree that such an inquiry is the function of an art. Now, the framers of the current treatises on rhetoric have cons- tructed but a small portion of that art. The modes of persuasion are the only true constituents of the art: everything else is me- rely accessory. These writers, however, say nothing about en- thymemes, which are the substance of rhetorical persuasion, but deal mainly with non-essentials. The arousing of prejudice, pity, anger, and similar emotions has nothing to do with the essential facts, but is merely a personal appeal to the man who is judging the case. Consequently if the rules for trials which are now laid down some states-especially in well-governed states-were applied everywhere, such people would have nothing to say. All men, no doubt, think that the laws should prescribe such rules, but some, as in the court of Areopagus, give practical effect to their thoughts 4 Aristotle and forbid talk about non-essentials.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetorical Being: a Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence Nathan Wagner Georgia State University
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Georgia State University Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University English Dissertations Department of English 4-30-2018 Rhetorical Being: A Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence Nathan Wagner Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss Recommended Citation Wagner, Nathan, "Rhetorical Being: A Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence." Dissertation, Georgia State University, 2018. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss/191 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of English at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in English Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RHETORICAL BEING: A METAPHYSICS OF FREEDOM AND ESSENCE by NATHAN R. WAGNER Under the Direction of Lynée Lewis Gaillet, PhD and Michael Harker, PhD ABSTRACT My dissertation examines the connection between rhetoric and being. I critique subject- oriented phenomenological assumptions that have perpetuated for decades within rhetorical theory and offer an alternative metaphysical methodology. I initially focus on Lloyd Bitzer and Richard Vatz’s debate about the rhetorical situation, which shaped accepted theories of subjectivity for decades to come. I offer an alternative model of the subject that is based on Augustine’s metaphysical model of being, and I focus on this notion of rhetorical being as a means of revealing knowledge as potentially, contextually already present through readings of Martin Heidegger and Emmanuel Levinas’s work. Augustine’s paradigm of the human being as perpetually free yet dependent on contextual surroundings for meaning, whether empirical or ephemeral, affords this study a framework through which to examine the subject within the rhetorical situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Rhetoric: the Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion
    Portland State University PDXScholar Young Historians Conference Young Historians Conference 2014 Apr 29th, 10:30 AM - 11:45 AM Aristotle's Rhetoric: The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion Claire Floyd-Lapp Grant High School Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/younghistorians Part of the Intellectual History Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Floyd-Lapp, Claire, "Aristotle's Rhetoric: The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion" (2014). Young Historians Conference. 12. https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/younghistorians/2014/oralpres/12 This Event is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Young Historians Conference by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Aristotle’s Rhetoric The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion Claire Floyd-Lapp 19 March 2014 PSU World History 105 Floyd-Lapp 1 A critical work in the field of persuasion—Aristotle essentially established the discipline—Rhetoric offers historians a framework by which to study the subject’s history. In his text, Aristotle argues what successful rhetoric entails, for what purposes rhetoric should be used, and what effective rhetoricians do. Aristotle’s Rhetoric speaks to the power of words and has remained relevant since its publication. Rhetoric offers writers and speakers a foundation from which to build their arguments. Although the perceived importance of persuasion has faded since Aristotle’s time, we still use words, and many scholars encourage the reclamation of rhetoric.
    [Show full text]
  • An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Phillip Keith St
    Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal Issue 20 Article 28 7-1-1999 An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Phillip Keith St. Cloud State University Sandra Z. Keith St. Cloud State University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj Part of the Intellectual History Commons, Logic and Foundations Commons, and the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Keith, Phillip and Keith, Sandra Z. (1999) "An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle)," Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal: Iss. 20, Article 28. Available at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj/vol1/iss20/28 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Claremont at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Philip Keith Sandy Z. Keith St. Cloud State University, MN Rhetoric, “the art of persuasion,” gets a bad rap among advantage for plaintiffs and accused, and as in courts workers in the mathematical sciences. This is unfor- today, the expression of pain and suffering would tunate, since although mathematics is concerned pri- carry a lot of weight. Not surprisingly, some entre- marily with the demonstration of formal truth, math- preneurial individuals offered lessons in speaking to ematicians do live in the world and need to concern get maximum benefit from these situations. The best themselves with persuading students, business agents known of these individuals are Corax and Tisias, to and others not on the mathematical team of the im- whom the art of rhetoric is traced by Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Emotion, London: Duckworth and New York: Barnes and Noble (Hard and Soft Cover) 1975, Reprinted with Epilogue 2002
    PUBLICATIONS Monograph: Aristotle on Emotion, London: Duckworth and New York: Barnes and Noble (hard and soft cover) 1975, reprinted with epilogue 2002 Text and Commentary: Quellen zur Ethik Theophrasts, Amsterdam: B. R. Gruener Verlag 1984 Text and Translation: Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, 2 vols. ed. and transl. with P. Huby, R. Sharples & D. Gutas, Leiden: E.J. Brill 1992 reprinted with corrections 1993 Commentary: Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, Commentary Volume 8: Sources on Rhetoric and Poetics, Leiden Brill 2005 Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, Commentary Volume 6a: Sources on Ethics, Leiden Brill, 2010 Text, Translation and Commentary: Theophrastus, On Sweat, in Theophrastus, On Sweat, On Dizziness and On Fatigue, ed. with R. Sharples and M. Sollenberger (Leiden 2003) 1-167 Collected Essays Theophrastean Studies, Stuttgart: Franz Schneider 2003 Aristotle’s Practical Side: on his psychology, ethics, politics and rhetoric, Leiden: Brill 2006 Edited Books: On Stoic and Peripatetic Ethics: The Work of Arius Didymus, New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1983 = RUSCH Vol. I Theophrastus of Eresus: On His Life and Works (ed. with A.A. Long and P.M. Huby), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1985 = RUSCH Vol. II Theophrastean Studies: On Natural Science, Physics and Metaphysics, Ethics, Religion and Rhetoric (ed. with R.W. Sharples), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1987 = RUSCH Vol. III Cicero's Knowledge of the Peripatos (ed. with P. Steinmetz), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1989 = RUSCH Vol. IV Theophrastus: His Psychological, Doxographical and Scientific Writings (ed. with D. Gutas), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1992 = RUSCH Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rhetoric of Commentary
    Glossator: Practice and Theory of the Commentary 3 (2010) THE RHETORIC OF COMMENTARY Carsten Madsen Since Antiquity, and through history, commentary and rhetoric seem to have had a complicated relationship. They are both discur- sive practices, but appear to have been thought of as based on very different approaches to the textual and rhetorical situations in which they take place. Commentary, taken as an exegetic and strictly logical activity, forms its statements on the basis of analytic arguments and rhetoric develops its arguments in the form of enthymemes. Conse- quently, the art of making commentaries is perceived as being based on a scientific method using deductive reasoning and functioning on the epistemic basis of formal logic. Rhetoric (which Aristotle calls “the antistrophe of dialectic”) seems to function primarily on the basis of informal logic and to deal with probability rather than scientific cer- tainty. Nevertheless, in various historic formations of knowledge and language, commentary and rhetoric have deeply influenced one another, but often in such a discrete or implicit manner that it has been difficult to appreciate the relationship between the two. Particu- larly in the Middle Ages, the ancient distribution of commentary and rhetoric seems to have shifted in this direction towards two different epistemological grounds in a definitive way that still exerts an influ- ence on the contemporary understanding of these discursive practic- es. As a result, it has been increasingly difficult to assess the relation between the two practices. Whereas commentary and rhetoric in An- tiquity were assigned very precise functions in the ancient complex of textual, pedagogical, juridical, and political practices, these same func- tions undergo fundamental and somewhat obscure changes when sys- tematized within the medieval trivium.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Theory of Actuality SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy Author : Bechler, Z
    title : Aristotle's Theory of Actuality SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy author : Bechler, Z. publisher : State University of New York Press isbn10 | asin : 0791422399 print isbn13 : 9780791422397 ebook isbn13 : 9780585046068 language : English subject Aristotle, Philosophy of nature. publication date : 1995 lcc : B491.N3B43 1995eb ddc : 113 subject : Aristotle, Philosophy of nature. cover Aristotle's Theory Of Actuality cover-0 SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy Anthony Preus, Editor cover-1 Aristotle's Theory OF Actuality Zev Bechler State University of New York Press cover-2 Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 1995 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, State University Plaza, Albany, N.Y., 12246 Production by Diane Ganeles Marketing by Fran Keneston Composition by Kelby Bowers, Compublishing, Cincinnati, Ohio Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Bechler, Z. Aristotle's theory of actuality / Zev Bechler. p. cm.(SUNY series in ancient Greek philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-7914-2239-9 (alk. paper).ISBN 0-7914-2240-2 (pbk.: alk. paper) 1. Aristotle. 2. Philosophy of nature. I. Title. II. Series. B491.N3B42 1995 185dc20 94-1045 CIP 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 cover-3 To Niza Dolav For her special friendship cover-4 Contents Acknowledgments xi Introduction: The Idea of Anti-Informationism 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Preliminary Reflections on the Rhetoric of Aristotle's Rhetoric1
    [Expositions 2.2 (2008) 163–188] Expositions (print) ISSN 1747-5368 doi:10.1558/expo.v2i2.163 Expositions (online) ISSN 1747-5376 Preliminary Reflections on the Rhetoric of Aristotle’s Rhetoric1 BRYAN-Paul FROST Department of Political Science University of Louisiana at Lafayette Perhaps the first question anyone would ask when reading a book whose theme is rhetoric is the following: What sort of rhetoric is the author going to employ in this work? To rephrase this in somewhat more cynical terms: Where, when, and how is the author going to attempt to pull the wool over my eyes? No serious author can be unaware that his readers will likely raise this question, especially when the author under consideration is universally acknowledged to have written the foundational work on the subject: Aristo- tle’s Rhetoric. In the words of Alan G. Gross and Arthur E. Walzer (2000, ix), “Whitehead’s observation that the history of philosophy is one long footnote to Plato can for us be transferred to the Rhetoric: All subsequent rhetorical theory is but a series of responses to issues raised by that central work.”2 Giv- en the obviousness of this question, one would expect that the scholar who wished to investigate this topic would have to wade through a veritable sea of secondary literature in order to set one’s bearings. But this is surprisingly not the case, at least in political science. Although there has been a sort of “mini- Renaissance” of the Rhetoric in the last decade or so,3 the book—let alone this question—has largely been ignored by contemporary
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography(Islamic Rhetoric)
    James Comas Department of English Middle Tennessee State University Last Updated: 13 May 2011 MEDIEVAL ARABIC-ISLAMIC RHETORIC & POETICS: SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF WORK IN ENGLISH This bibliography is not the product of an expert in the area of Arabic-Islamic rhetoric and poetics but, rather, the work of a teacher of the history of rhetoric who discovered a need for a more convenient, updated source of information for his students. The bibliography is organized into five sub-areas: (I) a section of general studies, (II-IV) a section for each of the three main figures (Alfarabi, Avicenna, Averroës), and (V) a section of studies on historiography and influence. I. General Studies Books Black, Deborah L. Logic and Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics in Medieval Arabic Philosophy. Vol. Islamic philosophy and theology, v. 7, Leiden ; New York: E.J. Brill, 1990. Kemal, Salim. The Philosophical Poetics of Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroës: The Aristotelian Reception. London: Routledge, 2003. Menocal, Maria Rosa. The Arabic Role in Medieval Literary History: A Forgotten Heritage. 1987. Reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004. Ouyang, Wen-chin. Literary Criticism in Medieval Arabic-Islamic Culture: The Making of a Tradition. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997. Vagelpohl, Uwe. Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the East: The Syriac and Arabic Translation and Commentary Tradition. Vol. 76, Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Science. Leiden: Brill, 2008. Articles & Chapters Badawi, M. M. “The Function of Rhetoric in Medieval Arabic Poetry: Abū Tammām’s Ode on Amorium.” Journal of Arabic Literature 9 (1978): 43-56. Bonebakker, S. A. “Aspects of the History of Literary Rhetoric and Poetics in Arabic Literature.” Viator: Medieval and Renaissance Studies 1 (1970): 75-95.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias, Polus, and Socrates on Rhetoric in Plato's Gorgias
    Volume 2004/1 LCMND e-Journal 1 LCMND e-Journal Volume 2004/1 ________________________________________________________________________ Gorgias, Polus, and Socrates on Rhetoric in Plato’s Gorgias by Daniel N. Erickson University of North Dakota, Grand Forks, ND _____________________________________________________________________________________ Introduction Rhetoric was an important part of Greco-Roman education, for it enabled politicians and others who spoke in public to persuade their audiences in an efficient and effective manner. However, there was (and still is) a danger associated with this art because, like any powerful tool, it can be misused. Just as a virtuous person can employ it to accomplish good, so can an evil one use it to do the opposite. The nature of rhetoric was of interest to Plato, and he wrote about it in the Gorgias. The focus of this paper is on what Gorgias, Polus, and Socrates say about the subject in this dialogue and the insights concerning its essence and proper use that can be gained therefrom. The Gorgias Dodds states that the Gorgias is presented as a drama with five actors (6), but due to the constraints of space, only the three mentioned above will be considered in this article. The main topic of conversation between Gorgias and Socrates is the definition of rhetoric. In the dialog between Polus (a follower of Gorgias) and Socrates, the emphasis is on how it should be used. Socrates masterfully leads the discussions through a series of questions and answers, termed “dialectic,” to help all of the interlocutors understand the subject better. Nothing seems to fluster him, and even when the impatient Polus becomes agitated, he maintains his composure and keeps the discussion on track.
    [Show full text]