Pronouns in Nanosyntax a Typological Study of the Containment Structure of Pronominals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pronouns in Nanosyntax a Typological Study of the Containment Structure of Pronominals Pronouns in Nanosyntax A typological study of the containment structure of pronominals *Name* *Student number* rMA Linguistics Universiteit van Amsterdam 24-06-2015 Acknowledgements This paper is the result of my Research Project Linguistics, the final part of my Research Master Linguistics at the University of Amsterdam. In following this rMA, I had the opportunity to study the fields that I am interested in the most: linguistic theory and typology. These two fields are fused in this research project, that was sometimes challenging but more often fun to work on. I would like to thank all my teachers and fellow students, in particular my co-students at the rMA, for the educational and fun experience this rMA has been. In particular, I want to express my gratitude to two of my teachers: Eva van Lier and Jan Don. I would like to thank Eva van Lier, for introducing me to the field of typology and for being an inspirational teacher. Besides that, I am grateful for her comments on earlier versions of this paper which made me evaluate my own work critically. I am most grateful to Jan Don, for making me realise that linguistics is the most interesting field of study, for his valuable lessons about linguistics and academic research, and for his faith in my capacities. Above all, I want to thank him for being the most inspirational, encouraging and helpful supervisor of this thesis project that a student could wish for. i Abbreviations 1 1st person 2 2nd person 3 3rd person ABS absolutive ACC accusative ALIEN alienable possession C common gender COM comitative D dual DAT dative DEM demonstrative DTLZ determinalizer ERG ergative EXCL exclusive F feminine gender GEN genitive INALIEN inalienable possession INCL inclusive INST instrumental M masculine gender MHG middle high grade polite form (used in Nepali) N neuter gender NMLZ nominalizer NOM nominative OBJ object OBL oblique P polite PL plural POSS possessive SBJ subject SG singular In the text, languages are referred to in the following template: 'Language (family; location; reference)' ii Pronouns in Nanosyntax A typological study of the containment structure of pronominals *Name* Abstract This paper describes a typological study of pronominal elements, including personal pronouns (I, me etc.), possessive pronouns (my etc.) and nominalized possessives (mine etc.). It aims to confirm a previous analysis of Dutch pronominals (Don et al. 2015) cross-linguistically. In this analysis, pronouns are complex forms that mirror an underlying containment structure. This structure is such that the accusative contains the nominative, the genitive contains the accusative, the possessive contains the genitive and the nominalized possessive contains the possessive. The results from the typological data argue indeed for an extension of this containment structure: it is not a structure underlying Dutch, but underlying all pronominals in human language. Besides this, it will be shown that this containment structure can be accounted for in a nanosyntactic framework (cf. Starke 2009; Caha 2009). Case studies of the implementation of the containment structure in nanosyntax are provided to strenghten this claim. Keywords: nanosyntax; containment hierarchy; typology; pronouns; possessives 1 Introduction Whilst studying the Dutch pronominal system, Don et al. (2015) observed patterns of formal (phonological) similarities between the different pronominal and possessive forms. In their analysis, they do not only study the standard possessive pronouns as in (1a), but also the 'nominalized possessives' in (1b-c). (1) a. Dit is mijn boek this is 1SG.POSS book 'This is my book.' b. Dit is de mijne this is the 1SG.POSS.NMLZ 'This is mine.' (Litt.: "This is the mine.") c. Dit is mijnes this is 1SG.POSS.NMLZ 'This is mine.' This formal correspondence is not acknowledged in grammatical descriptions of Dutch (cf. Broekhuis & Den Dikken 2012; Haeseryn et al. 1997), where personal and possessive pronouns 1 are treated as different paradigms. However, Don et al. (2015) claim that the personal and possessive pronouns (including the nominalized possessives) form in fact a single paradigm. They argue that the different pronominal and possessive forms can be analysed as complex forms that are built from each other. In their analysis there is an underlying 'containment structure' (cf. Bobaljik 2012), such that the accusative formally contains the nominative, the genitive contains the accusative, the possessive contains the genitive and the nominalized possessive contains the possessive, as in (2). (2) [[[[[nominative] accusative] genitive] possessive] nominalized possessive] Don et al. (2015) explain this containment structure by implementing their analysis of Dutch pronouns in the theory of nanosyntax (Starke 2009; Caha 2009). This leads to a nanosyntactic account of the Dutch pronominal system. However, previous work on both containment structures and nanosyntax has cross-linguistic implications, claiming explicitly that their generalizations hold across all human languages. This raises the question as to whether the analysis of Dutch pronouns by Don et al. (2015) can be confirmed cross-linguistically. This paper aims at answering this question. Based on data from a genetically balanced sample of fifty languages, it is tested whether the containment structure of pronouns applies cross-linguistically. As in the work by Don et al. (2015), this paper studies pronouns, possessives and nominalized possessives. I will argue that the analysis of Dutch can indeed be extended cross-linguistically, and that there is a universal containment structure underlying pronominals. Furthermore, I will show how this containment structure can be accounted for in a nanosyntactic framework. It is important to note that the claim of this paper is twofold. The first aim of this paper is to describe the containment structure of pronominal elements. Independent of a theoretical framework, the formal similarities between these elements can be established cross- linguistically. In itself this is an interesting and important typological conclusion. However, the second goal of this paper is to fit this statement in a theoretical framework. I will show that the cross-linguistic patterns follow naturally from a nanosyntactic account of the containment structure. This does not discard any other theoretical framework: that nanosyntax can account for the containment hierarchy does not mean that other frameworks cannot. In this paper, nanosyntax is shown to be a plausible framework to account for the data, but I explicitly do not want to claim that it is the compelling framework. This paper is structured as follows. The next section will describe the theoretical background, including the nanosyntactic framework and previous work on Dutch pronouns, and present the research question and hypotheses. Section 3 describes the methodology used and 2 section 4 gives a first description of the data. In section 5, the data are analysed with respect to the hypotheses and several case-studies are presented. Section 6 provides a conclusion and some points for discussion. 2 Theoretical Background Previous work on Dutch pronouns (Don et al. 2015) has shown that the patterns of formal similarity in Dutch can be accounted for in a nanosyntactic framework. This section will start with the observations on Dutch from Don et al. (2015), and will then show how these observations can be accounted for in a nanosyntactic analysis. This analysis leads to new research questions, hypothesis and predictions for a cross-linguistic study, that will be presented at the end of the section. 2.1 The empirical observation: Dutch pronouns The paradigm of Dutch personal and possessive pronouns, based on Broekhuis & Den Dikken (2012) and Weerman & Evers-Vermeul (2002), is given in table 1. A first observation that was made by Don et al. (2015) is that the paradigm contains many formal similarities between the different personal and possessive forms. For the first person singular for example, the object form mij 'me' and the possessive mijn 'my' are phonologically similar. All formal similarities in the paradigm are indicated by grey cells in the table. Nominative Accusative Possessive Nominalized Nominalized (Subject) (Object) possessive 1 possessive 2 ik mij mijn de mijne mijnes 1SG [ɪk] [mɛɪ] [mɛɪn] [də mɛɪnə] [mɛɪnəs] jij jou jouw de jouwe jouwes 2SG [jɛɪ] [jaʊ] [jaʊw] [də jaʊwə] [jaʊwəs] u u uw de uwe *uwes 2SG.P [y] [y] [yw] [də ywə] hij hem zijn de zijne zijnes 3SG.M [hɛɪ] [hɛm] [zɛɪn] [də zɛɪnə] [zɛɪnəs] zij haar haar de hare ?hares 3SG.F [zɛɪ] [ha:r] [ha:r] [də ha:rə] [ha:rəs] wij ons ons de onze onzes 1PL [wɛɪ] [ɔns] [ɔns] [də ɔnzə] [ɔnzəs] jullie jullie jullie *de jullie-e ?jullies 2PL [jʏli] [jʏli] [jʏli] [jʏlis] zij hun hun de hunne ?hunnes 3PL [zɛɪ] [hʏn] [hʏn] [də hʏnə] [hʏnəs] Table 1. Overview of personal and possessive pronouns in Dutch 3 The nominative pronoun is used in subject function. The accusative pronoun is used as direct object, indirect object and in prepositional phrases. Examples of this are shown in (3), and for the sake of completion, the examples of possessive constructions are repeated in (4). (3) a. Ik kus hem. 1SG.NOMkiss 3SG.ACC 'I kiss him.' b. Ik dans met hem. 1SG.NOMdance with 3SG.ACC 'I dance with him.' c. Ik geef hem een cadeau. 1SG.NOMgive 3SG.ACC a gift 'I give him a gift.' (4) a. Dit is mijn boek this is 1SG.POSS book 'This is my book.' b. Dit is de mijne this is the 1SG.POSS.NMLZ 'This is mine.' (Litt.: "This is the mine.") c. Dit is mijnes this is 1SG.POSS.NMLZ 'This is mine.' The examples in (4) show that a possessive pronoun in Dutch acts as determiner-element. It cannot be combined with other determiners (such as articles and demonstratives), precedes other prenominal elements and is always interpreted as definite (Weerman & Evers-Vermeul 2002: 313). The possessive pronoun can be nominalized with two different strategies in Dutch.
Recommended publications
  • Root and Semi-Phrasal Compounds: a Syntactic Approach Dimitrios Ntelitheos & Katya Pertsova*
    2019. Proc Ling Soc Amer 4. 30:1-14. https://doi.org/10.3765/plsa.v4i1.4530 Root and semi-phrasal compounds: A syntactic approach Dimitrios Ntelitheos & Katya Pertsova* Abstract. We present a syntactic account of the derivation of two types of attributive nominal compounds in Spanish, Russian and Greek. These include right-headed “root” compounds, which exhibit more “word”-like properties and single stress domains, and left-headed “semi-phrasal” compounds with more phrasal properties and independent stress domains for the two compound members. We propose that both compound structures are formed on a small clause predicate phrase, with their different properties derived from the merger of the predicate member of the small clause as a root or as a larger nominal unit with additional functional projections. The proposed structures provide an explanation of observed lexical integrity effects, as well as specific predictions of patterns of compound formation crosslinguistically. Keywords. morpho-syntax; compounds; Distributed Morphology; lexical integrity; predicate inversion; small clauses 1. Introduction. A hotly debated issue is to what extent morphological principles are independ- ent from the syntactic ones. There is no agreement on how and why differences between “words,” “phrases,” and other units proposed to exist in-between these two categories arise. Syn- tactic approaches to word-formation such as Distributed Morphology (Halle & Marantz 1993, Marantz 1997 and related work), antisymmetry (Kayne 1994, Koopman and Szabolcsi 2000) and more recently nanosyntax (Starke 2009) derive morphosyntactic properties of different units from the derivational path of their formation. For instance, Marantz (2001) proposes a difference between units created via combinations of functional heads with roots vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – a Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1
    Thomas Groß Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – A Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1 Abstract The Modern Hebrew (MH) desiderative construction must obey four conditions: 1. A subordinate clause headed by the clitic še= ‘that’ must be present. 2. The verb in the subordinate clause must be marked with future tense. 3. The grammatical properties genus, number, and person tend to be specified, i.e. if the future tense affix is underspecified, material tends to appear that aids specification, if contextual recovery is unavailable. 4. The units of form that make up the constructional meaning of the desiderative must qualify as a catena. A catena is a dependency-based unit of form, the parts of which are immediately continuous in the vertical dimension. The description of the individual parts of the desiderative must address trans-, pre-, and suffixes, and cliticization. Catena-based morphology is representational, monostratal, dependency-, construction-, and piece-based. 1. Purpose, means and claims The main purpose of this paper is to analyze the Hebrew desiderative construction. This construction is linguistically interesting and challenging for a number of reasons. 1. It is a periphrastic construction, with fairly transparent compositionality. 2. It is transclausal, i.e. some parts of the construction reside in the main clause, and others in the subordinated clause. The complementizer is also part of the construction. 3. The construction consists of more than one word, but it does not qualify as a constituent. Rather the construction cuts into words. 4. Two theoretically 1 I want to thank Outi Bat-El (Tel Aviv University) and three anonymous reviewers for their help and advice.
    [Show full text]
  • Ch1 LBEL Preprint
    Zurich Open Repository and Archive University of Zurich Main Library Strickhofstrasse 39 CH-8057 Zurich www.zora.uzh.ch Year: 2018 Nanosyntax: the basics Baunaz, Lena ; Lander, Eric Abstract: This chapter offers a thorough introduction to nanosyntactic theory, a development ofthe cartographic program in generative grammar. It discusses the foundations on which nanosyntax was conceived, such as the “one feature–one head” maxim and the universal functional sequence (fseq). It also provides a brief comparison of theoretical and terminological issues in nanosyntax vs. the competing framework of Distributed Morphology. It is seen that the syntactic component according to nanosyn- tax unifies aspects of (what are traditionally called) syntax, morphology, and formal semantics. Thisis reflected in the tools used to probe linguistic structure in the nanosyntactic approach, such asmorpholog- ical decomposition, syncretism, and containment. The chapter also discusses the technical details of the syntax–lexicon relation, detailing the matching or spellout process and Starke’s view of spellout-driven movement. This chapter is meant to provide readers with the necessary background to understand and navigate the rest of the chapters in this volume. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190876746.003.0001 Posted at the Zurich Open Repository and Archive, University of Zurich ZORA URL: https://doi.org/10.5167/uzh-167406 Book Section Accepted Version Originally published at: Baunaz, Lena; Lander, Eric (2018). Nanosyntax: the basics. In: Baunaz, Lena; De Clercq, Karen; Haegeman, Liliane; Lander, Eric. Exploring Nanosyntax. New York: Oxford University Press, 3-56. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190876746.003.0001 15 <Chapter 1 Nanosyntax: The Basics§> Lena Baunaz and Eric Lander Nanosyntax (Caha 2009; Starke 2009, 2011ab) is a generative approach to the study of language that is in line with the major tenets of the Principles and Parameters framework of Chomsky (1981, 1986).
    [Show full text]
  • THE LEXICALIST HYPOTHESIS: BOTH WRONG and SUPERFLUOUS Benjamin Bruening
    THE LEXICALIST HYPOTHESIS: BOTH WRONG AND SUPERFLUOUS Benjamin Bruening University of Delaware The lexicalist hypothesis , which says that the component of grammar that produces words is distinct and strictly separate from the component that produces phrases, is both wrong and super - fluous. It is wrong because (i) there are numerous instances where phrasal syntax feeds word for - mation; (ii) there are cases where phrasal syntax can access subword parts; and (iii) claims that word formation and phrasal syntax obey different principles are not correct. The lexicalist hypoth - esis is superfluous because where there are facts that it is supposed to account for, those facts have independent explanations. The model of grammar that we are led to is then the most parsi - monious one: there is only one combinatorial component of grammar that puts together both words and phrases.* Keywords : lexicalist hypothesis, word formation, phrasal syntax, subword units, parsimony, single grammatical component 1. Introduction . The lexicalist hypothesis , usually attributed to Chomsky (1970), is a foundational hypothesis in numerous current approaches to morphology and syntax, including head-driven phrase structure grammar (HPSG), lexical- functional grammar (LFG), simpler syntax (Culicover & Jackendoff 2005), vari - ous versions of the principles and parameters and minimalist models, and others. 1 The basic tenet of the lexicalist hypothesis is that the system of grammar that assembles words is separate from the system of grammar that assembles phrases out of words. The combinatorial system that produces words is supposed to use different principles from the system that produces phrases. Additionally, the word system is encapsulated from the phrasal system and interacts with it only in one direction, with the output of the word system providing the input to the phrasal system.
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on Huave Morpheme Ordering: Local Dislocation Or Generalized U20? ∗
    Chapter 1 A note on Huave Morpheme Ordering: Local Dislocation or Generalized U20? ∗ Hilda Koopman Version: August 28 2016. COMMENTS WELCOME. I will continue to work on these issues. To appear in: Gautam Sengupta, Shruti Sircar, Madhavi Gayathri Raman and Rahul Balusu, Per- spectives on the Architecture and Acquisition of Syntax: Essays in Honour of R. Amritavalli. (projected publication date: december 2016) 1.1 Introduction In the past few decades, different frameworks have emerged which claim that a single computational engine drives both syntactic and morphological composition, either to a large extent, as in Distributed Morphology (DM)), or entirely, as in frame- works based on antisymmetry (Kayne, 1994). Where morpheme order is concerned, Distributed Morphology (DM) attributes a major, but not exclusive, role to the syntax (see amongst others, Halle and Marantz (1993), Embick and Noyer (2007), Bobaljik (2012, 2015) and Harley (2012)). Mis- matches may arise between the output of the syntax and the actual morpheme order, Hilda Koopman UCLA, Department of Linguistics, 3125 Campbell Hall, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1543, e-mail: [email protected] ∗ This paper is dedicated to my friend Amrit: may our paths continue to cross in the future. I would like to thank Guglielmo Cinque, participants of my seminar on unifying syntax and mor- phology (UCLA winter 2016) for feedback and discussion, and Rolf Noyer and Yuni Kim for bringing Huave to bear on the theory, and their eagerness and openness to discuss and share their deep knowledge of the language. 1 2 Hilda Koopman in which case postsyntactic readjustment rules (Lowering, and Local Dislocation) apply to generate the observed linear orders.
    [Show full text]
  • Syntax and Morphology; a Single Computational Engine
    Syntax and Morphology; a Single Computational Engine Hilda Koopman [email protected] University of California, Los Angeles Paris EALING 2010 september 7 and september 8th Koopman Single computational engine 1 The atoms that Merge manipulates are not words but much tinier units. There is a single component for building structure, and that is syntax. There is no independent morphological component(derivational or inflectional or otherwise) Current theoretical understanding, and expectations Mandarin resultative compounds with further excursions into comparative syntax (serial verb constructions (Ewe (serial verbs) English Dutch resultatives) Koopman Single computational engine 2 Strings of verbs: Mandarin V V ’compounds’ resultative la kai ’pull open’ ; xiao si ’ laugh die’ =laugh someone to death tiao wu lit. jump dance’ ’dance’; tao lun lit: ask for-discuss =’ discuss’ V N (verb object compound) fang jia ’release-vacation’ =’have vacation’ Different distributional properties (Thompson, 1973) placement of LE (perfective aspect) position of the potential particle de or bu (NEG.POT) behavior under reduplication (’casual’ interpretation) V1V2res V1V2compound V N LE V1V2-LE V1V2 LE V LE N POT V1 de V2 V1*de V2 RED (V1V1 V2) V1V2-V1V2 V1 V1 N Koopman Single computational engine 3 A glimpse at Mandarin resultative V1 V2 ’compounds’ Very long tradition of study. (Thompson 1973, Yafeil Li 1990, A.Williams 2005 , Sybesma 1997, Cheng and Huang (1997), Cheng (1994), Zang (2007) Wang (2010) among many many others) V1 V2 resultatives: V1 and V2 get pronounced ’close’ to each other; (Why call these ’compounds’? ) Perfective LE follows V1 V2 (1) Ta la kai- le men He pull open- PERF door He pulled the door open object of V1 follows V2/LE.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous
    The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University of Delaware ([email protected]) draft, February 17, 2017; comments welcome Abstract The Lexicalist Hypothesis, which says that the component of grammar that produces words is distinct and strictly separate from the component that produces phrases, is both wrong and superfluous. It is wrong because (1) there are numerous instances where phrasal syntax feeds word formation; (2) there are cases where phrasal syntax can access sub-word parts; and (3) claims that word formation and phrasal syntax obey different principles are not correct. The Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous because where there are facts that are supposed to be accounted for by the Lexicalist Hypothesis, those facts have independent explanations. The model of grammar that we are led to is then the most parsimonious one: there is only one combinatorial component of grammar that puts together both words and phrases. 1 Introduction The Lexicalist Hypothesis, usually attributed to Chomsky 1970, is a foundational hypothesis in numerous current approaches to morphology and syntax, including Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), Lexical Func- tional Grammar (LFG), Simpler Syntax (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005), various versions of the Principles and Parameters and Minimalist models, and others.1 The basic tenet of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is that the system of grammar that assembles words is separate from the system of grammar that assembles phrases out of words. The combinatorial system that produces words is supposed to use different principles from the system that produces phrases. Additionally, the word system is encapsulated from the phrasal system and interacts with it only in one direction, with the output of the word system providing the input to the phrasal system.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lexical Category of Adjective
    DEPARTAMENT DE FILOLOGIA ANGLESA I DE GERMANÍSTICA The Lexical Category of Adjective: Challenging the Traditional Notion Treball de Fi de Grau/ BA dissertation Author: Víctor Quevedo Supervisor: Dr. Susagna Tubau Grau d’Estudis Anglesos June 2018 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisor Susagna Tubau for leading me throughout the whole TFG and helping me when I most needed it. I first became interested in the idea that adjectives may not exist as an independent lexical category when she explained it in an Advance English Syntax class, so I thank her as well for having introduced me to this topic months before doing this paper. Secondly, I thank my father, mother, and brother for all the patience they had and for the support they have given to me at every moment. Even though they are not really interested on adjectives, they always had a moment to ask me about the TFG and to cheer me up every I time I needed so. And last but not least, I would like to say thank you to Elise, who has made the distance less distant and has been one of my greatest supports, listening to me every time I learned something new about syntax, helping me when I had a problem, or just discussing anything about linguistics. Table of Contents ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................................... 1 1. INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................................................... 3 2. ADJECTIVES ...........................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Derivational Trapping and the Morphosyntax of Inflectionlessness
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2019 Derivational Trapping And The Morphosyntax Of Inflectionlessness Luke James Adamson University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Linguistics Commons Recommended Citation Adamson, Luke James, "Derivational Trapping And The Morphosyntax Of Inflectionlessness" (2019). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 3587. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3587 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3587 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Derivational Trapping And The Morphosyntax Of Inflectionlessness Abstract The broad objective of this dissertation is to advance our understanding of how grammatical operations are formulated in the postsyntactic module of the grammar. To that end, the dissertation examines the distribution of agreement morphemes, and especially the distribution of exceptionally inflectionless elements, whose lack of agreement morphology can affect other operations such as postsyntactic movement, in some cases interfering with these operations, yielding ungrammaticality. The dissertation pursues a serial rule-based approach within the Distributed Morphology (DM) framework (Halle and Marantz 1993; Embick and Noyer 2001, 2007; Arregi and Nevins 2012; Harley 2014; a.o.), focusing chiefly on postsyntactic operations that produce and refer to agreement morphology (‘node- sprouting’) and postsyntactic operations that displace heads onto neighboring elements. The key innovation of the current model is that postsyntactic operations distinguish between their triggering environments and the actual execution of a change. A theoretical consequence of making this distinction is that a derivation can crash when the conditions for application of an operation are satisfied but the change itself cannot be executed, yielding ungrammaticality.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Affixal Negation Is Syntactic
    WhyAffixalNegationIsSyntactic KarenDeClercqandGuidoVandenWyngaerd 1. The Problem The problem we want to address is that positive adjectives may be prefixed with un-, but negative ones cannot (Jespersen 1942; Zimmer 1964; Horn 2005). Negation of positive and negative adjectives alike is possible, though, with not. (1) a. unhappy b. *unsad c. not sad unfriendly *unhostile not hostile untrue *unfalse not false unkind *unrude not rude unhealthy *unsick not sick Existing accounts of this pattern, such as the ones in (2) and (3) below, assume that there exists some fundamental distinction between affixal and other types of negation. (2) “Negative affixes are not used with adjectival stems that have a negative value.” (Zimmer 1964:15) (3) “The stem to which a relatively nonproductive negative affix can attach tends to be an UNMARKED, WEAK POSITIVE scalar value.” (Horn 1989:286) These proposals (or empirical generalisations) are inadequate for two reasons. First, they are restricted to affixal negation (explaining (1c)), but we shall show that the pattern in (1) can be observed both with morphological and syntactic negation. Second, we believe that it is not a coincidence that negative markers are excluded with negative adjectives. The facts in (1) to us suggest the existence of a ban on double negation within a local domain, not only with respect to affixal negation, but with respect to all kinds of negative markers. We shall argue that they are to be accounted for in terms of the following constraint on double negation: (4) *hNeg, Negi The functional sequence must not contain two structurally adjacent Neg-features. It stands to reason that this ban itself is a particular instantiation of a more general restriction that can be formulated as follows: (5) *hX, Xi The functional sequence must not contain two structurally adjacent identical features.
    [Show full text]
  • Having Fun with Van – a Nanosyntactic Take on Syncretism
    Stellenbosch Papers in Linguistics Plus, Vol. 42, 2013, 243-261 doi: 10.5842/42-0-145 Having fun with van – a Nanosyntactic take on syncretism Erin Pretorius Department of General Linguistics, Stellenbosch University, South Africa E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Syncretism is the phenomenon where one (phonological) form is able to spell out more than one (grammatical) function. The P(repositional) element van (“from/of”) in Afrikaans represents an instance of syncretism: it is able to spell out many different functions including spatial, possessive and partitive functions. Any theoretical framework seeking to account for how form relates to function ought to provide an account of this phenomenon. Within the broad minimalist approach, Nanosyntax (NS) has yielded the most systematic and explicit accounts of syncretism (cf. e.g. Starke 2009; Caha 2007, 2009). This paper offers a nanosyntactic characterisation of the Afrikaans P element van, focusing specifically on its behaviour in Afrikaans partitive constructions and offering a tentative analysis to account for the seemingly irregular behaviour displayed by van in these constructions. The analysis is based on a modified syntactic decomposition of “the genitive zone” proposed by Caha (2009). The presence of an additional node, Specific (SPF), is argued for in the lowest layer of the structure that is encoded on the lexical entry for van. One merit of the proposed analysis is that it takes into account how van interacts with other word-level elements in the phrase. Keywords: partitive, pseudo-partitive, Afrikaans, syncretism, nanosyntax 1. Introduction Syncretism, in general terms, refers to the phenomenon where one phonological form is able to spell out more than one grammatical “meaning” or function.
    [Show full text]
  • The Spell-Out Algorithm and Lexicalization Patterns
    The spell-out algorithm and lexicalization patterns Slavic verbs and complementizers Bartosz Wiland language Open Slavic Linguistics 2 science press Open Slavic Linguistics Editors: Berit Gehrke, Denisa Lenertová, Roland Meyer, Radek Šimík & Luka Szucsich In this series: 1. Lenertová, Denisa, Roland Meyer, Radek Šimík & Luka Szucsich (Eds.). Advances in formal Slavic linguistics 2016. 2. Wiland, Bartosz. The spell-out algorithm and lexicalization patterns: Slavic verbs and complementizers. ISSN: 2627-8332 The spell-out algorithm and lexicalization patterns Slavic verbs and complementizers Bartosz Wiland language science press Wiland, Bartosz. 2019. The spell-out algorithm and lexicalization patterns: Slavic verbs and complementizers (Open Slavic Linguistics 2). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/242 © 2019, Bartosz Wiland Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-96110-160-3 (Digital) 978-3-96110-177-1 (Hardcover) ISSN: 2627-8332 DOI:10.5281/zenodo.2636394 Source code available from www.github.com/langsci/242 Collaborative reading: paperhive.org/documents/remote?type=langsci&id=242 Cover and concept of design: Ulrike Harbort Fonts: Linux Libertine, Libertinus Math, Arimo, DejaVu Sans Mono Typesetting software:Ǝ X LATEX Language Science Press Unter den Linden 6 10099 Berlin, Germany langsci-press.org Storage and cataloguing done by FU Berlin Dedicated to the memory of Morris Halle, who introduced me to the problems of Slavic morphology, some of which this book aims to resolve. Contents Acknowledgments v Abbreviations and symbols vii 1 Introduction 1 2 The spell-out mechanism in Nanosyntax 5 2.1 Introduction ............................
    [Show full text]