Conditional Probability Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Conditional Probability Theory Conditional Probability Theory Ioanid Rosu 1 Introduction Conditional probability theory is one of the most difficult parts of basic probability theory. The reason is that it is hard to come up with good intutitions for it. Just for fun, let me give the formal definition of conditional expectations. Start with a probability space (Ω; ;P ), with Ω the event space, a σ-algebra on Ω, and P a probability on , i.e., P is a positiveF real measure on (Ω; ) with PF(Ω) = 1. Let be a sub-σ-algebra of .F Let f be a random variable on Ω (whichF is -measurable, but notB necessarily -measurable).F Then the conditional expectation E(f ) ofFf given is a -measurable functionB g on Ω which satisfies jB B B g = E(f ) Z f dP = Z g dP B : (1) jB () B B 8 2 B Not very enlightening now, is it? I think that, unless you are a mathematical genius, the most reasonable intuition you can come up with by just looking at the definition is this: Let's assume f is a simple function, i.e., f is constant on some partition of Ω by -measurable sets. Since has a finer \resolution" than (there are more sets in ), conditionalF expectation of f givenF must be some way of forcingBf to be identified by someoneF who only \sees" . The way to doB that is by averaging out f on those smaller subsets of , and making it constantB on the larger subsets of . F Directly from the definitionB we can deduce two properties which are used a lot in practice: Notice that if f is already -measurable, we can take g = f in the above definition, • hence E f = f. In otherB words, -measurable functions are treated as constants by the operatorf jBg E . In particular,B if X is any ( -measurable) random variable, we deduce this important{·|Bg property about conditional expectations:F E fX = fE X f -measurable: (2) f j Bg f jBg 8 B Suppose X :Ω R is a -measurable random variable. Define E f X = E f X , • ! F 1f j g f jB g where = X is the σ-algebra generated by all sets of the form X− (B), with B a Borel set1 inBR. ThenB we have the following property: E f X = φ(X) with φ : R R measurable: (3) f j g ! Date: March 17,2003. 1 A Borel set on R is simply an element in the σ-algebra R generated by all open intervals in R. Equivalently, a Borel set can be obtained by taking a countable numberB of intersections, unions, and complements of open intervals. 1 To explain briefly why this is the case, let g = E f X , which according to the definition f j g of conditional expectation is X -measurable. But for a function g :Ω R to be X - measurable is the same as g Bbeing a composition of the form φ X, with! φ : R B R measurable. (It is trivial that g = φ X as functions; the fact◦ that φ is measurable! ◦ comes from the fact that X induces a one-to-one correspondence between X and R restricted to Im X R. B B ⊆ But enough about the definition of conditional expectations. I'm not a big fan of it, although this is what you have to use in order to prove formulas. Luckily, there is an easier way of interpreting conditional expectations, but it comes at the cost of losing some generality. Namely, if we restrict ourselves at the subclass of \square-integrable" random variables, we can come up with a nice geometric intuition. This is because the square-integrable functions form something called a Hilbert space, where one can do geometry in the usual way. We define the Hilbert space2 of square-integrable -measurable functions on Ω by H F (X; Y ) = E XY : (4) f g The great thing about Hilbert spaces is that the apparently innocuous inner product generates a lot of structure, to the extent that in a Hilbert space one can work smoothly with geometric concepts such as distance, projection, angles, etc. For example, the distance d(X; Y ) and the angle α(X; Y ) are defined as follows: 1 E XY 2 2 d(X; Y ) = E (X Y ) ; cos α(X; Y ) = f1 g 1 : (5) f − g E X2 2 E Y 2 2 f g f g Notice that if we restrict our attention at the subspace 0 = X EX = 0 of de-meaned random variables in , the formula for the cosine of theH anglef becomes2 H j g H cos α(X; Y ) = corr(X; Y ) X; Y 0; (6) 8 2 H where corr(X; Y ) denotes correlation between X and Y . Also, we say that X and Y are perpendicular, and write X Y , if cos α(X; Y ) = 0. Equivalently, ? X Y E XY = 0: (7) ? () f g What is then the projection of an element X on the subspace of all -measurable functions in ? It must be some element Y 2so H that (b Y ) (XHB Y ) forB all b in . But Y is alsoH in , so we can replace b by b+2Y H,B and deduce− that b? (X− Y ) for all b in HB. HB ? − HB This means that E b(X Y ) = 0 for all b in . In particular, take b = 1B, the indicator f − g HB function of some subset B . We then get E 1B(X Y ) = 0, which translates into 2 B f − g B X dP = B Y dP . The subset B was arbitrary, so it follows that Y satisfies our definition ofR conditionalR expectation of X with respect to B. In other words, Proj X = E X ; (8) HB f jBg where Proj X is the projection of X on . HB HB 2A real Hilbert space is a real vector space , endowed with an inner product ( ; ): R, so that (x; x) 0 with equality iff x = 0, and such thatH with the resulting metric is complete.· · TheH × metric H ! is defined by d(x;≥ y) = (x y; x y)1=2. For details see for example Rudin, \Real andH Complex Analysis". − − 2 One last subtle point here is about the existence of the projection of X on the closed subspace = (the fact that is closed is proved by some easy measure theory). The existenceL of theH projectionB Y = ProjL X is a standard fact in Hilbert space theory, and is proved as follows: First notice that L is a Hilbert space in its own right (easy). Then one can define the continuous linear functionalL Φ( ) = (X; ): R. According to the Riesz' representation theorem, there exists Y so· that Φ( )· = (L!Y; ) on . But this is equivalent to (X Y; b) = 0 for all b , which2 by L the definition· of projection· L means exactly that Y is the projection− of X on 2.L So the crucial step in this proof is Riesz' theorem, which only makes use of the fact that L is complete and is closed (and of course plays around with the inner product). H L By contrast, to see what we gained by reducing the generality from all measurable functions to the square-integrable ones (and thus entering the neat world of Hilbert spaces), let's see what is involved in the general existence proof for the conditional expectation g = E f in (1). f jBg First notice that the measure B µ(B) = B f dP is absolutely continuous with respect to P (that's easy). Then the hard part7! is provedR by Radon{Nikodym, namely that there exists g a -measurable function such that µ(B) = B g dP . But then, given our definition (1), g is exactlyB the conditional expectation of f givenR . The Radon{Nikodym theorem is one of the deepest theorems in measure theory, and its proofB is one of the most technical proofs I know, given such an elementary statement. I dare you to read the proof and remember it after just one day. This concludes our discussion about the geometric interpretation of the conditional expec- tation. Now we want to put it to use. 2 Formulas There are two basic formulas in conditional probability theory: the law of iterated expecta- tions (9), also called the ADAM formula, and the EVE formula (10)3. Let X be a -measurable random variable, and two sub-σ-algebras of . Then: F B0 ⊆ B F E X 0 = E E X 0 ; (9) f jB g f jBg j B V X = E V X + V E X : (10) f g f jBg f jBg Both of them have a nice geometric interpretation, which we now discuss. The law of iterated expectations (9) is quite simple. With our interpretation of conditional expectations, it says that projecting X on the smaller subspace gives the same result as 0 first projecting X on the larger subspace , and then takingH ProjB X and projecting it further on . This has a simple geometricHB proof if you draw theH pictureB (I learned it in 0 8'th grade asHB the theorem of the 3 perpendiculars). But, to be more rigorous, consider the decomposition of as an orthogonal sum, = ?. Notice that via this decomposition the first componentH of X is exactly the projectionH HB Proj⊕ HB X. Now also has an orthogonal decomposition, = . Then the projectionH ofB Proj XHBon the first component, 0 ? HB HB ⊕ HB0B HB , is Proj Proj X. We now look at the decomposition = ? ?, which 0 0 0 HB HB0 HB H HB ⊕ HB B ⊕ HB 3If you haven't figured it out yet, the reason these are called the ADAM and EVE formulas comes from the form of the EVE equation (10), which should perhaps be called the EVVE equation.
Recommended publications
  • Bayes and the Law
    Bayes and the Law Norman Fenton, Martin Neil and Daniel Berger [email protected] January 2016 This is a pre-publication version of the following article: Fenton N.E, Neil M, Berger D, “Bayes and the Law”, Annual Review of Statistics and Its Application, Volume 3, 2016, doi: 10.1146/annurev-statistics-041715-033428 Posted with permission from the Annual Review of Statistics and Its Application, Volume 3 (c) 2016 by Annual Reviews, http://www.annualreviews.org. Abstract Although the last forty years has seen considerable growth in the use of statistics in legal proceedings, it is primarily classical statistical methods rather than Bayesian methods that have been used. Yet the Bayesian approach avoids many of the problems of classical statistics and is also well suited to a broader range of problems. This paper reviews the potential and actual use of Bayes in the law and explains the main reasons for its lack of impact on legal practice. These include misconceptions by the legal community about Bayes’ theorem, over-reliance on the use of the likelihood ratio and the lack of adoption of modern computational methods. We argue that Bayesian Networks (BNs), which automatically produce the necessary Bayesian calculations, provide an opportunity to address most concerns about using Bayes in the law. Keywords: Bayes, Bayesian networks, statistics in court, legal arguments 1 1 Introduction The use of statistics in legal proceedings (both criminal and civil) has a long, but not terribly well distinguished, history that has been very well documented in (Finkelstein, 2009; Gastwirth, 2000; Kadane, 2008; Koehler, 1992; Vosk and Emery, 2014).
    [Show full text]
  • Estimating the Accuracy of Jury Verdicts
    Institute for Policy Research Northwestern University Working Paper Series WP-06-05 Estimating the Accuracy of Jury Verdicts Bruce D. Spencer Faculty Fellow, Institute for Policy Research Professor of Statistics Northwestern University Version date: April 17, 2006; rev. May 4, 2007 Forthcoming in Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 2040 Sheridan Rd. ! Evanston, IL 60208-4100 ! Tel: 847-491-3395 Fax: 847-491-9916 www.northwestern.edu/ipr, ! [email protected] Abstract Average accuracy of jury verdicts for a set of cases can be studied empirically and systematically even when the correct verdict cannot be known. The key is to obtain a second rating of the verdict, for example the judge’s, as in the recent study of criminal cases in the U.S. by the National Center for State Courts (NCSC). That study, like the famous Kalven-Zeisel study, showed only modest judge-jury agreement. Simple estimates of jury accuracy can be developed from the judge-jury agreement rate; the judge’s verdict is not taken as the gold standard. Although the estimates of accuracy are subject to error, under plausible conditions they tend to overestimate the average accuracy of jury verdicts. The jury verdict was estimated to be accurate in no more than 87% of the NCSC cases (which, however, should not be regarded as a representative sample with respect to jury accuracy). More refined estimates, including false conviction and false acquittal rates, are developed with models using stronger assumptions. For example, the conditional probability that the jury incorrectly convicts given that the defendant truly was not guilty (a “type I error”) was estimated at 0.25, with an estimated standard error (s.e.) of 0.07, the conditional probability that a jury incorrectly acquits given that the defendant truly was guilty (“type II error”) was estimated at 0.14 (s.e.
    [Show full text]
  • General Probability, II: Independence and Conditional Proba- Bility
    Math 408, Actuarial Statistics I A.J. Hildebrand General Probability, II: Independence and conditional proba- bility Definitions and properties 1. Independence: A and B are called independent if they satisfy the product formula P (A ∩ B) = P (A)P (B). 2. Conditional probability: The conditional probability of A given B is denoted by P (A|B) and defined by the formula P (A ∩ B) P (A|B) = , P (B) provided P (B) > 0. (If P (B) = 0, the conditional probability is not defined.) 3. Independence of complements: If A and B are independent, then so are A and B0, A0 and B, and A0 and B0. 4. Connection between independence and conditional probability: If the con- ditional probability P (A|B) is equal to the ordinary (“unconditional”) probability P (A), then A and B are independent. Conversely, if A and B are independent, then P (A|B) = P (A) (assuming P (B) > 0). 5. Complement rule for conditional probabilities: P (A0|B) = 1 − P (A|B). That is, with respect to the first argument, A, the conditional probability P (A|B) satisfies the ordinary complement rule. 6. Multiplication rule: P (A ∩ B) = P (A|B)P (B) Some special cases • If P (A) = 0 or P (B) = 0 then A and B are independent. The same holds when P (A) = 1 or P (B) = 1. • If B = A or B = A0, A and B are not independent except in the above trivial case when P (A) or P (B) is 0 or 1. In other words, an event A which has probability strictly between 0 and 1 is not independent of itself or of its complement.
    [Show full text]
  • Propensities and Probabilities
    ARTICLE IN PRESS Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2007) 593–625 www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsb Propensities and probabilities Nuel Belnap 1028-A Cathedral of Learning, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15260, USA Received 19 May 2006; accepted 6 September 2006 Abstract Popper’s introduction of ‘‘propensity’’ was intended to provide a solid conceptual foundation for objective single-case probabilities. By considering the partly opposed contributions of Humphreys and Miller and Salmon, it is argued that when properly understood, propensities can in fact be understood as objective single-case causal probabilities of transitions between concrete events. The chief claim is that propensities are well-explicated by describing how they fit into the existing formal theory of branching space-times, which is simultaneously indeterministic and causal. Several problematic examples, some commonsense and some quantum-mechanical, are used to make clear the advantages of invoking branching space-times theory in coming to understand propensities. r 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: Propensities; Probabilities; Space-times; Originating causes; Indeterminism; Branching histories 1. Introduction You are flipping a fair coin fairly. You ascribe a probability to a single case by asserting The probability that heads will occur on this very next flip is about 50%. ð1Þ The rough idea of a single-case probability seems clear enough when one is told that the contrast is with either generalizations or frequencies attributed to populations asserted while you are flipping a fair coin fairly, such as In the long run; the probability of heads occurring among flips is about 50%. ð2Þ E-mail address: [email protected] 1355-2198/$ - see front matter r 2007 Elsevier Ltd.
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Probability and Bayes Theorem A
    Conditional probability And Bayes theorem A. Zaikin 2.1 Conditional probability 1 Conditional probablity Given events E and F ,oftenweareinterestedinstatementslike if even E has occurred, then the probability of F is ... Some examples: • Roll two dice: what is the probability that the sum of faces is 6 given that the first face is 4? • Gene expressions: What is the probability that gene A is switched off (e.g. down-regulated) given that gene B is also switched off? A. Zaikin 2.2 Conditional probability 2 This conditional probability can be derived following a similar construction: • Repeat the experiment N times. • Count the number of times event E occurs, N(E),andthenumberoftimesboth E and F occur jointly, N(E ∩ F ).HenceN(E) ≤ N • The proportion of times that F occurs in this reduced space is N(E ∩ F ) N(E) since E occurs at each one of them. • Now note that the ratio above can be re-written as the ratio between two (unconditional) probabilities N(E ∩ F ) N(E ∩ F )/N = N(E) N(E)/N • Then the probability of F ,giventhatE has occurred should be defined as P (E ∩ F ) P (E) A. Zaikin 2.3 Conditional probability: definition The definition of Conditional Probability The conditional probability of an event F ,giventhataneventE has occurred, is defined as P (E ∩ F ) P (F |E)= P (E) and is defined only if P (E) > 0. Note that, if E has occurred, then • F |E is a point in the set P (E ∩ F ) • E is the new sample space it can be proved that the function P (·|·) defyning a conditional probability also satisfies the three probability axioms.
    [Show full text]
  • CONDITIONAL EXPECTATION Definition 1. Let (Ω,F,P)
    CONDITIONAL EXPECTATION 1. CONDITIONAL EXPECTATION: L2 THEORY ¡ Definition 1. Let (­,F ,P) be a probability space and let G be a σ algebra contained in F . For ¡ any real random variable X L2(­,F ,P), define E(X G ) to be the orthogonal projection of X 2 j onto the closed subspace L2(­,G ,P). This definition may seem a bit strange at first, as it seems not to have any connection with the naive definition of conditional probability that you may have learned in elementary prob- ability. However, there is a compelling rationale for Definition 1: the orthogonal projection E(X G ) minimizes the expected squared difference E(X Y )2 among all random variables Y j ¡ 2 L2(­,G ,P), so in a sense it is the best predictor of X based on the information in G . It may be helpful to consider the special case where the σ algebra G is generated by a single random ¡ variable Y , i.e., G σ(Y ). In this case, every G measurable random variable is a Borel function Æ ¡ of Y (exercise!), so E(X G ) is the unique Borel function h(Y ) (up to sets of probability zero) that j minimizes E(X h(Y ))2. The following exercise indicates that the special case where G σ(Y ) ¡ Æ for some real-valued random variable Y is in fact very general. Exercise 1. Show that if G is countably generated (that is, there is some countable collection of set B G such that G is the smallest σ algebra containing all of the sets B ) then there is a j 2 ¡ j G measurable real random variable Y such that G σ(Y ).
    [Show full text]
  • ST 371 (VIII): Theory of Joint Distributions
    ST 371 (VIII): Theory of Joint Distributions So far we have focused on probability distributions for single random vari- ables. However, we are often interested in probability statements concerning two or more random variables. The following examples are illustrative: • In ecological studies, counts, modeled as random variables, of several species are often made. One species is often the prey of another; clearly, the number of predators will be related to the number of prey. • The joint probability distribution of the x, y and z components of wind velocity can be experimentally measured in studies of atmospheric turbulence. • The joint distribution of the values of various physiological variables in a population of patients is often of interest in medical studies. • A model for the joint distribution of age and length in a population of ¯sh can be used to estimate the age distribution from the length dis- tribution. The age distribution is relevant to the setting of reasonable harvesting policies. 1 Joint Distribution The joint behavior of two random variables X and Y is determined by the joint cumulative distribution function (cdf): (1.1) FXY (x; y) = P (X · x; Y · y); where X and Y are continuous or discrete. For example, the probability that (X; Y ) belongs to a given rectangle is P (x1 · X · x2; y1 · Y · y2) = F (x2; y2) ¡ F (x2; y1) ¡ F (x1; y2) + F (x1; y1): 1 In general, if X1; ¢ ¢ ¢ ;Xn are jointly distributed random variables, the joint cdf is FX1;¢¢¢ ;Xn (x1; ¢ ¢ ¢ ; xn) = P (X1 · x1;X2 · x2; ¢ ¢ ¢ ;Xn · xn): Two- and higher-dimensional versions of probability distribution functions and probability mass functions exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Recent Progress on Conditional Randomness (Probability Symposium)
    数理解析研究所講究録 39 第2030巻 2017年 39-46 Recent progress on conditional randomness * Hayato Takahashi Random Data Lab. Abstract We review the recent progress on the definition of randomness with respect to conditional probabilities and a generalization of van Lambal‐ gen theorem (Takahashi 2006, 2008, 2009, 2011). In addition we show a new result on the random sequences when the conditional probabili‐ tie \mathrm{s}^{\backslash }\mathrm{a}\mathrm{r}\mathrm{e} mutually singular, which is a generalization of Kjos Hanssens theorem (2010). Finally we propose a definition of random sequences with respect to conditional probability and argue the validity of the definition from the Bayesian statistical point of view. Keywords: Martin‐Löf random sequences, Lambalgen theo‐ rem, conditional probability, Bayesian statistics 1 Introduction The notion of conditional probability is one of the main idea in probability theory. In order to define conditional probability rigorously, Kolmogorov introduced measure theory into probability theory [4]. The notion of ran‐ domness is another important subject in probability and statistics. In statistics, the set of random points is defined as the compliment of give statistical tests. In practice, data is finite and statistical test is a set of small probability, say 3%, with respect to null hypothesis. In order to dis‐ cuss whether a point is random or not rigorously, we study the randomness of sequences (infinite data) and null sets as statistical tests. The random set depends on the class of statistical tests. Kolmogorov brought an idea of recursion theory into statistics and proposed the random set as the compli‐ ment of the effective null sets [5, 6, 8].
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2: Probability
    16 Chapter 2: Probability The aim of this chapter is to revise the basic rules of probability. By the end of this chapter, you should be comfortable with: • conditional probability, and what you can and can’t do with conditional expressions; • the Partition Theorem and Bayes’ Theorem; • First-Step Analysis for finding the probability that a process reaches some state, by conditioning on the outcome of the first step; • calculating probabilities for continuous and discrete random variables. 2.1 Sample spaces and events Definition: A sample space, Ω, is a set of possible outcomes of a random experiment. Definition: An event, A, is a subset of the sample space. This means that event A is simply a collection of outcomes. Example: Random experiment: Pick a person in this class at random. Sample space: Ω= {all people in class} Event A: A = {all males in class}. Definition: Event A occurs if the outcome of the random experiment is a member of the set A. In the example above, event A occurs if the person we pick is male. 17 2.2 Probability Reference List The following properties hold for all events A, B. • P(∅)=0. • 0 ≤ P(A) ≤ 1. • Complement: P(A)=1 − P(A). • Probability of a union: P(A ∪ B)= P(A)+ P(B) − P(A ∩ B). For three events A, B, C: P(A∪B∪C)= P(A)+P(B)+P(C)−P(A∩B)−P(A∩C)−P(B∩C)+P(A∩B∩C) . If A and B are mutually exclusive, then P(A ∪ B)= P(A)+ P(B).
    [Show full text]
  • Probabilistic Logic Programming and Bayesian Networks
    Probabilistic Logic Programming and Bayesian Networks Liem Ngo and Peter Haddawy Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science University of WisconsinMilwaukee Milwaukee WI fliem haddawygcsuwmedu Abstract We present a probabilistic logic programming framework that allows the repre sentation of conditional probabilities While conditional probabilities are the most commonly used metho d for representing uncertainty in probabilistic exp ert systems they have b een largely neglected bywork in quantitative logic programming We de ne a xp oint theory declarativesemantics and pro of pro cedure for the new class of probabilistic logic programs Compared to other approaches to quantitative logic programming weprovide a true probabilistic framework with p otential applications in probabilistic exp ert systems and decision supp ort systems We also discuss the relation ship b etween such programs and Bayesian networks thus moving toward a unication of two ma jor approaches to automated reasoning To appear in Proceedings of the Asian Computing Science Conference Pathumthani Thailand December This work was partially supp orted by NSF grant IRI Intro duction Reasoning under uncertainty is a topic of great imp ortance to many areas of Computer Sci ence Of all approaches to reasoning under uncertainty probability theory has the strongest theoretical foundations In the quest to extend the framwork of logic programming to represent and reason with uncertain knowledge there havebeenseveral attempts to add numeric representations of uncertainty
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Probability Problems in Textbooks an Example from Spain 319
    CONDITIONAL PROBABILITY PROBLEMS IN TEXTBOOKS AN EXAMPLE FROM SPAIN 319 M. ÁNGELES LONJEDO VICENT, M. PEDRO HUERTA PALAU, MARTA CARLES FARIÑA CONDITIONAL PROBABILITY PROBLEMS IN TEXTBOOKS AN EXAMPLE FROM SPAIN RESUMEN PALABRAS CLAVE: En este artículo, que forma parte de los resultados de un estudio - Probabilidad condicional más amplio, presentamos un método para identificar, clasificar y - Resolución de problemas analizar los problemas ternarios de probabilidad condicional en - Análisis de libros de texto los libros de texto de matemáticas. Este método se basa tanto en la estructura de los problemas como en un enfoque realista de la enseñanza de las matemáticas basado en la resolución de problemas en contexto. Presentamos algunos resultados de este análisis realizado con libros de texto de matemáticas españoles. lame ABSTRACT C KEY WORDS: In this paper we show part of the results of a larger study1 - Conditional probability that investigates conditional probability problem solving. - Solving problems In particular, we report on a structure-based method to - Analysis of textbook identify, classify and analyse ternary problems of conditional probability in mathematics textbooks in schools. This method is also based on a realistic mathematics education approach to mathematics teaching through problem solving in context. We report some results of the analysis of mathematics textbooks from Spain. RESUMO PALAVRAS CHAVE: Neste artigo, que é parte dos resultados de um estudo maior, - Probabilidade condicional apresentamos um métodoersión para identificar, classificar e analisar - Resolução de problemas problemas de probabilidade condicional em livros didáticos de - Análise de livros didáticos matemática. Este método baseia-se tanto na estrutura dos problemas quantoV em uma abordagem realista para o ensino da matemática, com base na resolução de problemas em contexto.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.7 Conditional Probability on the Independence of Events
    Section 7. Conditional Probability on the Independence of Events (ATTENDANCE 3)39 2.7 Conditional Probability on the Independence of Events Often we know that a particular event, event B say, is “known to have occurred”. We can use this information to upgrade our knowledge about the probability of some other event, event A, say. More specifically, we calculate the probability of event A, conditional on the occurrence of event B. This probability is denoted P (A|B). For any two events A and B with P (B) > 0, the conditional probability of A given that B has occurred is defined by P (A ∩ B) P (A|B)= . P (B) Furthermore, two events are independent if any one of the following is true: P (A ∩ B) = P (A)P (B), P (A|B) = P (A), P (B|A) = P (B). Exercise 2.7 (Conditional Probability on the Independence of Events) 1. Conditional probability versus unconditional probability: Interviews. Seven can- didates, three of which are females, are being interviewed for a job. The three female’s names are Kathy, Susan and Jamie; the four male’s names are Tom, Tim, Tyler and Toothy. Assume the candidates are chosen at random for a job interview. 1 (a) The chance that Tom is chosen given that a male is chosen, 4 , is an example of (i) conditional probability (ii) unconditional probability. 0 (b) The chance Tom is chosen given that a female is chosen, 3 , is an example of (i) conditional probability (ii) unconditional probability. 1 (c) The chance Tom is chosen, 7 , is an example of (i) conditional probability (ii) unconditional probability.
    [Show full text]