Framing Effects in the Prisoner's Dilemma but Not in the Dictator Game

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Framing Effects in the Prisoner's Dilemma but Not in the Dictator Game Framing effects in the Prisoner’s Dilemma but not in the Dictator Game Sebastian J. Goerga,b, David Randc,d & Gari Walkowitze January 31, 2017 Abstract We systematically investigate prisoner’s dilemma games and dictator games with valence framing. We find that give versus take frames influence subjects’ behavior and beliefs in the prisoner’s dilemma game but not in the dictator game. Keywords: Prisoner’s Dilemma, Dictator Game, Framing, Give, Take, Cooperation, Generosity JEL Codes: A13, C72, C91, F51, Z13 Contacting the authors: [email protected] [email protected], [email protected] a Florida State University, 113 Collegiate Loop, Tallahassee, FL 32306, United States. b Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Kurt-Schumacher-Straße 10, 53113 Bonn, Germany. c Department of Psychology, 2 Hillhouse Ave, Yale University, New Haven CT 06511, United States. d Department of Economics, 2 Hillhouse Ave, Yale University, New Haven CT 06511, United States. e Faculty of Management, Economics and Social Sciences, University of Cologne, Albertus-Magnus-Platz, 50923 Cologne, Germany. 1 1. Introduction Countless papers have demonstrated that framing can change behavior despite the underlying information and options remaining the same (see recent reviews by Gerlach and Jaeger, 2016; Cartwrigth, 2016). But when and how, precisely, do frames affect behavior? Without additional assumptions, most theories of other-regarding preferences (e.g., Fehr and Schmidt 1999; Bolton and Ockenfels, 2000; Charness and Rabin, 2002) predict no differences between two frames of the same decision problem. Ellingsen et al. (2012) argue that social frames, i.e, naming a game for example “community” or “stock market” game, provides a coordination device helping to select between multiple equilibria with social preferences. They support this account by showing framing effects in synchronous but not asynchonorous Prisoner’s Dilemmas. The findings of Dreber et al. (2012), who do not observe significant effects of social frames in dictator games, provide further support, because coordination problems do not exist in dictator games. Also compatible with the beliefs account is Dufwenberg et al. (2011), who demonstrate that valence and social-frames in one-shot public good games affect not only subjects’ contributions but also their first- and second-order beliefs. Conversely, Cox et al. (2013) argue based on revealed altruism (Cox et al., 2008) that positive and negative frames result in different games with different degrees of expected reciprocity. Similarly, Gächter et al. (2016) find that give and take frames not only influence beliefs but also increase the share of conditional cooperators. In this paper, we provide new evidence regarding these arguments by systematically investigating prisoner’s dilemma games and dictator games with valence framing. We observe that give and take frames influence subjects’ behavior and beliefs in 2 the prisoner’s dilemma but not in the dictator game. Our data is most simply explained by Ellingsen et al. (2012)’s beliefs account, but cannot rule out frames affecting the extent of reciprocity-based preferences. 2. Experimental Design We investigate a give and a take frame for the prisoner’s dilemma game and the dictator game. The games are implemented as one-shot games. 2.1 Prisoner’s Dilemma Games The prisoner’s dilemma games are implemented as continuous choice games. They allow subjects to choose a degree of cooperation instead of a dichotomous decision to cooperate or to defect (Goerg and Walkowitz, 2010). Cooperation is welfare enhancing and increases the joint payoffs. In the give frame, cooperation is expressed by the amount given to the other player. In the take frame, it is expressed by the amount left to the other player. In both frames, two players are randomly matched and each subject receives an initial endowment of 100 Talers. In the give frame, subject i decides an integer amount a between 0 and 100 to the matched player. The transferred amount is doubled and credited to the matched player’s account. The game is symmetric. The matched player j simultaneously decides on an amount aj to be doubled and transferred to player i. Thus, the payoff function for player i, based on amounts ai and aj, is given as: �! = 100 − �! + 2�!, with �!, �! ∈ 0,1, … ,100 The payoff for player j is derived analogously. 3 The take frame is very similar. However, the players simultaneously decide on amounts ai and aj they want to transfer from the matched player’s endowment. The amount remaining in the matched player’s account is doubled. Player i’s payoff function is given as: �! = 2 ∗ (100 − �!) + �!, with �!, �! ∈ 0,1, … ,100 The payoff for player j is derived analogously. 2.2. Dictator Games The dictator games mimic our prisoner’s dilemma games but with one player remaining passive.1 One player is endowed with 200 Talers. The other player receives no initial endowment. In the give frame, the endowment is allocated to the dictator i, who decides on an integer amount a between 0 and 200 to be transferred to the passive receiver j. As in the Prisoner’s Dilemma Game with the give frame, the transfer is doubled. Thus, the payoffs functions for dictator i and receiver j are given as: �! = 200 − �!, with �! ∈ 0,1, … ,200 �! = 2�!, with �! 0,1, … ,200 In the take frame, the endowment is given to the passive player j. The dictator i decides on the amount to be transferred away from the passive player. The amount left to the passive player is doubled, resulting in the following payoff functions: �! = �!, with �! ∈ 0,1, … ,200 �! = 2 ∗ (200 − �!), with �! 0,1, … ,200 1 Other studies on dictator games with give and take options increase the action set into the take domain (List, 2007) or use give and take frames to investigate social norms (Krupka and Weber, 2013) and property rights (Hoffmann et al., 1994; Eichenberger and Oberholzer-Gee, 1998; Oxoby and Spraggon, 2008). Our game differs in the following ways: a very neutral framing is applied to identical action sets, we avoid terms like “give” or “take”, we induce efficiency gains from generosity, and the initial endowment is not earned. 4 2.3. Implementation The experiments were conducted at the Cologne Laboratory for Economic Research at the University of Cologne. While we confronted subjects with the different frames, we implemented the frames using language that was as neutral as possible. Instead of labeling decisions as “give” or “take” decisions, only the recipient of the transfers was changed in the description. In the give frame, subjects were told that they had the opportunity to transfer any part of their endowment to Person B. In the take frame, they had the opportunity to transfer any part of Person B’s endowment to themselves.2 After the decision, we elicited first order beliefs.3 To avoid session effects, we played all four games in each of the eight conducted sessions.4 Subjects were recruited from the local ORSEE database (Greiner, 2015). Decisions, beliefs and normative statements were gathered using pen and paper, followed by a questionnaire programmed in z-Tree (Fischbacher, 2007). Game Frame # ind. Observations # subjects %female av. age Prisoner’s Dilemma Give 52 52 55.7 24.4 Prisoner’s Dilemma Take 54 54 50 23.1 Dictator Give 40 (16) 56 55.4 22.5 Dictator Take 41 (16) 57 50.9 23.9 Table 1: Summary of gathered observations. Numbers in the brackets for the dictator games denote the number of recipients. 2 This is in contrast to other papers which used give and take frames. A translation of the instructions is provided in Appendix A. 3 In addition we elicited second order beliefs and statements on normatively fair. For brevity we will focus on first order beliefs and transfers. 4 In four sessions 31 subjects participated, in two sessions 24 subjects, in one session 22 subjects and one with 17 subjects. 5 In total 219, subjects participated: 106 in the Prisoner’s Dilemma Games, 113 in the Dictator Games (81 in the role of the dictator and 32 in the role of the passive receiver).5 53% of the subjects were female and the average age was 23.5 years (see Table 1). 3. Results Figure 1 depicts the transfers exhibited in the Prisoner’s Dilemma games and in the dictator games, as well as the corresponding first-order beliefs and standard errors.6 In the Prisoner’s Dilemma game, transfers are significantly higher in the give frame than in the take frame (p<0.001)7. On average, the cooperation level is more than twice as high if subjects were allowed to transfer to the matched player instead of transferring to themselves. Table 2 gives the results of Tobit regressions confirming the negative and significant influence of the take frame. This main effect remains significant when controlling for gender and age. 5 To generate more independent observations per session, we matched one passive receiver to several dictators. 6 To make transfers comparable across give and take frame, transfers in the take frames needed to be transformed. In the negative frame of the Prisoner’s Dilemma game, cooperation is measured by (100-a) and generosity in the dictator game by (200-a). 7 Two-sided Mann-Whitney u-tests are applied if not stated otherwise. 6 Behavior Belief Prisoners Dilemma PG Give PG Take Dictator Game DG Give DG Take 0 20 40 60 80 100 0 20 40 60 80 100 % Cooperation/Generosity Figure 1: Box plot for the degree of cooperation in the Prisoner’s Dilemma games and the degree of generosity in the dictator games. Bold line gives the median, the box the 25th and 75th quartiles, and whiskers the 1.5xIQR. Transfers in the take frames are transformed for comparability.
Recommended publications
  • Embezzlement and Guilt Aversion Giuseppe Attanasi, Claire Rimbaud, Marie Claire Villeval
    Embezzlement and Guilt Aversion Giuseppe Attanasi, Claire Rimbaud, Marie Claire Villeval To cite this version: Giuseppe Attanasi, Claire Rimbaud, Marie Claire Villeval. Embezzlement and Guilt Aversion. 2018. halshs-01779145 HAL Id: halshs-01779145 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01779145 Preprint submitted on 26 Apr 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. WP 1807 – April 2018 Embezzlement and Guilt Aversion Giuseppe Attanasi, Claire Rimbaud, Marie Claire Villeval Abstract: Donors usually need intermediaries to transfer their donations to recipients. A risk is that donations can be embezzled before they reach the recipients. Using psychological game theory, we design a novel three- player Embezzlement Mini-Game to study whether intermediaries suffer from guilt aversion and whether guilt aversion toward the recipient is stronger than toward the donor. Testing the predictions of the model in a laboratory experiment, we show that the proportion of guilt-averse intermediaries is the same irrespective of the direction of the guilt. However, structural estimates indicate that the effect of guilt on behaviour is higher when the guilt is directed toward the recipient. Keywords: Embezzlement, Dishonesty, Guilt Aversion, Psychological Game Theory, Experiment JEL codes: C91 Embezzlement and Guilt Aversion G.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods Agreements with Other-Regarding Preferences
    NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PUBLIC GOODS AGREEMENTS WITH OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES Charles D. Kolstad Working Paper 17017 http://www.nber.org/papers/w17017 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02138 May 2011 Department of Economics and Bren School, University of California, Santa Barbara; Resources for the Future; and NBER. Comments from Werner Güth, Kaj Thomsson and Philipp Wichardt and discussions with Gary Charness and Michael Finus have been appreciated. Outstanding research assistance from Trevor O’Grady and Adam Wright is gratefully acknowledged. Funding from the University of California Center for Energy and Environmental Economics (UCE3) is also acknowledged and appreciated. The views expressed herein are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Bureau of Economic Research. NBER working papers are circulated for discussion and comment purposes. They have not been peer- reviewed or been subject to the review by the NBER Board of Directors that accompanies official NBER publications. © 2011 by Charles D. Kolstad. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceed two paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission provided that full credit, including © notice, is given to the source. Public Goods Agreements with Other-Regarding Preferences Charles D. Kolstad NBER Working Paper No. 17017 May 2011, Revised June 2012 JEL No. D03,H4,H41,Q5 ABSTRACT Why cooperation occurs when noncooperation appears to be individually rational has been an issue in economics for at least a half century. In the 1960’s and 1970’s the context was cooperation in the prisoner’s dilemma game; in the 1980’s concern shifted to voluntary provision of public goods; in the 1990’s, the literature on coalition formation for public goods provision emerged, in the context of coalitions to provide transboundary pollution abatement.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Evidence of Dictator and Ultimatum Games
    games Article How to Split Gains and Losses? Experimental Evidence of Dictator and Ultimatum Games Thomas Neumann 1, Sabrina Kierspel 1,*, Ivo Windrich 2, Roger Berger 2 and Bodo Vogt 1 1 Chair in Empirical Economics, Otto-von-Guericke-University Magdeburg, Postbox 4120, 39016 Magdeburg, Germany; [email protected] (T.N.); [email protected] (B.V.) 2 Institute of Sociology, University of Leipzig, Beethovenstr. 15, 04107 Leipzig, Germany; [email protected] (I.W.); [email protected] (R.B.) * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +49-391-6758205 Received: 27 August 2018; Accepted: 3 October 2018; Published: 5 October 2018 Abstract: Previous research has typically focused on distribution problems that emerge in the domain of gains. Only a few studies have distinguished between games played in the domain of gains from games in the domain of losses, even though, for example, prospect theory predicts differences between behavior in both domains. In this study, we experimentally analyze players’ behavior in dictator and ultimatum games when they need to divide a monetary loss and then compare this to behavior when players have to divide a monetary gain. We find that players treat gains and losses differently in that they are less generous in games over losses and react differently to prior experiences. Players in the dictator game become more selfish after they have had the experience of playing an ultimatum game first. Keywords: dictator game; ultimatum game; gains; losses; equal split; experimental economics 1. Introduction Economists and social scientists have collected an increasing body of literature on the importance of other-regarding preferences for decision-making in various contexts [1].
    [Show full text]
  • Endogenous Institutions and Game-Theoretic Analysis
    Chapter 5 Endogenous Institutions and Game-theoretic Analysis Chapters 3 and 4 illustrate that restricting the set of admissible institutionalized beliefs is central to the way in which game theory facilitates the study of endogenous institutions. Durkheim (1950 [1895], p. 45) recognized the centrality of institutionalized beliefs, arguing that institutions are “all the beliefs and modes of behavior instituted by the collectivity.” But neither Durkheim nor his followers placed any analytic restrictions on what beliefs the collectivity could institute. Because beliefs are not directly observable, however, deductively restricting them, as game theory lets us do, is imperative. The only beliefs that can be instituted by the collectivity—that can be common knowledge—are those regarding equilibrium (self-enforcing) behavior. Furthermore, the behavior that these beliefs motivate should reproduce—not refute or erode—these beliefs. Game theory thus enables us to place more of the “responsibility for social order on the individuals who are part of that order” (Crawford and Ostrom 1995, p. 583). Rather than assuming that individuals follow rules, it provides an analytical framework within which it is possible to study the way in which behavior is endogenously generated—how, through their interactions, individuals gain the information, ability, and motivation to follow particular rules of behavior. It allows us to examine, for example, who applies sanctions and rewards that motivate behavior, how those who are to apply them learn or decide which ones to apply, why they do not shirk this duty, and why offenders do not flee to avoid sanctions. The empirical usefulness of the analytical framework of classical game theory is puzzling, however, because this theory rests on seemingly unrealistic assumptions about cognition, information and rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Rationality in Bargaining Games: Do Proposers Believe That Responders Reject an Equal Split?
    No. 11 UNIVERSITY OF COLOGNE WORKING PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS BOUNDED RATIONALITY IN BARGAINING GAMES: DO PROPOSERS BELIEVE THAT RESPONDERS REJECT AN EQUAL SPLIT? BEN GREINER Department of Economics University of Cologne Albertus-Magnus-Platz D-50923 Köln Germany http://www.wiso.uni-koeln.de Bounded Rationality in Bargaining Games: Do Proposers Believe That Responders Reject an Equal Split?∗ Ben Greiner† June 19, 2004 Abstract Puzzled by the experimental results of the ’impunity game’ by Bolton & Zwick (1995) we replicate the game and alter it in a systematic manner. We find that although almost nobody actually rejects an offered equal split in a bargaining game, proposers behave as if there would be a considerably large rejection rate for equal splits. This result is inconsistent with existing models of economic decision making. This includes models of selfish play- ers as well as models of social utility and reciprocity, even when combined with erroneous decision making. Our data suggests that subjects fail to foresee their opponent’s decision even for one step in our simple bargaining games. We consider models of bounded rational decision making such as rules of thumb as explanations for the observed behavioral pattern. Keywords: ultimatum game, dictator game, impunity game, social utility, bounded rationality JEL Classification: C72, C92, D3 ∗I thank Bettina Bartels, Hakan Fink and Ralica Gospodinova for research assistance, the Strategic Interaction Group at MPI Jena for comments and serving as pilot participants, especially Susanne B¨uchner, Sven Fischer, Katinka Pantz and Carsten Schmidt for support in the conduction of the experiment, and Werner G¨uth, Axel Ockenfels, Ro’i Zultan, participants at the European ESA Meeting in Erfurt and at the Brown Bag seminars in Jena and Cologne for discussions and valuable comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Labels Increase Cooperation and Costly Punishment in a Prisoner's
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Moral labels increase cooperation and costly punishment in a Prisoner’s Dilemma game with punishment option Laura Mieth *, Axel Buchner & Raoul Bell To determine the role of moral norms in cooperation and punishment, we examined the efects of a moral-framing manipulation in a Prisoner’s Dilemma game with a costly punishment option. In each round of the game, participants decided whether to cooperate or to defect. The Prisoner’s Dilemma game was identical for all participants with the exception that the behavioral options were paired with moral labels (“I cooperate” and “I cheat”) in the moral-framing condition and with neutral labels (“A” and “B”) in the neutral-framing condition. After each round of the Prisoner’s Dilemma game, participants had the opportunity to invest some of their money to punish their partners. In two experiments, moral framing increased moral and hypocritical punishment: participants were more likely to punish partners for defection when moral labels were used than when neutral labels were used. When the participants’ cooperation was enforced by their partners’ moral punishment, moral framing did not only increase moral and hypocritical punishment but also cooperation. The results suggest that moral framing activates a cooperative norm that specifcally increases moral and hypocritical punishment. Furthermore, the experience of moral punishment by the partners may increase the importance of social norms for cooperation, which may explain why moral framing efects on cooperation were found only when participants were subject to moral punishment. Within Economics and Economic Psychology, social dilemma games such as the Ultimatum game 1, the Public Goods game2 and the Prisoner’s Dilemma game3 are used to break down the complexities of human social interactions into specifc payof structures.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Procedures and Protocols Core Games: Dictator, Ultimatum, Third Party Punishment
    GAME PROCEDURES AND PROTOCOLS CORE GAMES: DICTATOR, ULTIMATUM, THIRD PARTY PUNISHMENT Translation: Each researcher will have to adapt these instructions to fit their particular field site by translating them into the appropriate local language and adjusting the currency and stake sizes. Researchers will use the method of back-translation to obtain the best possible game translation. This involves having one bilingual assistant with no knowledge of the game translate the game instructions into the local language and a second translate it back, thus identifying any problems in translation. Supply the translation in Appendix of your paper. Game Administrator: All games should be run by you with a native speaker to assist/interpret unless you yourself are completely fluent in the local language. If a local interpreter is used, he/she should be asked to turn around when offers are made so that no local individuals have knowledge of the offers being made. Gather Participants in One Place: All participants must be brought together in the same place prior to playing the game. Use research assistants to control the logistical flow once the game begins. Those who have completed the game must depart (or be assigned to a separate waiting area) and cannot interact with those waiting to play. Participants should be told that anyone waiting to play who talks to someone who has already played the game will be disqualified from participation. They can talk amongst themselves, but not about the game. Only explain the game to the group as a whole if you have sufficient assistants to avoid discussions among players that could lead to the 3 C’s (contagion, contamination and collusion).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods Games and Psychological Utility: Theory and Evidence
    School of Business Economics Division Public goods games and psychological utility: Theory and evidence Sanjit Dhami, University of Leicester Mengxing Wei, University of Leicester Ali al-Nowaihi, University of Leicester Working Paper No. 16/17 Public goods games and psychological utility: Theory and evidence. Sanjit Dhami Mengxing Weiy Ali al-Nowaihiz 10 November 2016 Abstract We consider a public goods game which incorporates guilt-aversion/surprise- seeking and the attribution of intentions behind these emotions (Battigalli and Dufwenberg, 2007; Khalmetski et al., 2015). We implement the induced beliefs method (Ellingsen et al., 2010) and a within-subjects design using the strategy method. Previous studies mainly use dictator games - whose results may not be robust to adding strategic components. We find that guilt-aversion is far more im- portant than surprise-seeking; and that the attribution of intentions behind guilt- aversion/surprise-seeking is important. Our between-subjects analysis confirms the results of the within-subjects design. Keywords: Public goods games; psychological game theory; surprise-seeking/guilt- aversion; attribution of intentions; induced beliefs method; strategy method; within- subjects design. JEL Classification: D01 (Microeconomic Behavior: Underlying Principles); D03 (Be- havioral Microeconomics: Underlying Principles); H41 (Public Goods). Corresponding author. Division of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, Uni- versity Road, Leicester. LE1 7RH, UK. Phone: +44-116-2522086. Fax: +44-116-2522908. E-mail: [email protected]. yDivision of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, University Road, Leicester, LE1 7RH. Fax: +44-116-2522908. Email: [email protected] zDivision of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, University Road, Leicester.
    [Show full text]
  • From Dictator Game to Ultimatum Game and Back Again: the Judicial
    Articles and Essays FROM DICTATOR GAME TO ULTIMATUM GAME... AND BACK AGAIN: THE JUDICIAL IMPASSE AMENDMENTS Ellen Dannint In 1935, Congress decided to replace the "dictator game" that had long been used to set working conditions with an "ultimatum game" by enacting the National Labor Relations Act (NLRA). A dictator game is a two-player economic game in which player one proposes a division of resources and player two has no choice but to accept the offer. Economic theory predicts that in such a case, player one will offer nothing to player two. This is indeed the most common offer.' Before the NLRA was enacted, the law allowed the employer (player one), to offer terms of employment and essentially required the employee (player two), to accept the offer dictated by the employer. The NLRA was enacted to replace this game with an "ultimatum game" by changing the balance of power between employers and employees and creating a system of wage setting that would better support the institutions of a democracy.2 In an ultimatum game, player one t Professor of Law, Wayne State University Law School. B.A., University of Michigan; J.D., University of Michigan. The author wishes to thank the following: Theodore St. Antoine, Richard Lempert, Gregory Saltzman, Gangaram Singh, participants in the University of Michigan Learning Theory Workshop, my colleagues at Wayne State University, and the University of Michigan labor law students class for their questions and thoughts that challenged ideas about the core issues discussed here. 1. Alvin E. Roth, Bargaining Experiments, in THE HANDBOOK OF EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS 253, 270 (John H.
    [Show full text]
  • Perfect Or Bounded Rationality? Some Facts, Speculations and Proposals
    Analyse & Kritik 26/2004 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 364–381 Werner G¨uth/Hartmut Kliemt∗ Perfect or Bounded Rationality? Some Facts, Speculations and Proposals Abstract: Simple game experiments of the reward allocation, dictator and ultimatum type are used to demonstrate that true explanations of social phenomena cannot con- ceivably be derived in terms of the perfect rationality concept underlying neo-classical economics. We explore in some depth, if speculatively, how experimental game theory might bring us closer to a new synthesis or at least the nucleus of a general theory of ‘games and boundedly rational economic behavior’ with enhanced explanatory power. 1. Introduction and Overview Explanations in terms of bounded rationality are typically based on strongly do- main dependent theories of quite short range. Using them leads to a fragmented view of the world. As opposed to that, decision and game theoretic language convey the impression of a unified view of the world that renders diverse phe- nomena more intelligible by putting them in (the same) perspective. Yet if we look more closely at the way the general language of decision and game theory has to be adapted to specific domains mostly by ad hoc assumptions, it is obvi- ous that the rational choice theorists’ claims to universality and unity of their theories are based on a kind of collective self-deception. They have a common language—not a small accomplishment—but no common theory with general empirical content and explanatory power. It may well be that in the end there are no convincing truly general theories of human behavior at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Decision Are Preferences for Allocating Harm Rational? Alexander L
    Decision Are Preferences for Allocating Harm Rational? Alexander L. Davis, John H. Miller, and Sudeep Bhatia Online First Publication, April 3, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/dec0000076 CITATION Davis, A. L., Miller, J. H., & Bhatia, S. (2017, April 3). Are Preferences for Allocating Harm Rational?. Decision. Advance online publication. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/dec0000076 Decision © 2017 American Psychological Association 2017, Vol. 1, No. 999, 000 2325-9965/17/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/dec0000076 Are Preferences for Allocating Harm Rational? Alexander L. Davis, John H. Miller, and Sudeep Bhatia Carnegie Mellon University The allocation of nonmonetary harm is an important—yet understudied—domain of choice. Using a modified Dictator Game, we asked 27 participants to allocate a harmful event (time of putting their hand in ice water) between themselves and an anonymous stranger. We found substantially less coherent, and more egalitarian, preferences compared to other studies that ask participants to allocate monetary endowments. Specifically, 26% of participants made choices inconsistent with utility maximization, and 78% of participants behaved in an egalitarian manner. In comparable studies of monetary gains, only 2% were inconsistent and 30% egalitarian. The results suggest that the focus on monetary gains likely overestimates the rationality of other-regarding preferences and underestimates egalitarianism. Keywords: altruism, prosocial behavior, rationality, revealed preference Research in the last two decades has illumi- an individual going off to war, to the more nated our understanding of costly, other- mundane, like taking out the trash. regarding behavior (Andreoni & Vesterlund, We emphasize nonmonetary bads for a vari- 2001; Benabou & Tirole, 2006; Fehr & ety of reasons.
    [Show full text]
  • Collusive Security Games
    Divide to Defend: Collusive Security Games Shahrzad Gholami, Bryan Wilder, Matthew Brown, Dana Thomas, Nicole Sintov, and Milind Tambe Computer Science Department, University of Southern California {sgholami,bwilder,matthew.a.brown,danathom, sintov,tambe}@usc.edu Abstract. Research on security games has focused on settings where the de- fender must protect against either a single adversary or multiple, independent adversaries. However, there are a variety of real-world security domains where adversaries may benefit from colluding in their actions against the defender, e.g., wildlife poaching, urban crime and drug trafficking. Given such adversary col- lusion may be more detrimental for the defender, she has an incentive to break up collusion by playing off the self-interest of individual adversaries. As we show in this paper, breaking up such collusion is difficult given bounded rationality of human adversaries; we therefore investigate algorithms for the defender assum- ing both rational and boundedly rational adversaries. The contributions of this paper include (i) collusive security games (COSGs), a model for security games involving potential collusion among adversaries, (ii) SPECTRE-R, an algorithm to solve COSGs and break collusion assuming rational adversaries, (iii) obser- vations and analyses of adversary behavior and the underlying factors includ- ing bounded rationality, imbalanced- resource-allocation effect, coverage per- ception, and individualism / collectivism attitudes within COSGs with data from 700 human subjects, (iv) a learned human behavioral model that incorporates these factors to predict when collusion will occur, (v) SPECTRE-BR, an enhanced algorithm which optimizes against the learned behavior model to provide demon- strably better performing defender strategies against human subjects compared to SPECTRE-R.
    [Show full text]