Philosophical Review

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophical Review Philosophical Review Leibniz's Phenomenalisms Author(s): Glenn A. Hartz Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 101, No. 3 (Jul., 1992), pp. 511-549 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2186056 . Accessed: 24/01/2011 16:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org The PhilosophicalReview, Vol. 101, No. 3 (July1992) Leibniz's Phenomenalisms Glenn A. Hartz ocke's Essay is like a mail-ordercatalogue," writesP. T. Geach, "and you buy what suitsyou. To switchto a communication- theorymetaphor, the trouble is to make out which part is message and which is noise."' Something similarmight be said of the Leib- nizian corpus. It is large and diverse and rich-so rich that there are withinit tensions or outrightcontradictions. These force the commentatorto choose which items to purchase and which to let well alone. Message and noise are alarminglyoften set side by side in texts from the same or closely neighboringperiods of time, in differentdrafts of the same essay,and sometimesin the verysame draft. When one turns to Leibniz's views of matter,one is confronted withan astonishingcollection of distinctaccounts. One must adopt either (i) the so-called "Athenian" approach, drummingout all of the incompatibilityand presentinga single overarchinginclusive account, or else (ii) the "Darwinian" strategy,saying his views of 'The followingabbreviations are used in the text and footnotes:A = Robert Merrihew Adams, "Phenomenalism and Corporeal Substance in Leibniz," MidwestStudies in Philosophy8, ContemporaryPerspectives on the Historyof Philosophy,ed. P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, Jr., and H. K. Wettstein(Minneapolis: Universityof Minnesota Press, 1983), 217-57; AG = G. W. Leibniz:Philosophical Essays, ed. and trans.R. Ariew and D. Garber (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989); C = Opusculesetfragments ine'dits de Leibniz, ed. L. Couturat (Paris: Alcan, 1903); G = Die philosophischenSchriften von GottfriedWilhelm Leibniz, 7 vols., ed. C. I. Gerhardt(Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1875-90); GM = G. W. Leibniz, MathematischeSchriften, 7 vols., ed. C. I. Gerhardt (Berlin: A. Asher; Halle: H. W. Schmidt, 1849- 63); L = GottfriedWilhelm Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters,2d. ed., ed. and trans.L. E. Loemker (Dordrecht,The Netherlands: Reidel, 1969); LA = The Leibniz-ArnauldCorrespondence, ed. and trans. H. T. Mason (Manchester, England: Manchester UniversityPress, 1967; New York: Garland, 1985); P = Leibniz:Philosophical Writings, ed. G. H. R. Parkinson, trans. M. Morris and G. H. R. Parkinson (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield,1975); R = Bertrand Russell,A CriticalExposition of thePhilos- ophyof Leibniz, 2d. ed. (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1937). The quo- tation is from P. T. Geach, "Identity,"Review of Metaphysics 21 (1967-68): 12. 511 GLENN A. HARTZ matterchanged significantlyduring his lifetime.2Though the Dar- winian view applies to some of his doctrines-for example, his views of space and time3-it does not apply to his metaphysicsof matter.Instead of runninga single doctrineof body throughmany mutationsand emerging with a completelynew doctrine,Leibniz allows several doctrines to coexist and flourishtogether. The viewsare scatteredthroughout the maturecorpus, but I will note the date of textsI cite because theirinterpretation is affected cruciallyby the nature of other doctrinesLeibniz held at that time. I will follow Leibniz in using 'body' as the most general term des- ignating material objects. But I will somewhat diverge from his usage of the term 'phenomenon' and its cognates. Leibniz tends to use this as a specific,pejorative label for such ontologicallylight- weightitems as illusionsand aggregatesof substances.I will argue thata more general meaning thatLeibniz sometimesattaches to the concept of phenomena is useful as a wayof characterizinghis over- all doctrine of body. At the outsetlet us set fortha pictureof Leibniz's overall system. From the perspectiveof perceivingsubstances ("monads" or "cor- poreal substances"),there are four possible objects of perception: (1) illusions:mere appearances that fail to cohere with other objects of perception. (2) aggregates:appearances thatare misleadinglyunified-they actuallyare collectionsof an infinitenumber of substances. (3) corporealsubstances: combinations of specially-organized groups of monads/corporealsubstances (formingthe "or- ganic body") and a perfect-unity-bestowing"dominant monad." (4) substantiallybonded corporeal substances: corporeal substances that have added to them a "substantialbond" that makes them perfectlycontinuous. (4) is not supported widely in the corpus, and (1) does not play a great role in the Leibnizian program. Thus I shall concentrate mainlyon (2) and (3). 2See Hector-Neri Castafieda, "Leibniz's Concepts and Their Coin- cidence Salva Veritate,"Nouis 8 (1974): 381-98. 3See Glenn A. Hartz andJ. A. Cover, "Space and Time in the Leibnizian Metaphysic,"No Ws22 (1988): 493-519. 512 LEIBNIZ'S PHENOMENALISMS In the firstsection I clarifyLeibniz's use of 'phenomenon'. The second section is devoted to settingforth the accounts that high- light perceptual featuresas the nature of body. I explore mereo- logical accounts in the third section, followed by a supervenience construal. Finally, I combine several of the accounts to derive various versions of Leibniz's sufficientconditions for body. For most of these accounts I will ask: What conditionsmust obtain in order for there to be (i) a body at a time, and (ii) a body that endures fora period of time?More familiarand accessiblepassages will typicallybe quoted only briefly,less familiarpassages more fully. 1. 'Phenomenon' In a seminal letterof 1687 to Arnauld, Leibniz uses 'phenomena' to referto illusionsand aggregates.He saysthat if matterlacked "true unity,"it would be "a phenomenon, lacking all realityas would a coherent dream" (G 2:99/LA 122). Of aggregates he writes that though there are various "degrees of accidentalunity," such unities "are made complete only by thoughtsand appearances, like colors and other phenomena. ." (G 2:100/LA 126). How does the mind dole out unity? Our mindnotices or conceivesof certaingenuine substances which have variousmodes; thesemodes embracerelationships with other substances,from which the mindtakes the opportunity to linkthem togetherin thoughtand to enterinto the accountone name forall thesethings together, which makes for convenience in reasoning.(G 2:101/LA126; cf. G 2:97/LA121; G 2:119/LA153) There are two senses of 'phenomenon' here, both metaphysically pejorative. Either ILL: x is a phenomenon = x is an illusoryappearance, which makes it quite ontologicallyflimsy; or MEN: x is a phenomenon = x is the appearance of an aggregate of corporeal substances or monads whose unity is only apparent, since it is manufacturedby the mind, 513 GLENN A. HARTZ which makes it a bit less flimsybut neverthelessfar from funda- mental since its unity is not genuine. We can call bodies cor- responding to ILL Illusoryphenomena, and those corresponding to MEN mentalphenomena. Illusory phenomena are ontologicallynegligible, since they are nothingover and above appearances in minds. Mental phenomena belong to a higher caste, since there is somethingextra-mental- aggregates of substances-that theyrepresent. In MEN I've allowed those aggregates to be composed of either corporeal substances or monads. Why? Because Leibniz allows for the disjunction.In the Arnauld correspondence and elsewhere the constituentsare called "corporeal substances,""animals," or "living bodies" and are clearlythought of as the constituentsof phenome- nal aggregates (G 2:120/LA 154). Each corporeal substanceis com- posed of a dominant monad plus an "organic body" or "machine." Organic bodies are best thoughtof as fancyaggregates-typically collectionsof organs-that are speciallysuited to the role of acting as the body of a corporeal substance after that organic body has been joined to a dominant monad. Frankenstein's"monster body" before it came to lifewould be an example of an organic body. Like ordinaryaggregates, the organic body-which in the Arnauld ex- change Leibniz calls the "body apart,without the soul" (G 2: 100/LA 125) or "the mass of [a person's] body" (G 2:120/LA 154)-is said to be composed of other smaller corporeal substances.
Recommended publications
  • World, Senses, Human Spirit: Extrapolating the Direction from the Past Through the Present and Into the Future
    International Tinnitus Journal, Vol.ll, No.2, 103-105 (2005) EDITORIAL World, Senses, Human Spirit: Extrapolating the Direction from the Past Through the Present and Into the Future or human life, time is a specific monodirectional The Roman philosopher Lucius Aenaeus Seneca F dimension forcing us into serial development (4 Be - AD 65) then defined the phrase nihil in intel­ and behavior. We are living in the now, but we [ectu, quod non erat ante in sensu (from Naturales know that we stem from yesterday and that we are fac­ Quaestiones; "nothing can enter into the intellect if it ing the future: our tomorrow. With respect to bodily ex­ does not first pass through the gates of the senses"). In istence, every human seemingly has only one life. The this, Seneca coined the essentials of humans' communi­ human life can be regarded as constructing a wheel : We cation with the world and fellow men within the world. can imagine that year by year we fit a new spoke into We can encode from our surrounding things, facts , pic­ that circular element, a wheel that we call life and that tures, smells, odors, and sounds only after they have rolls us in only one direction, the future. Through de­ been perceived by our senses. veloping the species for many generations of humans, This really was an important philosophical step in many of these virtual wheels have been linked serially, the description of how human spirit works. All our un­ one behind the other. On the basis of culture and civili­ derstanding within our "now" needs information that zation, many humans have formed swarms of such arrives through the senses.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to Our Second Lecture on Personhood and Identity
    PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to our second lecture on personhood and identity. We’re going to begin today what will be two lectures on Rene Descartes’ thoughts on this subject. The position that is attributed to him is known as mind/body dualism. Sometimes it’s simply called the dualism for short. We need to be careful, however, because the word dualism covers a number of different philosophical positions, not always dualisms of mind and body. In other words, there are other forms of dualism that historically have been expressed. And so I will refer to his position as mind/body dualism or as Cartesian dualism as it’s sometimes also called. I said last time that Descartes is not going to talk primarily about persons. He’s going to talk about minds as opposed to bodies. But I think that as we start getting into his view, you will see where his notion of personhood arises. Clearly, Descartes is going to identify the person, the self, with the mind as opposed to with the body. This is something that I hoped you picked up in your reading and certainly that you will pick up once you read the material again after the lecture. Since I’ve already introduced Descartes’ position, let’s define it and then I’ll say a few things about Descartes himself to give you a little bit of a sense of the man and of his times. The position mind/body that’s known as mind/body dualism is defined as follows: It’s the view that the body is a physical substance — a machine, if you will — while the mind is a non-physical thinking entity which inhabits the body and is responsible for its voluntary movements.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Aristotle Plato’S “Realm of Being”
    Plato Aristotle Plato’s “Realm of Being” P.58 "The philosopher's arithmetic applies precisely and strictly only to the world of Being". I am having a hard time understanding this part which seems to be Socrate's thinking. He is taking about equal and unequal units in math- where he says that the ordinary arithmetician operates with unequal units (becoming) and the philosopher with equal units (being). My question is: why does he think this and does that tell us something about how he sees the nature of numbers ultimately? — Loreta Plato’s “Realm of Being” If the realm is meant to be unchanging, and everything has a form, I find it hard to believe that the realm of being contains every possible object for the rest of time. But when new things such as computers are conceived into this world, does the realm of forms not change to account for a new concept? —Ariel Plato’s “Realm of Being” Just the other day I was thinking about why it is we dream of perfection and yet the world is never perfect in any regard. In that sense, I can understand why Plato posits that there is such thing as a world of Being and a World of Becoming, because I recognize the distinction. However, the World of Forms still seems to be a human's idealistic dream, something we believe will never exist in the physical world but is meant to exist anyway. I'm not sure if I can believe in something that is driven by just the idea of wanting it, since we dream of it.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a REFUTATION of QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael
    1 To appear in M. O’Rourke and C. Washington (eds.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry (MIT Press) A REFUTATION OF QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University Recent defenders of reductive physicalism such as Brian Loar (1990, 1997) and John Perry (2001) have adopted an intriguing new strategy:i (1) accept as so much common sense (nearly) everything that property-dualists want to say about sensory qualia, including the central claims that sensory qualia determine ‘what it’s like’ to have a given sense experience, and that persons are directly aware of these qualia in the having of such experiences; (2) contend that while these common sense facts about qualia may show that our ways of thinking and speaking about qualia are conceptually different from our ways of thinking and speaking about physical properties of the brain, these facts do not show that sensory qualia themselves (as opposed to our ways of thinking and speaking about them) are distinct from physical properties of the brain; (3) use this contention to turn aside the few existing arguments against reductive physicalism by such property dualists as Kripke (1972), Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996); and finally (4) insist that sensory qualia are in fact just identical with physical properties of the brain, so that consequently, the facts about the sensory qualities of conscious experience are nothing over and above physical facts about the brain. I will call the view that incorporates this strategy ‘qualia-physicalism’, or ‘Q-physicalism’ for short. In this paper I will argue that Q-physicalism is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt2779p48t No online items Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Processed by David MacGill; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Finding Aid for the Gottfried 503 1 Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Manuscripts Division Los Angeles, CA Processed by: David MacGill, November 1992 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, October 2003 © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, Date (inclusive): 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 Creator: Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von, 1646-1716 Extent: 6 oversize boxes Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library. Dept. of Special Collections. Los Angeles, California 90095-1575 Abstract: Leibniz (1646-1716) was a philosopher, mathematician, and political advisor. He invented differential and integral calculus. His major writings include New physical hypothesis (1671), Discourse on metaphysics (1686), On the ultimate origin of things (1697), and On nature itself (1698). The collection consists of 35 reels of positive microfilm of more than 100,000 handwritten pages of manuscripts and letters. Physical location: Stored off-site at SRLF. Advance notice is required for access to the collection. Please contact the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Reference Desk for paging information. Language: English. Restrictions on Use and Reproduction Property rights to the physical object belong to the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • Quine and Whitehead: Ontology and Methodology 3
    McHENRY I QUINE AND WHITEHEAD: ONTOLOGY AND METHODOLOGY 3 philosophical scene as of late (e.g., deconstructionism, postmodem relativism), the and Whitehead: Ontology and gulf that separates Whitehead and analytical philosophy is not as great as it used to Quine 'be.3 Before I begin to explore the affinities, as well as some contrasts, between Methodology . Quine and Whitehead, a word of caution is in order. It is well known that Quine wrote his doctoral dissertation, "The Logic of Sequences: A Generalization of LeemonMcHenry Principia Mathematica," under Whitehead's direction.4 Quine also took two of Whitehead's seminars at Harvard,"Science and the Modem World" and "Cosmol­ I LEEMON McHENRY reaches philosophy at Loyola Marymount University, Los ogies Ancient and Modem," but he says that he "responded little to these courses" Angeles, CA 90045, E-mail: [email protected] and "took refuge in his relatively mathematical material on 'extensive abstrac­ tion. "'s Despite Quine's statement that he "retained a vivid sense of being in the presence of the great," he does not acknowledge any philosophical influence from · Introduction . the ph!losoph!es o!'W.V . Qu�e an d Whitehead. Rather, Camap and Russell are cited as the inspirations of Quine's The very idea· of a basis for comparing . , mcluding Qume himself. early development. A.N. Whitehead may be surprising to most philosophe� . philosophy two completely Both produced systems of thought that have taken m When Quine overlapped with Whitehead at Harvard, Whitehead was deeply at the forefron: of c�ntemp�­ involved in working out the details of his metaphysics of process--a philosophic different directions.
    [Show full text]
  • Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead
    CREATIVITY IN WIDTEHEAD'S l\1ETAPHYSICS CREATIVITY IN THE METAPHYSICS OF ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD By JEFFREY A. MCPHERSON, B.A.(Hons.) A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts © Copyright by Jeffrey A. McPherson, SEPTEMBER, 1996 MASTER OF ARTS (1996) McMaster University (Religious Studies) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead. AUTHOR: Jeffrey A. McPherson, B.A.(Hons.) (York University) SUPERVISOR: Dr. J.C. Robertson, Jr. NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 127 ii ABSTRACT This is a study of the role that creativity plays in the metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead ( 1861-1947). As the title generally indicates, there are two parts to this project. The first part develops an understanding of Whitehead's metaphysics through the careful analysis of two key texts, namely Religion in the Making ( 1926), and Process and Reality (1929). The second part examines and carefully analyses the role that creativity plays within this metaphysic. The second part focuses on two questions. The first question considers the ontological status which creativity requires to perform the role which it is given within the metaphysical system. The second question discusses implications of this status for creativity's relationship to God. This second section further discusses the implications of such an understanding of "process theology" for Christian theology in general. Specifically it comments on the various responses of theology to creatio ex nihilo and the problem of evil. This thesis concludes that creativity functions as an ultimate explanatory principle in Whitehead's metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Art3 Frapolli SUBJECT NATURALISM FINAL
    Análisis. Revista de investigación filosfófica, Vol. 1, nº 1, 2014, pp. 41-67 YOU AND ME BABY AIN’T NOTHING BUT MAMMALS. SUBJECT NATURALISM AND DEFAULT POSITIONS1 María J. Frápolli RESUMEN Este artículo discute el problema de la localización, tal como Price lo ha definido. En el se distinguen diferentes versiones de naturalismo y se defiende el naturalismo del sujeto. Se asume que el sistema de conceptos humano se ha desarrollado en interacción con el medio natural y social. Por esta razón no podemos evitar ser realistas y representacionalistas por defecto. Las afirmaciones básicas del realismo, el representatcionalismo y la teoría de la verdad como correspondencia son difícilmente rechazables, y esto explica el aire de artificiosidad que acompaña a las posiciones anti- realistas. Sin embargo las posiciones por defecto no apoyan en absoluto a sus versiones filosóficamente desarrolladas. Estas son incompatibles con una visión naturalista sobre la realidad, el significado y la verdad. PALABRAS CLAVE: Correspondentismo por defecto, naturalismo, naturalismo del sujeto, realismo por defecto, representacionalismo por defecto, teoría de la verdad como correspondencia, teoría prooracional de la verdad, verdad aristotélica ABSTRACT This paper deals with Price’s placement problem. In it, different versions of naturalism are distinguished and subject naturalism is defended. It is assumed that human conceptual system has evolved as a result of humans relations with the natural 1 My colleagues Manuel de Pinedo and Neftalí Villanueva have read versions of this paper and made insightful suggestions. I am also grateful to the Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación del Gobierno de España, (project FFI2010-15704), the Consejería de Innovación de la Junta de Andalucía (project HUM-04099), and the Plan Propio of the University of Granada that have supported this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Bodily Resurrection Compatible with Materialism? Lucienne Altman-Newell Scripps College
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2017 Is Bodily Resurrection Compatible with Materialism? Lucienne Altman-Newell Scripps College Recommended Citation Altman-Newell, Lucienne, "Is Bodily Resurrection Compatible with Materialism?" (2017). Scripps Senior Theses. 1067. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1067 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IS BODILY RESURRECTION COMPATIBLE WITH MATERIALISM? by LUCIENNE ALTMAN-NEWELL SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR AVNUR PROFESSOR WEINBERG APRIL 18, 2017 Many thanks to my parents, Micah Altman and Pat Newell for their support; my professors—especially Professors Avnur, Weinberg, and Alwishah—for guiding me through my college years; my love, Jocelyn Gardner, for inspiration and motivation; my friends and treatment team for getting me through the year in more or less one piece; and the Mellon Undergraduate Research Fellowship for generous summer funding. It’s been one hell of a ride… 1 Table of Contents Presentation of the Question ........................................................................................................... 4 An Introduction to Materialism and its Problems ..........................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Densephysnet: Learning Dense Physical Object Representations Via Multi-Step Dynamic Interactions
    DensePhysNet: Learning Dense Physical Object Representations via Multi-step Dynamic Interactions Zhenjia Xu1;2, Jiajun Wu2, Andy Zeng3;4, Joshua B. Tenenbaum2;5, Shuran Song3;4;6 1Shanghai Jiao Tong University 2Massachusetts Institute of Technology 3Princeton University 4Google 5MIT Center for Brains, Minds and Machines 6Columbia University Abstract—We study the problem of learning physical object Multi-Step Dynamic Interactions with Scenes of Multiple Objects representations for robot manipulation. Understanding object physics is critical for successful object manipulation, but also challenging because physical object properties can rarely be inferred from the object’s static appearance. In this paper, we propose DensePhysNet, a system that actively executes a sequence of dynamic interactions (e.g., sliding and colliding), and uses a deep predictive model over its visual observations to learn dense, pixel-wise representations that reflect the physical properties of Decoding observed objects. Our experiments in both simulation and real Object plastic settings demonstrate that the learned representations carry rich Properties metal wood physical information, and can directly be used to decode physical Material Mass Friction object properties such as friction and mass. The use of dense representation enables DensePhysNet to generalize well to novel Unknown scenes with more objects than in training. With knowledge of Application object Physics object physics, the learned representation also leads to more in Control Engine accurate and efficient manipulation in downstream tasks than Target location the state-of-the-art. Video is available at http://zhenjiaxu.com/ Dense Physical Object Representations Object Sliding Novel Tasks DensePhysNet Fig. 1. Our goal is to build a robotic system that learns a dense physical I.I NTRODUCTION object representation from a few dynamic interactions with objects.
    [Show full text]
  • Physical Object
    A version of this article appears in the 2nd edition of Blackwell’s A Companion to Metaphysics (edited by Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa, and Gary S. Rosenkrantz), pp. 486-489. Physical Object Ned Markosian Physical objects are the most familiar of all objects, and yet the concept of a physical object remains elusive. Any six-year-old can give you a dozen examples of physical objects, and most people with at least one undergraduate course in philosophy can also give examples of non-physical objects. But if asked to produce a definition of ‘physical object’ that adequately captures the distinction between the physical and the non- physical, the average person can offer little more than hand-waving. Among metaphysicians, on the other hand, it is easy to find an account of what physical objects are. Too easy, in fact: if you ask ten metaphysicians, you are likely to get ten different accounts. So what exactly are physical objects? We might be tempted to say, with George Berkeley, that physical objects are the things that can be sensed. But sensed by whom? Different beings have different sensory abilities; yet we don’t want the notion of a physical object to be a relativistic one (especially considering the crucial role played by the concept in various philosophical debates, including the longstanding controversy over physicalism, the thesis that the only concrete objects in the world are purely physical objects). Perhaps, then, we should say that physical objects can be sensed by some sentient being or other. But if we say this then we run the risk of making the concept hopelessly broad – for is it not possible for a disembodied mind to sense itself, or even another mind? And might it not be possible for a creature with super-sensory powers to sense such seemingly non-physical entities as propositions? Perhaps the most popular view of physical objects among philosophers working on topics like physicalism and the mind-body problem is that physical objects are the objects studied by physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Bound States and the Special Composition Question
    Contribution to: Proceedings EPSA 2015 Bound States and the Special Composition Question Penultimate draft. Please only cite the final version, published in ‘Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science - EPSA15 Dusseldorf’, eds. Michela Massimi, Jan-Willem Romeijn. and Gerhard Schurz. KERRY MCKENZIE Department of Philosophy University of California, San Diego USA [email protected] & F.A. MULLER Faculty of Philosophy, Erasmus University Rotterdam, and Faculty of Science Utrecht University, The Netherlands [email protected] September 2016 Key Words Composition, mereology, part-whole relation, naturalised metaphysics. Abstract. The Special Composition Question asks under what conditions a plurality of objects form another, composite object. We propose a condition grounded in our scientific knowledge of physical reality, the essence of which is that objects form a composite object when and only when they are in a bound state – whence our Bound State Proposal. We provide a variety of reasons in favour of a mereological theory that accommodates our Proposal. We consider but reject another proposal, which is quantum-physical in nature: the Entanglement Proposal.We close by responding to Teller’s ‘Suit Objection’. 1. Preamble P.van Inwagen (1987, p. 23) raised the question what condition physical objects have to satisfy in order to compose another physical object. Three answers to this so-called Special Composition Question (whence- forth: the Question) have been considered and debated: merelogical Nihilism, according to which there are no composite objects, only elementary particles; mereological Universalism, according to which any collection of physical objects compose another physical object; and Van Inwagen’s moderate answer (1990: 82), according to which physical objects compose another one iff their activity constitutes a life.
    [Show full text]