Genealogical Debunking Arguments, Moral Realism, and the Possibility of Moral Knowledge

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Genealogical Debunking Arguments, Moral Realism, and the Possibility of Moral Knowledge Taking the Helm: Genealogical Debunking Arguments, Moral Realism, and the Possibility of Moral Knowledge by Joshua D. McBee A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland April 2019 © Joshua McBee 2019 All Rights Reserved Abstract Genealogical debunking arguments aim to show that, given their provenance, none of our moral beliefs are justified, at least assuming moral realism. In particular, they claim that this is so because the best, complete explanation of why we hold the moral beliefs we do neither presupposes nor entails their truth. I dispute this explanatory claim, suggesting instead that, in at least some cases, the best explanation of our beliefs must appeal to our capacity to acquire moral knowledge through reflection. To defend this suggestion, I respond to three different rejoinders debunkers might offer. One of these contends that the proposed explanation is redundant: if we want to explain why someone judges some action wrong, all we need to know is the character of their moral sensibilities. Two other rejoinders appeal to general skeptical challenges. According to the first, if realism is true, the evidence available to us in reflection necessarily underdetermines the truth of our ethical beliefs. Like the so-called Benacerraf-Field challenge to mathematical platonism from which it derives, the second challenge involves two distinct charges: first, that knowledge requires there be a causal or explanatory connection between our beliefs and the facts that realism precludes, and second, that realists cannot explain our reliability in ethics. Making novel use of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s remarks about following rules, I argue that that each of the first two rejoinders rests on a confused view about the ways we are liable to go wrong in ethical reflection. In response to the third rejoinder, I ii argue that while the no-accident condition on knowledge is indeed best understood in explanatory terms, realism does not preclude the possibility that our beliefs might satisfy this condition on knowledge; in addition, I explain how realists can explain our reliability in ethics. In all of these cases, moreover, I suggest that the responses I outline are open only to proponents of a deflationary form of realism that, following Amie Thomasson, I call “simple realism,” conceding to debunkers that their arguments are likely unanswerable by proponents of more inflationary or so-called “robust” forms of realism. Committee: Dean Moyar (primary advisor), Richard Bett (second reader), Chris Lebron, Mark Lance, and Andrew Miller (chair) iii For Dot and Nini iv Acknowledgements You could say I first began thinking about the issues I take up here in fall 2012, when I first encountered Street’s Darwinian Dilemma while reading Parfit’s On What Matters. But I’ve been thinking about much of this in one way or another for far longer. Maybe it would be best to date it back to Christmas 2007, when my brother recommended a book from an introductory philosophy class he had taken the semester before, Russ Shafer-Landau’s Whatever Happened to Good and Evil? Or maybe it would be better to say I started thinking along these lines a couple of years later, in early 2009, when I had my first encounter with Wittgenstein’s later work in Carl Sachs’ epistemology class at the University of North Texas. In any case, these things have been on my mind a long time, and I’ve acquired many debts along the way. In particular, I want to thank Dean Moyar and Richard Bett, both for providing invaluable verbal and written feedback and for supporting me in many other ways throughout the process; the Johns Hopkins University Department of Philosophy for funding, especially for the Barnhart and Sachs dissertation completion fellowships that gave me the time I needed to pull my thoughts together during the final stages of the project; Carl Sachs for encouraging my interest in Wittgenstein all those years ago and for his friendship and mentorship ever since; Ian Moore for helpful v discussion of Blood Meridian, as well as for a philosophical friendship that has been a consistent delight for more than ten years now; Steven Gross for invaluable discussions of contextualism, nonsense, and realism; Louis Gularte, Mario Brandhorst, and other audience members who provided helpful feedback at the 3rd conference on Wittgensteinian Approaches in Moral Philosophy in Leuven; and, for helpful discussion and reading recommendations at various points, Mark Lance, Tom Wilk, Nandi Theunissen, Elanor Taylor, Justin Bledin, Kevin Powell, Itai Marom, Alex James, Patrick O’Donnell, Daniel Estrada, Dan Korman, Kieran Setiya, Josef Simpson, Nikola Andonovski, Micah Lott, David Killoren, Cara Cummings, and Sharon Street. Of course, a project this size doesn’t take place in a vacuum. It has been a part of my life for many years now and was only possible because I managed to make it into graduate school in the first place and, thereafter, stick with it. Many people helped make all that possible. In particular I want to mention Adam Reid, who was kind enough to drink and commiserate with me after my disastrous first topical; David Jacobs, whose friendship and lifting tips have helped keep me sane; Tim Lowery, who has been a reliable companion for twenty years; Angela Hvitved and Damian Dalle Nogare, with whom I’m so glad we’ve become such good friends; and many other friends whose company has sustained me in various ways throughout the process, including David Lindeman, Alex, Luise, Anton, Aimee, Richard and Megan Lowery, Richard Teague, Shelley, Mike, Sandy, Lisa, Dan, Kasey, and Wes. Finally, I want to thank my family. In particular, I want to thank Ingrid, Jose, Miren, Sabina, and Amelia, whose presence in my life over the last few years has been a joy; my Texas family generally, but especially Mom, Jonathan, Hillary, and Hailey, who have been so consistently supportive and encouraging, and Papa, the first Dr. McBee, and to whom all the cowboy examples are a sort of tribute; and, most importantly, I want to thank Erika, without whose love, support, and encouragement I may well have left the program a long time ago, and without whom life would undoubtedly be worse. vi Writing this, I am touched by how many people have gone out of their way to help me in one way or another or in some other way supported or encouraged me these past eight years. From the bottom of my heart, thank you all. vii Table of Contents Abstract ii Dedication iv Acknowledgments v Introduction 1 1 The Debunking Challenge 6 2 How to Begin at the Beginning 48 3 Making Your Own Epistemic Luck 106 4 Objections and Replies 137 Conclusion 166 Bibliography 171 Biographical Note 182 viii Introduction But then with me the horrid doubt always arises whether the convictions of man’s mind, which has been developed from the mind of the lower animals, are of any value or at all trustworthy. Would any one trust in the convictions of a monkey’s mind, if there are any convictions in such a mind? -Darwin to W. Graham, July 3rd, 18811 Though he does express the thought in an unusually colorful way, Darwin was neither the first nor the last to think facts about their provenance give us reason to be suspicious of our beliefs. Nietzsche’s claims in On the Genealogy of Morality that Christian moral beliefs originated in ressentiment are meant to undermine those beliefs, just as Freud’s claim in The Future of an Illusion that religious beliefs are a form of wish fulfillment are meant to undermine them. Similarly, Marx’s claim in The German Ideology that “the ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas” is meant to 1 Darwin correspondence project number 13230, quoted at Fraser, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments and the Reliability of Moral Cognition,” p. 457. 1 debunk prevailing moral, political, and economic ideas by suggesting that they reflect, not moral, political, and economic reality, but the class interests of the bourgeoisie.2 More recently, several philosophers, most prominently Sharon Street and Richard Joyce, have followed in Darwin’s footsteps, suggesting that their evolutionary origins should lead us to doubt our moral beliefs or to regard them as unjustified.3 In all of these cases, the impetus is an observation about the source of our beliefs or about the influences that shape or explain why we hold the beliefs we do. Notice, though, that the mere fact that our beliefs have a history or are shaped in all sorts of ways does not by itself entail that they are untrustworthy, unjustified, or in some other way epistemically suspect. Far from it; in fact, information about the sources of or influences on our beliefs can often vindicate or justify them. Suppose, for instance, that a friend tells me the twin prime conjecture is false. Though I am not familiar with the details, I am under the impression that twin prime conjecture is an unproven mathematical theorem, and since I have no reason to think my non-mathematician friend knows anything more about the conjecture than I do, I might wonder whether she has good reason to believe as she does. However, were she to explain that earlier in the day she had read an article in The Washington Post in which a prominent mathematician claimed to have disproven the conjecture, I would not only cease to be suspicious but would come to regard my friend’s belief as justified and likely true. In other cases, of course, information about the provenance of some belief does serve to undermine it.
Recommended publications
  • Annual Report 2020 1
    ACLS Annual Report 2020 1 AMERICAN COUNCIL OF LEARNED SOCIETIES Annual Report 2020 2 ACLS Annual Report 2020 Table of Contents Mission and Purpose 1 Message from the President 2 Who We Are 6 Year in Review 12 President’s Report to the Council 18 What We Do 23 Supporting Our Work 70 Financial Statements 84 ACLS Annual Report 2020 1 Mission and Purpose The American Council of Learned Societies supports the creation and circulation of knowledge that advances understanding of humanity and human endeavors in the past, present, and future, with a view toward improving human experience. SUPPORT CONNECT AMPLIFY RENEW We support humanistic knowledge by making resources available to scholars and by strengthening the infrastructure for scholarship at the level of the individual scholar, the department, the institution, the learned society, and the national and international network. We work in collaboration with member societies, institutions of higher education, scholars, students, foundations, and the public. We seek out and support new and emerging organizations that share our mission. We commit to expanding the forms, content, and flow of scholarly knowledge because we value diversity of identity and experience, the free play of intellectual curiosity, and the spirit of exploration—and above all, because we view humanistic understanding as crucially necessary to prototyping better futures for humanity. It is a public good that should serve the interests of a diverse public. We see humanistic knowledge in paradoxical circumstances: at once central to human flourishing while also fighting for greater recognition in the public eye and, increasingly, in institutions of higher education.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Asya Passinsky
    Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Asya Passinsky Visiting Assistant Professor, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill “NORM AND OBJECT: A NORMATIVE HYLOMORPHIC THEORY OF SOCIAL OBJECTS” Thursday, March 4, 2021, 5:00-6:00 pm Via Zoom Draft, February 19, 2021. For UCLA Workshop. Please Don’t Cite Or Quote Without Permission. Norm and Object: A Normative Hylomorphic Theory of Social Objects Asya Passinsky ABSTRACT: This paper is an investigation into the metaphysics of social objects such as political borders, states, and organizations. I articulate a metaphysical puzzle concerning such objects and then propose a novel account of social objects that provides a solution to the puzzle. The basic idea behind the puzzle is that under appropriate circumstances, seemingly concrete social objects can apparently be created by acts of agreement, decree, declaration, or the like. Yet there is reason to believe that no concrete object can be created in this way. The central idea of my positive account is that social objects have a normative component to them, and seemingly concrete social objects have both normative and material components. I develop this idea more rigorously using resources from the Aristotelian hylomorphic tradition. The resulting normative hylomorphic account, I argue, solves the puzzle by providing a satisfying explanation of creation-by-agreement and the like, while at the same time avoiding the difficulties facing extant accounts of social objects. 1. Introduction This paper is an investigation into the metaphysics of social objects such as political borders, states, and organizations. Roughly speaking, social objects are things that can be created through the performance of social acts such as agreement, decree, declaration, or the like.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics, History, Phenomenology 341
    METAPHYSICS,HISTORY,PHENOMENOLOGY Kris McDaniel Abstract: There are three interconnected goals of this paper. The first is to articulate and motivate a view of the methodology for doing metaphysics that is broadly phenomenological in the sense of Husserl circa the Logical Investigations. The second is to articulate an argument for the importance of studying the history of philosophy when doing metaphysics that is in accordance with this methodology. The third is to confront this methodology with a series of objections and determine how well it fares in light of them. 1 Introduction Here is an easy observation. In one respect, we all know the methodology of philosophy as it is currently practiced today, at least among large portions of the ‘analytic tradition.’ Some person—sometimes it is more than one person—has an idea. She talks about it with colleagues or friends, either in person or by email. Eventually it is written up as a talk or as a paper, and either way is vetted in some sort of public venue. If things go well for her and her idea, the written thing eventually appears as a publication in a journal, book chapter, or whatnot; if things go not so well, it ends up as a blog post. Either way, other philosophers might eventually read the written thing, and might then have some new ideas as a consequence. Is there a plausible explanation of how this way of doing things could be justified or reasonable given that the goal of philosophy is the acquisition of philosophical knowledge, that is, the acquisition of true and appropriately warranted beliefs about characteristically philosophical questions?1 Call such an explanation a justificatory story.
    [Show full text]
  • A Tentative Theory for Chinese Contemporary Art Peng
    paths to the middle 271 PATHS TO THE MIDDLE: A TENTATIVE THEORY FOR CHINESE CONTEMPORARY ART Peng Feng Chinese contemporary art can be divided into three stages: following the Other, being valuated by the Other, and finally getting its identity.1 Only in the third stage can Chinese contemporary art have its self- awareness or self-understanding, i.e., can Chinese contemporary art realize itself as Chinese contemporary art. However, according to Hegel and Danto, the history of art is at an end as soon as art has real- ized itself. By the same token, does Chinese contemporary art come to an end since it has realized itself in the third stage? Does art or Chinese or contemporary come to an end? What is the difference between them? If art comes to an end, it, according to Hegel and Danto, is sub- lated into philosophy.2 If Chinese art comes to an end, it, according to the scholars who advocate trans-cultural aesthetics, is substituted for by a new International Style.3 If contemporary art comes to an end, it, according to the scholars who advocate evolutionary aesthetics, welcomes “the return of beauty”.4 I propose to discuss the first issue in this paper and leave the others for other papers. If what comes to an end is not Chinese but contemporary art, it should be sublated into Chinese traditional philosophy. Ironically, once contemporary art takes shelter in Chinese traditional philosophy, it can refuse to come to an end and welcome a new beginning. With 1 Li Xiaofeng, “Preface for Chenxiang Exhibition,” in Chenxiang Catalogue (Shanghai: Shanghai Shipingxian Gallery).
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy California State University, Northridge
    RONALD McINTYRE Professor Emeritus Department of Philosophy California State University, Northridge EDUCATION Ph.D. (philosophy), Stanford University, 1970 Dissertation: “Husserl and Referentiality: The Role of the Noema as an Intensional Entity” Dissertation Committee: Dagfinn Føllesdal, John Goheen, Jaakko Hintikka (Principal Adviser) M.A. (philosophy), Florida State University, 1966 Thesis: “On the Criterion of Empirical Meaningfulness” Thesis Director: Robert W. Beard B.S. (physics), Wake Forest College, 1964, magna cum laude TEACHING POSITIONS Professor, California State University, Northridge, 1981-2010 Associate Professor, California State University, Northridge, 1977-81. Assistant Professor, Case Western Reserve University, 1970-77. Lecturer, International Summer School in Philosophy, Bolzano (Bozen), Italy, 1990. Visiting Professor, University of Colorado, spring 1982. Visiting Assistant Professor, Stanford University, summer 1971. Visiting Instructor, Wake Forest University, summer 1967 and summer 1968. ADMINISTRATIVE AND LEADERSHIP EXPERIENCE Faculty President / Faculty Senate Chair, CSUN, 2004-06. Chair, Department of Philosophy, CSUN, 1996-2002. Coordinator, Instructional Development Program (ancestor of the Center for Innovative & Engaged Learning Opportunities), CSUN, 1988-90. PUBLICATIONS Books • Husserl and Intentionality: A Study of Mind, Meaning, and Language, with David W. Smith (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, Synthese Library, 1982), xxiii + 423 pp. Articles, Reviews, Editorships • “’We-Subjectivity’: Husserl on Community and Communal Constitution,” in Intersubjectivity and Objectivity in Adam Smith and Edmund Husserl, ed. by Christel Fricke and Dagfinn Føllesdal (Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, 2012), pp. 61-92. • Review of Science and the Life-World: Essays on Husserl’s “Crisis of European Sciences”, ed. by David Hyder and Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, July 7, 2010 (http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=20447).
    [Show full text]
  • 2021 APA Central Division Meeting Program
    The American Philosophical Association CENTRAL DIVISION ONE HUNDRED EIGHTEENTH ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM VIRTUAL MEETING FEBRUARY 22 – 27, 2021 Mention coupon code ZAPC21 and receive a 30% discount on all pb & a 50% discount on all hc only Offer good until 3/27/21 Order online: www.sunypress.edu Order by phone: 877.204.6073 or 703.661.1575 Critique in German American Endangered Philosophy Aesthetics Excellence From Kant Theory and Practice On the Political to Critical Theory Walter B. Gulick and Philosophy of Aristotle María del Rosario Acosta Gary Slater, editors Pierre Pellegrin López and J. Colin Translated by McQuillan, editors John Dewey’s Anthony Preus Later Logical Hegel on Tragedy Theory The Disintegration and Comedy James Scott Johnston of Community New Essays On Jorge Portilla’s Social Mark Alznauer, editor The Rorty- and Political Philosophy, Available May 2021 Habermas Debate With Translations of Toward Freedom Selected Essays NEW IN PAPER as Responsibility Carlos Alberto Sánchez Hyperthematics Marcin Kilanowski and Francisco Gallegos The Logic of Value Available May 2021 Marc M. Anderson Religion within Decolonizing the Limits Living Landscapes American of History Alone Meditations on the Philosophy Pragmatic Historicism Five Elements in Hindu, Corey McCall and and the Future Buddhist, and Jain Yogas Phillip McReynolds, of Theology Christopher Key Chapple editors Demian Wheeler The Primary Way Image and Contribution to the Philosophy of Yijing Argument in Correction of the Chung-ying Cheng Foreword by Plato’s Republic Public’s Judgments Robert Cummings Marina Berzins McCoy on the French Neville Revolution NEW IN PAPER J. G. Fichte Human Beings Metaphysics Editied, Translated and or Human of Goodness with an Introduction by Becomings? Harmony and Form, Jeffrey Church and A Conversation with Beauty and Art, Anna Marisa Schön Confucianism on the Obligation and Concept of Person Personhood, Flourishing Peter D.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Explanations for Modal Normativists
    Locke, T. 2020. Metaphysical Explanations for Modal Normativists. Metaphysics, 3(1), pp. 33–54. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/met.35 RESEARCH Metaphysical Explanations for Modal Normativists Theodore Locke Concordia University, CA [email protected] I expand modal normativism, a theory of metaphysical modality, to give a normativist account of metaphysical explanation. According to modal normativism, basic modal claims do not have a descriptive function, but instead have the normative function of enabling language users to express semantic rules that govern the use of ordinary non-modal vocabulary. However, a worry for modal normativism is that it doesn’t keep up with all of the important and interest- ing metaphysics we can do by giving and evaluating metaphysical explanations. So, I advance modal normativism by arguing that metaphysical explanations also have a normative rather than descriptive function. In particular, non-causal explanatory claims have formal and semantic prop- erties that make them expressively stricter than basic modal claims and so are better suited to express fine-grained aspects of semantic rules. A major payoff of my normativist account of metaphysical explanations is that it yields a plausible story about how we come to evaluate and know metaphysical explanations—we do this primarily by conceptual analysis. I also respond to a number of objections, including the objection that the epistemic payoffs of my view are not worth the metaphysical costs. Keywords: grounding; explanation; modality; essence; real definition; normativism; quasi- realism; metaphysical laws 1. Introduction Metaphysical explanations seem to concern non-causal, constitutive connections between things that are the case. For example, a metaphysical explanation of why a ball is red isn’t necessarily concerned with how the ball was causally manufactured but with what metaphysically makes it the case that the ball is red, e.g., that the ball is crimson rather than cerulean.
    [Show full text]
  • FOP Newsletter Fall 2015.Pub
    FRIENDS OF FALL 2015 NEWSLETTER philosophy W ear Alumni and Friends of Philosophy, It is, once again, a sincere pleasure to greet you, and share some news from the Department of Philosophy. This has been another terrific year. The big news is that two fantasc colleagues have joined the department: Pro- fessor Magdalena Balcerak Jackson and Professor Brendan Balcerak Jackson. Magdalena’s work focuses on philosophy of mind and epistemology, with parcular aenon to imaginaon and reasoning. But her philosophical interests are broad and span all key areas of philosophy, including philosophy of language, philosophy of science, and aesthecs (among other areas). She has already developed a number of new courses for the department, including a course on food ethics that promises to be a big hit. Brendan’s work focuses on philosophy of language, epistemology and metaphysics. His research interests are also very broad, and include philosophy of mind, the history of analyc philosophy, and logic. A significant fact about Brendan’s work is that it is informed by theorecal linguiscs, in parcular generave syntax, semancs, and prag- macs. This provides him with a disncve way of addressing philosophical issues. Please join me in welcoming both of them to the department. Our colleagues connue to be extremely producve. Professor Brit Brogaard published two books: On RomanƟc Love (Oxford University Press, 2015) and The Superhuman Mind (Hudson Street Press, 2015). Both aracted significant aenon well beyond the usual philosophical circles. Professor Eli Chudnoff’s latest book, CogniƟve Phenomenology (Routledge, 2015), has also been published. It’s the first book-length treatment of this important field.
    [Show full text]
  • Sara J. Bernstein Curriculum Vitae
    Sara J. Bernstein Curriculum Vitae University of Notre Dame email: [email protected] Department of Philosophy 100 Malloy Hall Notre Dame, IN 46556 http://duke.edu/~sb192/ AREA OF SPECIALIZATION Metaphysics AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Law, Nineteenth Century Philosophy, Philosophy of Computing, Feminist Philosophy EMPLOYMENT Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Fall 2016- Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Duke University, 2010-2016 Andrew W. Mellon Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Duke University, 2013-2014 EDUCATION Ph.D., Philosophy, University of Arizona, 2010 Dissertation: Essays on Overdetermination Directors: L.A. Paul, Terence Horgan M.A., Philosophy, University of Arizona, 2008 A.B., (Honors), Philosophy, University of Chicago, 2004 PUBLICATIONS (forthcoming) “Causal and Moral Indeterminacy”, Ratio (forthcoming) “Omission Impossible”, Philosophical Studies (forthcoming) “Free Will and Mental Quausation” (with Jessica Wilson), Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (Publications, continued) (forthcoming) “Causal Idealism”, Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, eds. Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenny Pearce, Oxford University Press (2016) “Overdetermination Underdetermined”, Erkenntnis 81:1 17-40 (2015) “Nowhere Man: Time Travel and Spatial Location”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 39:1 158-168 (2015) “Time Travel and the Movable Present”, Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen (ed. John Keller, Oxford University Press) (2015) “The Metaphysics of Omissions”, Philosophy Compass 10:3 208-218 (2015) “A Closer Look at Trumping”, Acta Analytica 30:1 41-57 (2014) “What Causally Insensitive Events Tell Us About Overdetermination”, Philosophia 42:4 935-948 (2014) “Two Problems for Proportionality about Omissions”, Dialectica 68:3 429-441 (2014) “Omissions as Possibilities”, Philosophical Studies 167:1 1-23 Book Reviews Review of S.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl's Philosophy of the Categories and His Development
    grazer philosophische studien 94 (2017) 460-493 brill.com/gps Husserl’s Philosophy of the Categories and His Development toward Absolute Idealism Clinton Tolley University of California, San Diego [email protected] Abstract In recent work, Amie Thomasson has sought to develop a new approach to the philoso- phy of the categories which is metaphysically neutral between traditional realist and conceptualist approaches, and which has its roots in the ‘correlationalist’ approach to categories put forward in Husserl’s writings in the 1900s–1910s and systematically charted over the past few decades by David Woodruff Smith in his studies of Husserl’s philosophy. Here the author aims to provide a recontextualization and critical as- sessment of correlationalism in a Husserlian vein. To this end, the author presents, first, the reasons why, later in his life, Husserl himself found his earlier treatment of categories philosophically naive, and why he increasingly advocated for a more genetic-teleological account. The author then draws upon arguments made a century earlier by Schelling and Hegel, in criticism of Fichte, to point up what might remain philosophically unsatisfying about even the post-correlationalist genetic position of the later Husserl, in light of the pronounced trend in Husserl’s own development, on the questions of reason and spirit, toward absolute idealism. Keywords Husserl – Kant – Hegel – phenomenology – idealism – categories – German philosophy – correlationalism – metametaphysics 1 Introduction: A Neo-Husserlian Doctrine of the Categories? Recently it has been suggested by Amie Thomasson that Husserl’s approach to the philosophy of categories during the 1900s–1910s is one that might offer a © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2017 | doi 10.1163/18756735-09403009 <UN> Husserl’s Philosophy of the Categories 461 promising third alternative that brings together some of the key commitments of both traditional realist and traditional conceptualist accounts, while avoid- ing some of their more controversial aspects (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Sara J. Bernstein Curriculum Vitae
    Sara J. Bernstein Curriculum Vitae University of Notre Dame email: [email protected] Department of Philosophy 100 Malloy Hall Notre Dame, IN 46556 http://www3.nd.edu/~sbernste/ AREA OF SPECIALIZATION Metaphysics AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Law, Ethics, Philosophy of Science, Feminist Philosophy EMPLOYMENT University of Notre Dame Thomas J. and Robert T. Rolfs Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2018-2021 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Fall 2016-present Affiliate, Gender Studies, 2017- Duke University Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 2010-2016 Andrew W. Mellon Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 2013-2014 EDUCATION Ph.D., Philosophy, University of Arizona, 2010 Dissertation: Essays on Overdetermination Directors: L.A. Paul, Terence Horgan M.A., Philosophy, University of Arizona, 2008 A.B. (Honors), Philosophy, University of Chicago, 2004 1 PUBLICATIONS (Forthcoming) “Could a Middle Level be the Most Fundamental?”, Philosophical Studies (Forthcoming) “Moral Luck and Deviant Causation”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy (Forthcoming) “David Lewis’ Theories of Causation and his Influence”, Cambridge History of Philosophy, ed. Kelly Michael Becker, Cambridge University Press (2018) “Causal Idealism”, Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, eds. Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenny Pearce, Oxford University Press, 217-230 (2017) “Causal Proportions and Moral Responsibility”, Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, ed. David Shoemaker, Oxford University Press, 165-182 (2017) “Intuitions and the Metaphysics of Causation”, Experimental Metaphysics,
    [Show full text]
  • New Waves in Musical Ontology
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2008 New Waves in Musical Ontology Andrew Kania Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Kania, A. (2008). New waves in musical ontology. In K. Stock & K. Thomson-Jones (Eds.), New waves in aesthetics (pp. 20-40). Palgrave Macmillan. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. New Waves in Musical Ontology Andrew Kania [Andrew Kania, “New Waves in Musical Ontology” in New Waves in Aesthetics, ed. Kathleen Stock and Katherine Thomson-Jones (Palgrave Macmillan, 2008) pp. 20-40; reproduced with permission of Palgrave Macmillan. This extract is taken from the author's original manuscript and has not been edited. The definitive, published, version of record is available here: https://www.palgrave.com/gp/book/9780230220461. Please cite only the published version.] Since analytic aesthetics began, around fifty years ago, music has perhaps been the art most discussed by philosophers. This interest is reflected even in the contents of this volume, with three chapters devoted to specifically musical issues, with other arts getting at most one chapter to themselves. The reasons for philosophers’ attraction to music as a subject are obscure, but one element is surely that music, as a non-verbal, multiple- instance, performance art, raises at least as many questions about expression, ontology, interpretation, and value as any other art – questions that often seem more puzzling than those raised by other arts.
    [Show full text]