Heideggerian Marxism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Heideggerian Marxism 1 2 3 4 5 Heideggerian Marxism 6 7 8 9 10 11 [First Page] 12 [-1], (1) 13 14 15 Lines: 0 to 16 ——— 17 * 429.1755pt 18 ——— 19 Normal Page 20 * PgEnds: PageB 21 22 [-1], (1) 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 european horizons 2 Series Editors 3 Richard Golsan, 4 Texas A&M University 5 6 Christopher Flood, 7 University of Surrey 8 Jeffrey T. Schnapp, 9 Stanford University 10 11 Richard Wolin, 12 The Graduate Center, [-2], (2) 13 City University of New York 14 15 Lines: 15 16 ——— 17 * 321.29399pt 18 ——— 19 Normal P 20 * PgEnds: 21 22 [-2], (2) 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 Heideggerian 6 7 8 9 Marxism 10 11 12 [-3], (3) 13 14 15 Lines: 36 to 16 ——— 17 0.78pt PgV 18 Herbert Marcuse ——— 19 Normal Page 20 * PgEnds: PageB 21 22 [-3], (3) 23 24 25 Edited by 26 27 Richard Wolin and John Abromeit 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 university of nebraska press 37 lincoln and london 1 © 2005 by the University of Nebraska Press 2 All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America 3 ⅜ϱ 4 The essays of Herbert Marcuse contained in this volume 5 are reprinted with the permission of the Literary Estate of Herbert Marcuse Peter Marcuse, executor. 6 Supplementary material from previously unpublished work of Herbert Marcuse, 7 much now in the archives of the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University 8 Frankfurt am Main, is being published by Routledge in a six-volume series edited by Douglas Kellner. 9 All rights to further publication of this material are retained by the estate. 10 “Heidegger’s Politics: An Interview with Herbert Marcuse” is reprinted 11 with the permission of the Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal. 12 [-4], (4) Set in Garamond. 13 Designed by R. W. Boeche. 14 15 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Lines: 71 Marcuse, Herbert, 1898– 16 Heideggerian Marxism / Herbert Marcuse ; ——— 17 edited by Richard Wolin and John Abromeit. * 170.593pt 18 p. cm. – (European horizons) ——— Includes bibliographical references and (p. ) index. Normal P 19 isbn-13: 978-0-8032-8312-1 (pbk. : alk. paper) 20 isbn-10: 0-8032-8312-1 (pbk. : alk. paper) * PgEnds: 1. Heidegger, Martin, 1889–1976. 2. Historical materialism. 21 3. Dialectical materialism. 4. Socialism. 5. Communism. 22 I. Wolin, Richard. II. Abromeit, John, 1970– III. Title. IV. Series. [-4], (4) 23 b3279.h49m2732 2005 191–dc22 24 2005012975 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 For Martin Jay 6 In honor of his sixtieth birthday 7 8 9 10 11 12 [-5], (5) 13 14 15 Lines: 154 to 16 ——— 17 * 416.22151pt 18 ——— 19 Normal Page 20 * PgEnds: PageB 21 22 [-5], (5) 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 [-6], (6) 13 14 15 Lines: 166 16 ——— 17 0.0pt PgV 18 ——— 19 Normal P 20 PgEnds: 21 22 [-6], (6) 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 Contents 6 7 8 9 10 Preface ix 11 Introduction: What is Heideggerian Marxism? xi 12 [-7], (7) 13 1. Contributions to a Phenomenology 14 of Historical Materialism 1 15 Lines: 168 to 16 2. On Concrete Philosophy 34 ——— 17 3. On the Problem of the Dialectic 53 * 42.38951pt 18 ——— 19 4. New Sources on the Foundation Normal Page 20 of Historical Materialism 86 * PgEnds: PageB 21 5. On the Philosophical Foundations of the 22 Concept of Labor in Economics 122 [-7], (7) 23 24 6. German Philosophy, 1871–1933 151 25 26 7. Heidegger’s Politics: An Interview 165 27 8. Postscript: My Disillusionment with Heidegger 176 28 29 Glossary 177 30 Notes 191 31 32 Publication History 223 33 34 Index 225 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 [-8], (8) 13 14 15 Lines: 262 16 ——— 17 0.0pt PgV 18 ——— 19 Normal P 20 PgEnds: 21 22 [-8], (8) 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 Preface 6 7 8 9 10 The idea for this volume evolved from a remarkable 1998 conference held at 11 the University of California, Berkeley, and organized by John Abromeit and 12 W. Mark Cobb in honor of Herbert Marcuse’s centennial. [-9], (9) 13 For the 1960s generation, Marcuse was a towering figure—living proof that 14 the so-called generation gap was, in large measure, a mass media fabrication. Lines: 266 to 15 Unlike his Frankfurter School compagnons de route, Max Horkheimer and 16 Theodor Adorno, Marcuse remained remarkably open and receptive to con- ——— 17 temporary political developments. Horkheimer and Adorno’s skepticism vis-à- 13.5pt PgV ——— 18 vis the student movement resulted from their critical assessment of Bolshevism 19 Normal Page as a potent and insidious form of political domination. Their assessment was 20 * PgEnds: Eject consistent with the criticisms of the so-called left communists such as Anton 21 Pannekoek, Hermann Görter, and Rosa Luxemburg. But their views were also 22 conditioned by Germany’s vulnerable geopolitical position on the front lines of [-9], (9) 23 the cold war. Marcuse, conversely, had witnessed firsthand the political evils of 24 McCarthyism, followed by America’s grotesque military build-up in Vietnam, 25 26 in which the horrors of modern war—napalm and massive, indiscriminate 27 aerial bombardment—seemingly knew no bounds. 28 At the Berkeley conference, it was clear that John Abromeit and I shared 29 a profound interest in German philosophy of the 1920s, whose high points 30 were undoubtedly Georg Lukács’s History and Class Consciousness (1923) and 31 Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time (1927). What made Marcuse’s intellectual 32 itinerary so unique was that, at a remarkably young age, he attempted a land- 33 mark synthesis of both traditions: Hegelian Marxism and existential ontology. 34 Moreover, both John and I felt strongly that Marcuse’s contributions were not 35 of merely “historical” value. Instead, we believed that his efforts to combine 36 these two orientations helped to shed important light on problems of the 37 philosophical-political present. x Preface 1 The volume took longer than anticipated to bring to completion. During 2 the late 1920s and 1930s, Marcuse adopted a hybrid, existential Marxist idiom 3 that places peculiar demands on English-speaking readers. Consequently, we 4 felt that our primary responsibility was to ensure that the texts in question 5 appeared in a lucid and accessible English, while at the same time preserving 6 the conceptual rigor of Marcuse’s philosophical and theoretical arguments. 7 Publication of Heideggerian Marxism would not have been possible were it 8 not for the solidarity and assistance of a number of individuals. Above all, we 9 would like to thank Herbert Marcuse’s son, Peter, for his willingness to grant 10 rights and permissions in his capacity as executor of his father’s literary estate. 11 We would also like to publicly acknowledge the efforts of the translators: 12 Ron Haas, Eric Oberle, Matthew Erlin, and John Abromeit. Without their [-10], (10) 13 dedication and tenacity, the volume would never have come to fruition. We 14 would also like to thank our editor at the University of Nebraska Press, M. 15 J. Devaney for her keen editorial discernment and consistent enthusiasm for Lines: 291 16 the project. ——— 17 Allow me to conclude on a personal note. During the 1970s, I had the * 48.0pt 18 good fortune to meet Herbert Marcuse on several occasions—in San Diego, ——— 19 Toronto, and Berkeley. No one who met him could fail to be impressed by Normal P 20 his humanity, his playfulness, and his generosity of spirit. In so many respects, * PgEnds: 21 he was a modern embodiment of the proverbial Aristotelian “great-souled 22 individual.” Our conversations—though they were few—remain permanently [-10], (10) 23 etched in my memory. Publishing this collection of his early philosophical 24 writings is a modest way of acknowledging an intellectual and personal debt 25 that I could never hope to repay in full. 26 Lastly, John Abromeit and I would like to dedicate this volume to the 27 man who has perhaps done more than anyone else to promote international 28 interest in the Frankfurt School legacy: Martin Jay. To me, Marty has been a 29 mentor, friend, confidante, and critic. His generosity and open-mindedness 30 are matchless. We have known each other now for nearly twenty-five years. 31 May our friendship last at least another twenty-five. 32 Richard Wolin 33 New York 34 35 36 37 1 2 3 4 5 Introduction 6 What Is Heideggerian Marxism? 7 8 Richard Wolin 9 10 11 12 [-11], (11) 13 The relatively late and then very rapid reception of Marcuse’s work has allowed a 14 historically inaccurate image of him to emerge: the older strata of his development 15 remain unrecognizable. Marcuse’s 1932 book, Hegel’s Ontology, remains essen- Lines: 315 to 16 tially unknown. I suppose that one would find few among Marcuse’s contemporary ——— 17 readers who would not be completely surprised by the Introduction’s concluding 9.48601pt sentence: “Any contribution this work may make to the development and 18 ——— clarification of problems is indebted to the philosophical work of Martin Normal Page 19 Heidegger.” I don’t know what Marcuse thinks about this sentence today; we PgEnds: T X 20 have never spoken about it.
Recommended publications
  • Sovereign Poetics: from Exception to Apocrypha
    [Expositions 9.2 (2015) 16–34] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747–5376 Sovereign Poetics: from Exception to Apocrypha ERIN FORBES University of Wyoming ABSTRACT This essay suggests an aesthetic solution to the problem of foundation in Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology by reading that work in relation to the Old English poem Judith. This is an essay that analyzes the dynamics of beginnings (those that are overt and locatable together with those that are concealed and irrecoverable). I myself begin by asking what might be gained by reading the Old English poem Judith, whose own beginning has gone missing, as a prelude to political philosopher Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Political Theology is a text whose famous opening hovers suggestively between gnomic aphorism and clear definition: “Sovereign is he who decides on the exception.”1 Unlikely as the pairing of Judith and Political Theology might at first seem, I argue that this juxtaposition helps us think through the problem of what Kathleen Davis, following Schmitt, has described as the “absent foundation of sovereignty.”2 Ultimately, I propose that the philosophical problem that Schmitt’s theorization of the sovereign exception poses has an aesthetic solution in the fragmentary Judith. Although his theories of political life have been influential to both conservative and radical thinkers in recent decades, it remains the case that Schmitt is most often remembered for his association with Hitler’s totalitarian regime. Yet Schmitt objected to constitutional politics throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries because of their pretense to organic totality, not because of their failures of authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualitative Freedom
    Claus Dierksmeier Qualitative Freedom - Autonomy in Cosmopolitan Responsibility Translated by Richard Fincham Qualitative Freedom - Autonomy in Cosmopolitan Responsibility Claus Dierksmeier Qualitative Freedom - Autonomy in Cosmopolitan Responsibility Claus Dierksmeier Institute of Political Science University of Tübingen Tübingen, Baden-Württemberg, Germany Translated by Richard Fincham American University in Cairo New Cairo, Egypt Published in German by Published by Transcript Qualitative Freiheit – Selbstbestimmung in weltbürgerlicher Verantwortung, 2016. ISBN 978-3-030-04722-1 ISBN 978-3-030-04723-8 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04723-8 Library of Congress Control Number: 2018964905 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2019. This book is an open access publication. Open Access This book is licensed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this book are included in the book’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the book’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Theory of Herbert Marcuse: an Inquiry Into the Possibility of Human Happiness
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 1986 Critical theory of Herbert Marcuse: An inquiry into the possibility of human happiness Michael W. Dahlem The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Dahlem, Michael W., "Critical theory of Herbert Marcuse: An inquiry into the possibility of human happiness" (1986). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5620. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5620 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. COPYRIGHT ACT OF 1976 This is an unpublished manuscript in which copyright sub­ s is t s, Any further reprinting of its contents must be approved BY THE AUTHOR, Mansfield Library U n iv e rs ity o f Montana Date :_____1. 9 g jS.__ THE CRITICAL THEORY OF HERBERT MARCUSE: AN INQUIRY INTO THE POSSIBILITY OF HUMAN HAPPINESS By Michael W. Dahlem B.A. Iowa State University, 1975 Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts University of Montana 1986 Approved by Chairman, Board of Examiners Date UMI Number: EP41084 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Critical Theory of Society Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse Edited by Douglas Kellner
    TOWARDS A CRITICAL THEORY OF SOCIETY COLLECTED PAPERS OF HERBERT MARCUSE EDITED BY DOUGLAS KELLNER Volume One TECHNOLOGY, WAR AND FASCISM Volume Two TOWARDS A CRITICAL THEORY OF SOCIETY Volume Three FOUNDATIONS OF THE NEW LEFT Volume Four ART AND LIBERATION Volume Five PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOANALYSIS AND EMANCIPATION Volume Six MARXISM, REVOLUTION AND UTOPIA TOWARDS A CRITICAL THEORY OF SOCIETY HERBERT MARCUSE COLLECTED PAPERS OF HERBERT MARCUSE Volume Two Edited by Douglas Kellner London and New York First published 2001 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003. © 2001 Peter Marcuse Selection and Editorial Matter © 2001 Douglas Kellner Afterword © Jürgen Habermas All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Marcuse, Herbert, 1898– Towards a critical theory of society / Herbert Marcuse; edited by Douglas Kellner. p. cm. – (Collected papers of Herbert Marcuse; v. 2) Includes bibliographical
    [Show full text]
  • An Essay on Liberation by Herbert Marcuse
    An Essay on Liberation by Herbert Marcuse 1969 Title: An Essay on Liberation Author: Marcuse, Herbert (1898 - 1979) Retrieved from: Facsimile version with OCR: http://libgen.org/search.php also in: http://www.lifeaftercapitalism.info/downloads/read/Philosophy/Herbert% 20Marcuse/Herbert%20Marcuse%20- %20An%20Essay%20on%20Liberation%20(Beacon,%201969).pdf https://wiki.brown.edu/confluence/download/attachments/73535007/an_ essay_on_liberation.pdf 2 3 Herbert Marcuse (July 19, 1898 – July 29, 1979) was a German Jewish philosopher, sociologist and political theorist, associated with the Frankfurt School of critical theory. Born in Berlin into a Jewish family, Marcuse studied at the universities of Berlin and Freiburg. He was a prominent figure in the Frankfurt-based Institute for Social Research - what later became known as the Frankfurt School. He was married to Sophie Wertheim (1924- 1951), Inge Neumann (1955-1972), and Erica Sherover (1976-1979). Active in the United States after 1934, his intellectual concerns were the dehumanizing effects of capitalism and modern technology. After his studies, in the late 1960s and the 1970s he became known as the preeminent theorist of the New Left and the student movements of Germany, France, and the USA. Between 1943 and 1950, Marcuse worked in US Government Service, which helped form the basis of his book Soviet Marxism (1964). Celebrated as the "Father of the New Left," his best known works are Eros and Civilization (1955) and One-Dimensional Man (1964). His Marxist scholarship inspired many radical intellectuals and political activists in the 1960s and '70s, both in the U.S. and internationally. Herbert Marcuse 4 Contents Acknowledgments 6 Preface 7 Introduction 9 1 - A Biological Foundation for Socialism? 12 2 - The New Sensibility 22 3 - Subverting Forces -- in Transition 38 4 - Solidarity 56 5 Acknowledgments Thanks Again to my friends who read the manuscript and whose comments and criticism I heeded throughout: especially Leo Lowenthal (University of California at Berkeley), Arno J.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980
    Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980 Robert L. Richardson, Jr. A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of History. Chapel Hill 2009 Approved by, Michael H. Hunt, Chair Richard Kohn Timothy McKeown Nancy Mitchell Roger Lotchin Abstract Robert L. Richardson, Jr. Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1985 (Under the direction of Michael H. Hunt) This dissertation examines the origins and evolution of neoconservatism as a philosophical and political movement in America from 1945 to 1980. I maintain that as the exigencies and anxieties of the Cold War fostered new intellectual and professional connections between academia, government and business, three disparate intellectual currents were brought into contact: the German philosophical tradition of anti-modernism, the strategic-analytical tradition associated with the RAND Corporation, and the early Cold War anti-Communist tradition identified with figures such as Reinhold Niebuhr. Driven by similar aims and concerns, these three intellectual currents eventually coalesced into neoconservatism. As a political movement, neoconservatism sought, from the 1950s on, to re-orient American policy away from containment and coexistence and toward confrontation and rollback through activism in academia, bureaucratic and electoral politics. Although the neoconservatives were only partially successful in promoting their transformative project, their accomplishments are historically significant. More specifically, they managed to interject their views and ideas into American political and strategic thought, discredit détente and arms control, and shift U.S. foreign policy toward a more confrontational stance vis-à-vis the Soviet Union.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of Political Action
    1 THEORIES OF POLITICAL ACTION POLS 520, Spring 2013 Professor Bradley Macdonald Office: C366 Clark Office Hours: TW 2-3:30 or by appointment Telephone #: 491-6943 E-mail: [email protected] Preliminary Remarks: The character of political theory is intimately related to the diverse political practices in which the theorist wrote. Particularly in the contemporary period, theorists have increasingly recognized this political nature to their enterprise by clarifying the linkages of their theory to politics and by rethinking the way in which their ideas may promote social and political change. This critical reassessment has become particularly important in the wake of the dissolution of both classical liberalism and classical Marxism as political ideologies guaranteeing universal human emancipation, not to mention providing conceptual tools to understand the unique political dilemmas facing political actors in the 21st century. If there have been differing ideologies and theories that have confronted new conditions, there are also different strategies and tactics that have been increasingly revamped and rearticulated to engage our contemporaneity. If anything, the present century increasingly gives rise to issues associated with the nature of the “political.” How do we define political action and political knowledge? In what way is politics related to cultural practices (be they art, popular culture, or informational networks)? In what way is political action imbricated within economic practices? How has politics changed given the processes associated with globalization? This course will attempt to explore some of the more important developments within recent theory associated with defining differing positions on the nature of politics and the political.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Rawlsian Liberalism Has Failed and How Proudhonian Anarchism Is the Solution
    A Thesis entitled Why Rawlsian Liberalism has Failed and How Proudhonian Anarchism is the Solution by Robert Pook Submitted to the graduate faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy __________________________________ Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Chair __________________________________ Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Member __________________________________ Dr. Charles V. Blatz, Committee Member __________________________________ Dr. Patricia Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo August 2011 An abstract of Why Rawlsian Liberalism has Failed and How Proudhonian Anarchism is the Solution by Robert Pook Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy University of Toledo August 2011 Liberalism has failed. The paradox in modern society between capitalism and democracy has violated the very principles of liberty, equality, and social justice that liberalism bases its ideology behind. Liberalism, in directly choosing capitalism and private property has undermined its own values and ensured that the theoretical justice, in which its foundation is built upon, will never be. This piece of work will take the monumental, landmark, liberal work, A Theory of Justice, by John Rawls, as its foundation to examine the contradictory and self-defeating ideological commitment to both capitalism and democracy in liberalism. I will argue that this commitment to both ideals creates an impossibility of justice, which is at the heart of, and is the driving force behind liberal theory. In liberalism‟s place, I will argue that Pierre-Joseph Proudhon‟s anarchism, as outlined in, Property is Theft, offers an actual ideological model to achieving the principles which liberalism has set out to achieve, through an adequate and functioning model of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Great Refusal: Herbert Marcuse and Contemporary Social Movements
    Excerpt • Temple University Press 1 Bouazizi’s Refusal and Ours Critical Reflections on the Great Refusal and Contemporary Social Movements Peter N. Funke, Andrew T. Lamas, and Todd Wolfson The Dignity Revolution: A Spark of Refusal n December 17, 2010, in a small rural town in Tunisia, an interaction that happens a thousand times a day in our world—the encounter Obetween repression’s disrespect and humanity’s dignity—became a flashpoint, igniting a global wave of resistance. On this particular day, a police officer confiscated the produce of twenty-six-year-old street vendor Mohamed Bouazizi and allegedly spit in his face and hit him. Humiliated and in search of self-respect, Bouazizi attempted to report the incident to the municipal government; however, he was refused an audience. Soon there- after, Bouazizi doused himself in flammable liquid and set himself on fire. Within hours of his self-immolation, protests started in Bouazizi’s home- town of Sidi Bouzid and then steadily expanded across Tunisia. The protests gave way to labor strikes and, for a few weeks, Tunisians were unified in their demand for significant governmental reforms. During this heightened period of unrest, police and the military responded by violently clamping down on the protests, which led to multiple injuries and deaths. And as is often the case, state violence intensified the situation, resulting in mounting pressure on the government. The protests reached their apex on January 14, 2011, and Tunisian president Ben Ali fled the country, ending his twenty- three years of rule; however, the demonstrations continued until free elec- tions were declared in March 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason-And-Revolution.Pdf
    Reason and Revolution HEGEL AND THE RISE OF SOCIAL THEORY HERBERT MARCUSE 2nd Edition with Supplementary Chapter LONDON ROUTLEDGE & KEGAN PAUL LTD BROADWAY HOUSE: te-74 CARTER LANE, E.C.4 Preface > ) ceo c- THE content of a truly philosophical work does not remain unchanged with time. If its concepts have an essential bearing upon the aims and interests of men, a fundamental change in the historical situation will make them see its teachings in a new light. In our time, the rise of Fascism calls for a reinterpretation of Hegel's philosophy. We hope that the analysis offered here will demonstrate that Hegel's basic concepts are hostile to the tendencies that have led into Fascist theory and practice. We have devoted the first part of the book to a survey of the structure of Hegel's system. At the same time, we have tried to go beyond mere restatement and to elucidate those implications of Hegel's ideas that identify them closely with the later developments in European thought, particularly with the Marxian theory. Hegel's critical and rational standards, and especially his dialectics, had to come into conflict with the prevailing social reality. For this reason, his system could well be called a negative philosophy, the name given to it by its contemporary opponents. To counteract its destructive tendencies, there arose, in the decade following Hegel's death, a positive philosophy which undertook to subordi- nate reason to the authority of established fact. The strug- gle that developed between the negative and positive philosophy offers, as we haVe attempted to show in the second part of this book, many clues for understanding the rise of modern social theory in Europe.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason? “Nihilism” As a Contemporary Critical Narrative
    chapter 4 Heidegger within the Boundaries of Mere Reason? “Nihilism” as a Contemporary Critical Narrative Jon Wittrock Der Gedanke geht der That voraus, wie der Blitz dem Donner - Heinrich Heine1 Heidegger and the Classics That Martin Heidegger was one of the most important thinkers of the 20th century remains indisputable; regardless of our eventual estimation of the man and his thought, the influence of the latter cannot be denied. Even so, however, that influence has remained to a great extent selective, in several ways. Firstly, the earliest wave of Heideggerian influence was largely restricted to that strand which is called, somewhat misleadingly, continental, as opposed to analytic, philosophy.2 The terminology is misleading, of course, because many of the most prominent of the analytic philosophers—e.g., Frege, Wittgenstein and those of the Vienna Circle—indeed stemmed from the European conti- nent. In recent decades, however, Heidegger’s thought has become increasingly more respectable even among some analytic philosophers, notably with the consistent efforts of Rorty.3 Secondly, the influence of the early magnum opus, Being and Time, has been more pervasive than that of Heidegger’s main later works. There are several quite obvious reasons for this: Being and Time remains unmatched in its origi- nality and impact not only because it came first among his major works, but also because it still resembles an ambitious work of systematic philosophy in 1 Heine 1979: 118. 2 This is not to say that Heidegger was entirely ignored—Gilbert Ryle, for example, wrote a review of Being and Time which was originally published in Mind in 1928—it can now be found in Ryle’s (2009) Critical Essays.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger and the Politics of the University 515
    HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICS OF THE UNIVERSITY 515 Heidegger and the Politics of the University IAIN THOMSON* An ancient proverb ran, “He who learns but does not think is lost.” Confucius added, “He who thinks but does not learn is in great danger.”1 IF THIS PROVERB’S EXHORTATION TO THINKING sounds paradigmatically Heideggerian, Confucius’s wise rejoinder helps raise that haunting political question: What, if anything, did Heidegger learn from his appalling misadventure with Nazism? Heidegger told Der Spiegel that he reached this infamous political decision “by way of the university.” If, as I believe, Heidegger’s philosophical views on higher edu- cation were largely responsible for his decision to become the first Nazi Rector of Freiburg University in 1933, then one of our Confucian questions becomes: Did Heidegger learn from what he later called his “life’s greatest stupidity” and transform the underlying philosophical views that helped motivate this “political mistake”?2 The only scholars to address this question, Otto Pöggeler and Jacques Derrida, both think so.3 We will examine their interpretations once we are in a better posi- tion to evaluate them. Obviously, we need first to understand Heidegger’s early views on university education before we can decide whether or not he changed these views after the war. This task is complicated, however, by the fact that Heidegger’s early work on the university turns out to be less philosophically ho- 1 Confucius, The Analects of Confucius, Arthur Waley, trans. (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), II.11, 91 (translation emended). 2 Heidegger, “Only A God Can Save Us,” Maria P.
    [Show full text]