Fuller and the Folk: the Inner Morality of Law Revisited

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fuller and the Folk: the Inner Morality of Law Revisited Forthcoming in T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume 3. Oxford: UK, Oxford University Press. Fuller and the Folk: The Inner Morality of Law Revisited Raff Donelson Ivar R. Hannikainen LOUISIANA STATE UNIVERSITY PONTIFICAL CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY [email protected] OF RIO DE JANEIRO [email protected] The philosophy of law, or jurisprudence, is an concept has—this empirical debate would area of study wherein experimental methods benefit from empirical research. In are largely absent but sorely needed. It is particular, we might seek out folk puzzling that the experimental turn has been psychological evidence, predicated on the slow in coming to jurisprudence, as the field positive impact such evidence has had in other straddles two disciplines where empirical domains of philosophy. evidence is increasingly common. On one The foregoing may not be convincing. flank, empirical studies have long been Traditional legal philosophers who do not use popular among non-philosophers in law empirical methods will need to hear more to departments; on the other, experimental appreciate why strange, new techniques methods now abound in many areas of might be appropriate. Experimental philosophy. philosophers who have yet to consider While it is difficult to understand why few jurisprudence will need to hear more about have adopted an experimental approach to the subfield and its issues to understand how jurisprudence, it is clear why experimental they might contribute. We hope to address jurisprudence should be on the agenda: legal such philosophers and others, but not with a philosophers routinely ask questions that are purely metaphilosophical tract. Instead, our explicitly empirical. To give just one brief essay aims to exemplify the potential for example, consider the fact that in experimental approaches to jurisprudence. As contemporary jurisprudence, some such, we focus on a narrow issue in philosophers are concerned, in part, to give jurisprudence. We appraise Lon Fuller’s the correct account of our concept of law or procedural natural law theory using our concept of a legal system (Raz 2009), experimental techniques. Admittedly, his is while others are anxious to show that there is just one of many theories about law; however, no single concept of law (L. Murphy 2005; it is a prominent theory, and legal Priel 2011). It would seem that this debate— philosophers have written extensively to about whether we have a shared concept of criticize (Hart, 1965; D’Amato, 1981), defend law at all, and if so, what contours that (C. Murphy, 2005), and extend that theory (Winston, 2005). If our experiments usefully made public for those regulated to learn of add to this debate, we thereby establish the their rights and duties), and the prospectivity legitimacy and value of experimental principle (that a legal rule of conduct may only jurisprudence. regulate conduct performed after the The trajectory of the essay is as follows. We promulgation of said rule of conduct).1 Since begin with background on Fuller’s theory of its initial formulation in the 1960s, Fuller’s law and on the state of jurisprudence. For theory has been widely discussed and those well-versed in those debates, this can be continues to enlist new adherents. This is not skimmed or skipped. Next, we offer an surprising because the view has certain overview of the studies that we performed. In theoretical virtues, virtues one can identify this overview section, we state with precision upon reviewing other well-known views in how our experimental approach helps to this debate. assess Fuller’s theory. After the overview, we If the key discussion in jurisprudence is the present each of the three studies themselves. search for necessary and sufficient conditions For each study, we discussion our predictions, for law, the most notorious debate within that the motivating thoughts behind those key discussion concerns whether a norm has predictions, the manner by which the to have particular content in order to count as experiment was performed, and the results. legal norm. Legal philosophers have been In the final section of the essay, the general especially interested in whether a norm’s discussion, we elaborate on results of our content has to comport with the strictures of research and explore their limitations, and morality in order to be a legal norm. If a norm muse in more broad-minded way about the permits or even requires those subject to it to future of experimental jurisprudence. perform grossly immoral acts, can that norm be a legal norm? That kind of question has Fuller’s procedural natural law theory long been the hot-button issue in jurisprudence. Those who answer in the The key discussion in jurisprudence concerns affirmative are, roughly speaking, legal the necessary and sufficient conditions positivists; whereas, those who answer in the something must satisfy in order to count as a negative are, roughly speaking, natural law law or a legal system. Fuller (1969) offered a theorists. Legal positivism has a long list of major contribution to this discussion when he famous proponents (e.g., Austin, 1998; proposed a novel set of necessary conditions. Kelsen, 1967; Hart, 1994; Raz, 2009; Specifically, Fuller argued that a social Waluchow, 1994; Shapiro, 2011); while arrangement is a legal system insofar as that natural law theory has its own list of famous arrangement satisfies eight principles that he proponents (e.g., Aquinas, 1994; King, 1986; collectively called “the inner morality of law.” Finnis, 1980; Dworkin, 1986; Murphy, 2011). These principles include the generality Fuller set himself apart by straddling the principle (that legal systems must have divide between the two camps. general rules of conduct), the publicity principle (that legal rules of conduct must be 1 We reproduce the full set of Fullerian principles below and only offer this abbreviated list to help fix ideas. 2 Scholars are often drawn to natural law sees as necessary features of law, laws theory because they hold as a considered minimally treat people fairly. Arguably, this judgment the thought that, prima facie, those feature of law would deserve respect and subject to a law’s provisions have a moral would give subjects some moral reason to reason to obey it. Or to put this considered comply with law. To illustrate the minimal judgment another way, prima facie, law sense in which law treats people fairly on deserves subjects’ respect. If this considered Fuller’s theory, consider two of his principles. judgment is used as a desideratum for The publicity principle (that legal rules of selecting one’s theory of law, one will endorse conduct must be made public for those some content restriction as a condition for regulated to learn of their rights and duties) some norm to count as law. On the other and the prospectivity principle (that a legal hand, scholars are often drawn to legal rule of conduct may only regulate conduct positivism because they hold as a considered performed after the promulgation of said rule judgment the thought that some laws are of conduct) together imply that law unjust such as those of the Third Reich, necessarily gives subjects fair notice of which apartheid South Africa, and the antebellum behavior will elicit adverse state responses. American South. The foregoing explains how Fuller can Because, for Fuller, a norm can be law only accommodate one of the driving thoughts if it has certain content (e.g. it is prospective behind traditional natural law theory, but he and not retrospective), his view is often does not incur that theory’s key theoretical classed as a version of natural law theory. cost, denying that there are unjust laws. It is However, Fuller’s natural law theory differs to Fuller’s theoretical advantage over other from more familiar versions of natural law natural lawyers that he can claim with legal theory which claim that a norm is a law only positivists that some norms are both unjust if the norm is just (Aquinas, 1994; King, 1986) and legal in the fullest sense. or claim that unjust norms can, at best, be Before concluding this section on Fuller’s defective instances of law (Finnis, 1980; work and its place in contemporary Murphy, 2011). Fuller’s conditions only jurisprudence, we summarize the eight disqualify norms which exhibit certain principles which comprise Fuller’s inner procedural failings from being laws. Thus, for morality of law. The principles are as follows. Fuller, many unjust norms can be laws, and (For ease of exposition, n will signify some only some unjust norms would fail to be laws. norm, L will signify law, and all claims For this reason, commentators often label concern a single jurisdiction.) Fuller’s view an instance of procedural natural law theory. CONSISTENCY: n1 and n2 are both L only if n1 Fuller’s procedural natural law theory and n2 are mutually consistent might be thought to enjoy theoretical virtues of both traditional natural law theory and ENFORCEMENT: n is L only if the published legal positivism. Fuller’s view can version of n accords with how n is enforced countenance the considered judgment that GENERALITY: n is L only if n is a general rule law, prima facie, deserves subjects’ respect. of conduct Given the procedural constraints that Fuller 3 INTELLIGIBILITY: n is L only if n can be whether his attempt has been successful. The understood by subjects folk intuitions are the very subject of Fullerian claims on this construal. Alternately, insofar POSSIBILITY: n is L only if n requires only those acts subjects are physically capable of as Fuller attempts to do descriptive analysis of performing law, analysis of what law actually is, folk intuitions bear indirectly on whether Fuller is PROSPECTIVITY: n is L only if n regulates right.
Recommended publications
  • Hans Kelsen Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy Synthese Library
    HANS KELSEN ESSAYS IN LEGAL AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MATHEMATICAL METHODS OF SOCIAL AND BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON, The Rockefeller University and Princeton University J AAKKO H INTI K KA, Academy of Finland and Stanford University GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, Indiana University HANS KELSEN (1881-1973) HANS KELSEN ESSAYS IN LEGAL AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY Selected and Introduced by OT A WEINBERGER Translated by PETER HEATH D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT-HOLLAND I BOSTON-U.S.A. First printing: December 1973 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 73-86090 ISBN -l3: 978-94-010- 2655-0 e-ISBN -l3: 978-94-010- 2653-6 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-010-2653-6 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, Dordrecht, Holland Sold and distributed in the U.S.A., Canada and Mexico by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Inc. 306 Dartmouth Street, Boston, Mass. 02116, U.S.A. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1973 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1973 No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any other means, without written permission from the publisher CONTENTS PREFACE VII TRANSLA TOR'S NOTE VIII INTRODUCTION: HANS KELSEN AS PHILOSOPHER (BY OTA WEINBERGER) IX 1. Kelsen's Conception of Legal Science: the Struggle against Syncretism of Methods X 2. The Contrasting of 'Is' and 'Ought' XIV 3. The Validity of the Norm XVII 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Law Without Justice--The Kelsen and Hall Theories Compared Miriam Theresa Rooney
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 23 | Issue 2 Article 2 1-1-1948 Law without Justice--The Kelsen and Hall Theories Compared Miriam Theresa Rooney Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Miriam T. Rooney, Law without Justice--The Kelsen and Hall Theories Compared, 23 Notre Dame L. Rev. 140 (1948). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr/vol23/iss2/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW WITHOUT JUSTICE? - THE KELSEN AND HALL THEORIES COMPARED In the midst of war, laws are silent, as the Romans, who were great warriors as well as great lawyers, warned us. War may be the ultimate sanction for law in at least one phil- osophy, but once war has been declared, soldiers take over, and lawyers, at least from the standpoint of the selective service rules, are "nonessential." Under Christian influence civilization attempted to develop laws of warfare, extending from the truce of God in the middle ages to the outlawing of poisonous gas in our day. Nevertheless, war remains in- human in its brutality and its devastating effects on family life. In a sustained effort to supplement war with law, Christianity undertook to distinguish between just and un- just wars and inspired publicists to write learned treatises upon that point. Although many hundred years have passed since such a task was first undertaken, the results are still unsatisfactory.
    [Show full text]
  • The Autonomy of Legal Norms
    THE AUTONOMY OF LEGAL NORMS Lisa Van Alstyne In the American legal academy, the view that legal norms are autonomous has long been in disgrace. In this paper I make a beginning on the larger project of rescuing this view from its current state of infamy. A full vindication of the the- sis that legal norms are autonomous would include within its purview an exami- nation of a variety of legal norms drawn from diverse legal fields. My present aim is more modest; it is simply to cast plausibility upon the thesis for one area of the law, namely: tort law.1 As we shall see, this area is not chosen at random. A number of theorists whose own approach to legal theory involves a repudia- tion of the thesis defended here have taken tort law to be a particularly promis- ing field for demonstrating the fecundity of their approach. Tort law thus pro- vides a useful laboratory space for testing the philosophical credentials of these opposing conceptions of how to do legal theory. In the first two sections of the paper, I situate this contest of opposing conceptions within a larger philosophi- cal context. In the third section of the paper, I offer an overview of the basic concepts of tort law for the benefit of those to whom this area of the law may be unfamiliar. In the fourth section, I will survey the analysis of this stretch of the legal landscape which has been offered by Richard Posner, one of America’s most prominent legal theorists. Finally, in the fifth section, I will offer a con- trasting analysis of this same area of the law, one which respects the autonomy of its norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Legality of Law (2004) by John Gardner Professor of Jurisprudence University of Oxford
    The Legality of Law (2004) by John Gardner Professor of Jurisprudence University of Oxford http://users.ox.ac.uk/~lawf0081 This is an author eprint, which may not incorporate final edits. The definitive version of the paper is published in Ratio Juris 17 (2004), 168 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9337.2004.00262.x © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 The typescript appears here with the consent of the publisher, under the publisher’s eprint policy, or by author’s reserved rights. Please do not quote from or cite to this eprint. Always use the definitive version for quotation and citation. The Legality of Law JOHN GARDNER* ‘Philosophy is not lexicography’, as Joseph Raz reminds us.1 An explanation of the nature of law is not an explanation of the meaning (let alone a definition) of the word ‘law’ nor of any of its cognates. We speak of laws of nature and laws of logic. We speak of legal moves in chess and illegal operations by computer programmes. There is nothing suspect or misleading about these usages. They are not, for example, mere figures of speech. Yet we should not expect a philosopher of law to account for them. It is no objection to an explanation of the nature of law that according to it the laws of logic are not laws, or that according to it a computer programme cannot act illegally. Whereas it is an objection to an explanation of the nature of law that according to it the laws of Sweden are not laws, or that according to it the US government cannot act illegally.
    [Show full text]
  • Fazhi in China
    China Fazhi in China Original Contribution by Robert Heuser, Dr. iur., Professor for China Studies, University of Köln In Chinese the „rule of law" is usually referred to as fazhi which literally means "regulating by laws". It is regarded as the antithesis of renzhi (regulating by men); to postulate fazhi is therefore tantamount to negate the long tradition of renzhi. Still in the beginning of the 1980s fazhi as a value of chinese political culture was not unchallenged. Since 1999, however, the constitution stipulates that China "implements (the principle) to rule the country according to law" (yi fa zhi guo) and "establishes a socialist state regulated by law" (jianshe shehuizhuyi fazhi guojia). Therefore fazhi became first and above all an expression for extensive legislation, i.e. lawmaking by the National People's Congress and the State Council (central government). Implementation of the newly created legal rules by administrative bodies and the judiciary as well as legal education became further elements of fazhi. D ue to a political system with a "leading party" as its nucleus and the refusal of the doctrine of checks and balances (separation of powers) fazhi tends to be instrumental for political ends rather than limiting political power. I. Preliminary remarks In 1978, the Chinese leadership pronounced that the establishment of a legal system was necessary both as an instrument and as a guarantee for the intended transformation of the ways of economical and social life ("modernization"). Since then, Chinese leaders have been increasingly confronted with the duality inherent in law: law as an instrument of political power and as an agent for restraining this same power.
    [Show full text]
  • The Application of Jurisprudence and the Construction of Legal Discourse System
    2018 3rd International Social Sciences and Education Conference (ISSEC 2018) The Application of Jurisprudence and the Construction of Legal Discourse System Jie He Kunming University, School of Social Management, Kunming, Yunnan, 650214 Keywords: jurisprudence; construction; Legal Discourse System Abstract: The jurisprudence has always been an important issue for legal scholars. However, for many years, the research on the role or function of jurisprudence has not been detailed. Although the function of jurisprudence can be carried out from both the perspectives of legislation and judicature, most scholars explore the political function of jurisprudence from the perspective of legislation. The jurisprudential function of the legislative perspective mainly focuses on the political function of jurisprudence, more about borrowing the discourse system of current affairs politics and the link of legal discourse, and interpreting political discourse from the perspective of jurisprudence. 1. Introduction There are several reasons why the “use of jurisprudence” or the argumentative theory of science has become a problem. The main ones include: First, there is a lack of methodological content in the knowledge structure of most jurisprudence textbooks. Many of the texts in the textbooks are law-centered. Position, there is little talk about the law of justice and law enforcement. Did not regard the understanding, interpretation and use of the law as the key to teaching; did not improve the level of legal thinking as the main goal and key content of teaching. This makes the practicality that jurisprudence itself should not show. Second, the reason why the theory of jurisprudence is useless is, to a certain extent, related to the research position of jurisprudence and the narrative methods of professors.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pure Theory of Law
    Vanderbilt Law Review Volume 14 Issue 1 Issue 1 - December 1960 Article 10 12-1960 The Pure Theory of Law Reginald Parker Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Law and Society Commons Recommended Citation Reginald Parker, The Pure Theory of Law, 14 Vanderbilt Law Review 211 (1960) Available at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr/vol14/iss1/10 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PURE THEORY OF LAW REGINALD PARKER* Philosophy teaches us to feel un- certain about the things that seem to us self-evident. Aldous Huxley There is hardly a theory of law about which there exists so much confusion in the minds of so many scholars as about Hans Kelsen's theory, which is commonly known under the name "Pure Theory of Law." If, for instance, a scholar of the stature and standing of Pro- fessor Northrop maintains that Kelsen locates the basic norm of the Austrian Constitution of 1920 "in the earliest Constitution of 1867,"' then it seems that there is still room, indeed an intellectual demand, for a brief and simple exposition of Kelsen's theory. We shall at- tempt it in the following article2 not without avoiding the temptation to oversimplify crucial problems. The Pure Theory of Law is called "pure" because it is a theory of law and not, like sociology, of causally related social facts; because it is a theory of law and not of ethics; and because it is a theory of law regardless of the political conditions that led to the creation of this or that democratic, communist, fascist, tribal or other law.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Culture
    Ralf Michaels Forthcoming in Oxford Handbook of European Private Law (Basedow, Hopt, Zimmermann eds., Oxford University Press) Legal Culture 1. Term Legal culture has been intensively discussed in legal discussions over the last twenty years or so, especially in connection with the Europeanisation of private law. Often, national legal culture is simply viewed as an obstacle to → European private law; a European legal culture is viewed as its prerequisite. What is actually meant by legal culture often remains unclear: legal culture is considered important, but an exact definition is not. Moreover, the problems bound up in the concept of culture, which related disciplines – especially anthropology and sociology – have tackled, are widely ignored. The term legal culture refers to multiple different ideas, which are not always sufficiently separated. Legal culture often describes merely an extended understanding of law and is thus synonymous with „living law“ (Eugen Ehrlich) or „law in action“ (Roscoe Pound). Sometimes, the term legal culture is used interchangeably with the term → legal family or legal tradition. More specific concepts exist as well. Legal sociologists especially understand legal culture as the values, ideas and attitudes that a society has with respect to its law (Lawrence M. Friedman, James Q. Whitman). Sometimes legal culture itself is seen as a value and placed in opposition to the barbarism of totalitarianism (Peter Häberle); here, legal culture is used synonymously with the rule of law. Others understand culture as certain modes of thinking; they speak of episteme or mentalité (Pierre Legrand), legal knowledge (Annelise Riles) and collective memory (Niklas Luhmann), law in the minds (William Ewald) or even cosmology (Rebecca French, Lawrence Rosen).
    [Show full text]
  • Guide to Cuban Law and Legal Research
    International Journal of Legal Information 45.2, 2017, pp. 76–188. © The Author(s) 2017 doi:10.1017/jli.2017.22 GUIDE TO CUBAN LAW AND LEGAL RESEARCH JULIENNE E. GRANT,MARISOL FLORÉN-ROMERO,SERGIO D. STONE,STEVEN ALEXANDRE DA COSTA,LYONETTE LOUIS-JACQUES,CATE KELLETT, JONATHAN PRATTER,TERESA M. MIGUEL-STEARNS,EDUARDO COLÓN-SEMIDEY,JOOTAEK LEE,IRENE KRAFT AND YASMIN MORAIS1 CONTENTS INTRODUCTION Julienne E. Grant LEGAL SYSTEM AND GOVERNMENT STRUCTURE Steven Alexandre da Costa and Julienne E. Grant A. HISTORICAL OVERVIEW B. TRANSITION TO THE CURRENT LEGAL LANDSCAPE C. CURRENT LEGAL LANDSCAPE D. THE CUBAN GOVERNMENT: A BRIEF OVERVIEW E. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY THE CONSTITUTION Lyonette Louis-Jacques A. INTRODUCTION B. THE 1976 CONSTITUTION AND ITS AMENDMENTS C. FUTURE D. CONSTITUTIONAL TEXTS E. CONSTITUTIONAL COMMENTARIES F. CURRENT AWARENESS G. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY EXECUTIVE POWERS Julienne E. Grant A. THE COUNCIL OF STATE B. THE COUNCIL OF MINISTERS C. FIDEL CASTRO’S ROLE: POST-2007 D. RESEARCHING THE COUNCILS OF STATE AND MINISTERS IN SPANISH E. RESEARCHING THE COUNCILS OF STATE AND MINISTERS IN ENGLISH F. SOURCES FOR THE CASTROS’ SPEECHES, INTERVIEWS AND WRITINGS LEGISLATION AND CODES Marisol Florén-Romero and Cate Kellett A. OFFICIAL GAZETTE B. COMPILATIONS OF LAWS C. CODES D. ENGLISH-LANGUAGE TRANSLATIONS OF CUBAN LAWS E. ONLINE RESOURCES FOR CODES AND LEGISLATION F. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF LEGISLATION, CODES AND COMMENTARY 1 © 2017 Julienne E. Grant, Marisol Florén-Romero, Sergio D. Stone, Steven Alexandre da Costa, Lyonette Louis-Jacques, Cate Kellett, Jonathan Pratter, Teresa M. Miguel-Stearns, Eduardo Colón-Semidey, Jootaek Lee, Irene Kraft and Yasmin Morais. 76 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 Legal Positivism
    Chapter 2 Legal positivism Imagine a powerful sovereign who issues commands to his subjects. They are under a duty to comply with his wishes. The notion of law as a command lies at the heart of classical legal positivism as espoused by its two great protagonists, Jeremy Bentham and John Austin. Modern legal positivists adopt a considerably more sophisticated approach to the concept of law, but, like their distinguished predecessors, they deny the relationship proposed by natural law, outlined in the previous chapter, between law and morals. The claim of natural lawyers that law consists of a series of propositions derived from nature through a process of reasoning is strongly contested by legal positivists. This chapter describes the essential elements of this important legal theory. The term ‘positivism’ derives from the Latin positum, which refers to the law as it is laid down or posited. Broadly speaking, the core of legal positivism is the view that the validity of any law can be traced to an objectively verifiable source. Put simply, legal positivism, like scientific positivism, rejects the view – held by natural lawyers – that law exists independently from human enactment. As will become clear in this chapter, the early legal positivism of Bentham and Austin found the origin of law in the command of a sovereign. H. L. A. Hart looks to a rule of recognition that distinguishes law from other social rules. Hans Kelsen identifies a basic norm that validates the constitution. Legal positivists also often claim that 18 there is no necessary connection between law and morals, and that the analysis of legal concepts is worth pursuing, and distinct from (though not hostile to) sociological and historical enquiries and critical evaluation.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Norms and Epistemic Accountability
    volume 18, no. 8 n May 1940, German Panzer divisions slashed through Northern april 2018 France, threatening to encircle the British Expeditionary Force I along with French and Belgian armies. In a desperate gamble, Winston Churchill decided to throw in more squadrons of the Fighter Command. In his recent The Battle of Britain, the historian James Hol- land reports that when one group of Spitfire pilots landed at an airfield, they saw a French fighter practicing aerobatics above. However, they Epistemic Norms and also spotted a German Dornier bomber approaching, and urged the French colonel in charge to inform the fighter pilot. But, if we are to be- lieve Holland, the colonel refused, saying “Today he is only authorized to do aerobatics” (Holland 2010, 225). Epistemic Accountability I think we shouldn’t believe Holland. This story, based on an interview with one of the still surviving British pilots, has all the marks of an urban legend designed to embellish the bureaucratic incompetence of the hapless French. The odds are nil that there would be regulations forbidding a fighter pilot to take defensive action in time of war, not to mention that an airfield commander would enforce such regulations at the risk of losing the rest of his planes. As a military historian, Holland should know this, and consequently shouldn’t report the anecdote without comment. The proper response to his being so gullible or negligent is not just to doubt his professionalism, but also to reduce epistemic trust in him — roughly, to give a lower Antti Kauppinen credence to the rest of what he says, to be less willing to regard him as a potential partner in co-operative inquiry, and to have less attitudinal University of Helsinki confidence in him.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Positivism Reginald Parker
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 32 | Issue 1 Article 3 12-1-1956 Legal Positivism Reginald Parker Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Reginald Parker, Legal Positivism, 32 Notre Dame L. Rev. 31 (1956). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr/vol32/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LEGAL POSITIVISM The legal positivist holds that only positive law is law; and by "positive law" he means legal norms by authority of the state. Nothing else is "law" to him, even though he may recognize other normative orders such as the religious or moral orders, or etiquette. Furthermore, every- thing thus created by state authority is law to the posi- tivist, even though he may deplore the state of the law and seek to change it. The name "legal positivism," inci- dentally, appears to be preferable to "analytical juris- prudence" or "analytical positivism," which are often used, especially in connection with John Austin's work.' The legal thinking of the positivist is no more "analyti- cal" (either in the sense of critical thinking or pertaining to analysis as opposed to synthesis) than that of, say, an adherent of the historical school. It is beyond the scope of this brief exposition to outline the history of legal thinking, on which there exist many excellent works.' Suffice it here to remind ourselves that until the eighteenth century most, if not all, legal philoso- phy was steeped in the theory of natural law.
    [Show full text]