Plotinus, Epicurus, and the Gnostics: on Plotinian Classification of Philosophies

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plotinus, Epicurus, and the Gnostics: on Plotinian Classification of Philosophies PLOTINUS, EPICURUS, AND THE GNOSTICS: ON PLOTINIAN CLASSIFICATION OF PHILOSOPHIES Andrei Cornea 1. When we try to figure out what Plotinus might have looked like, it is a Byzantine icon that usually comes up in our mind: a slim, tall, highly- spiritualized figure, floating in out-of-this-world space, intensively gazing upon us, totally detached from the things below. Yet such an image over- simplifies this philosopher’s life. For instance, although one does not expect a Byzantine icon to be involved in heavy polemic, polemic plays an impor- tant role in Plotinus’ life and philosophy. So the icon has got cracks. In fact, because Plotinus, like many in his epoch, denied that his ideas had any basic originality,1 considering them (despite obvious and essential innovations) to be but the unfolding of one master’s ultimate truth, polemic mainly con- cerned the question of whether or not his own interpretation of this master, Plato, was the most faithful of all. Besides, Plotinus believed, Plato had to be defended against all misinterpretation and outright contestation which were never in short supply. So Plotinus had a lot of potential adversaries; but of course he could not afford to take on all of them at once. Therefore, he needed politics. In fact, there is no polemic without some politics, and that prompts me to invoke Carl Schmitt’s famous definition: The political is the art of distinguishing friends from enemies. In other words, politics usually establish a divide between the former and the latter that must be appropriate to the occasion. If this is the case, then even a philosopher cannot avoid pursuing a certain policy about who his friends and his enemies in philosophy should be at a certain moment. So he needs to be “opportunistic” to some extent, regardless of how unpolitical his philosophy in itself may be. Therefore, it is meaningful to ask: (1) where did Plotinus consider fit to draw the major 1 See Enn. 5.1 [10] 8. The Gnostics, his enemies, were not different in this respect, for they claimed to be the interpreters of some old savior like Zoroaster. The real trouble for someone like Plotinus would not have been a lack of originality with respect to Plato but with respect to some more recent philosophers. To emulate a wise man of old was considered noble and necessary, while to emulate a “modern” was paramount to plagiarism. Plotinus was actually accused of plagiarizing Numenius of Apamea (Porphyry, Vit. Plot. 17). 466 andrei cornea dividing line between “we” (his friends and allies) and “they” (his major adversaries) in philosophy? (2) Did these “we” and “they” remain the same throughout his whole career? (3) In case we answer “no” to the second point, how can we account for the resulting shift in terms of Plotinus’ policy on alliances in philosophy? 2. Plotinus speaks rarely explicitly about how philosophy in general should be divided up into major trends or schools, or about the number of these trends and the criteria for the most appropriate classifications of them. In fact, there are just two places within the whole corpus Plotinianum where such a discussion occurs—the former in Enn. 5.9 [5] 1 (from now on, classi- fication A), and the latter in Enn. 2.9 [33] 15 (classification B).2 Let us examine both: (a) At the beginning of his early fifth treatise (Enn. 5.9 [5] 1), Plotinus por- trays three kinds of philosophers (unnamed but easy to identify) and likens each of them to a species of bird. The most despicable “birds” are the Epi- cureans who have only a pretense of rationality (οἵ γε λόγου μεταποιούμενοι). Because they hold, like the common people, that pleasure is the τέλος (the end) of life, they are “like the heavy sort of birds who have taken much from the earth and are weighed down by it and so are unable to fly high, although nature has given them wings.” The next kind of “birds” (the Stoics) are said to be better, still not good enough: “they have risen a little from the things below, because the better part of their soul has urged them on from the pleasant to a greater beauty; but since they are unable to see what is above … they are brought down, with the name of virtue, to practical actions …” Only the third kind is really perfect: so these philosophers are thought to be “divine”: “they see the glory above and are raised to it as if above the clouds and the mist of this lower world …”3 Of course, these “high-flying birds” are the Platonists like Plotinus himself. A.H. Armstrong rightly remarks that this classification of philosophical schools has nothing original, except, possibly, for the image itself.4 It has all 2 Plotinus comments on solutions introduced by other philosophies elsewhere as, for instance, in Enn. 4.7 [2] 2–8; yet, apart from those two places there are no others where he produces any classification as such of philosophies. 3 Trans. Armstrong 1966–1988. 4 Armstrong 1966–1988, 5:286–287n1. Bréhier (1924–1938, 5:154) had commented in the same vein: “Il est visible que Plotin suit d’assez près les commentaires platoniciens clas- siques …”.
Recommended publications
  • Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources of the Central Christian Doctrine
    ! Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources ! of the Central Christian Doctrine Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX 77004 Paper published in A Journal from the Radical Reformation. A testimony to Biblical Unitarianism. Vol. 14, No.! 1, Spring 2007, pp. 3-31. Quis obsecro, nisi penitus amens logomachias has sine risu toleraret? Nec in Thalmud, nec in Alchoran, sunt tam horrendae blasfemiae. Haec nos hactenus audire ita sumus alsuefacti, ut nihil miremur. Futurae vero generationes stupenda haec iudicabunt. Stupenda sunt vere, plusquam ea daemonum inventa, quae Valentinianis tribuit Irenaeus. I implore you, who in his sane mind could tolerate such logomachias without bursting into laughter? Not in the Talmud, nor in the Qu’ran can one find such horrendous blasphemies. But we are accustomed to hear them to the point that nothing astonishes us. Future generations will judge them obscure. Indeed, they are obscure, much more than the diabolic inventions which Irenaeus attributed to the Valentinians. ! Michael Servetus Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. I. p. 46. Si locum mihi aliquem ostendas, quo verbum illud filius olim vocetur, fatebor me victum. Christianismi Restitutio, If you show me a single passage in which the Son was called the Word, I will give up. Michael Servetus, Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. III p. 108. ! Abstract This paper attempts to explain the sources of the central Christian doctrine about the nature of deity. We can trace a continuous line of thought from the Greek philosophy to the development of the doctrine of the Trinity. The first Christian doctrine was developed by Justin Martyr (114-165 C.E.).
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION BEAU BRANSON, MARCUS WILLIAM HUNT, TIMOTHY D KNEPPER, ROBERT SLOAN LEE, STEVEN STEYL, HANS VAN EYGHEN, BEAU BRANSON (BOOK EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion by Beau Branson, Marcus William Hunt, Timothy D Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee, Steven Steyl, Hans Van Eyghen, Beau Branson (Book Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. DEDICATION To Roger Branson — the best dad I ever had. For all the sacrifices I know ouy made. And for all the ones I don’t. CONTENTS What is an Open Textbook? ix Christina Hendricks How to Access and Use the Books xi Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xiii Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xvi Acknowledgements xviii Beau Branson and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Beau Branson 1. The Intertwining of Philosophy and Religion in the Western Tradition 7 Beau Branson 2. Reasons to Believe – Theoretical Arguments 18 Marcus William Hunt 3. Non-Standard Arguments for God’s Existence 30 Robert Sloan Lee 4. Reasons Not to Believe 49 Steven Steyl 5. Debunking Arguments against Theistic Belief 62 Hans Van Eyghen 6. From Philosophy of (Mono)theism to Philosophy of Religions 74 Timothy D Knepper Glossary 87 About the Contributors 91 Feedback and Suggestions 94 Adoption Form 95 Licensing and Attribution Information 96 Review Statement 98 Accessibility Assessment 99 Version History 101 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Discourse of Daemonic Sacrifice in Porphyry's De Abstinentia
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Carolina Digital Repository Daemonic Trickery, Platonic Mimicry: the Discourse of Daemonic Sacrifice in Porphyry’s De Abstinentia Travis W. Proctor A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Religious Studies Chapel Hill 2013 Approved by: Bart D. Ehrman Zlatko P e e James B. Rives © 2013 Travis W. Proctor ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT TRAVIS W. PROCTOR: Daemonic Trickery, Platonic Mimicry: the Discourse of Daemonic Sacrifice in Porphyry’s De Abstinentia Porphyry of Tyre’s discussion of daemons and anima sacrifice in his De Abstinentia strays from traditional Graeco-Roman formulations of daemonic benevolence and physiology. As a result, past studies have struggled to identify the intellectual lineage for Porphyry’s daemonology. By contrast, I propose that Porphyry draws his daemonology from Christian Platonic sources, best represented in the writings of Origen of Alexandria. I provide an extensive survey of early Christian views on daemonic physiology and encroachment upon sacrificial ritual, with a special section devoted to a comparison with the daemonology of Origen. There are notable similarities between the daemonologies of Porphyry and early Christian writers, ike y occasioned by Porphyry’s fami iarity with Christian daemonological discourses. Porphyry attributes his daemono ogica discussion, moreover, to “certain P atonists,” a c aim which, when read in ight of Porphyry’s Vita Plotini, places Origen (and other Christians) squarely within the intellectual circles from which Porphyry was drawing his daemonological discourse.
    [Show full text]
  • Pattison, Kirsty Laura (2020) Ideas of Spiritual Ascent and Theurgy from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico. Mth(R) Thesis
    Pattison, Kirsty Laura (2020) Ideas of spiritual ascent and theurgy from the ancients to Ficino and Pico. MTh(R) thesis. http://theses.gla.ac.uk/81873/ Copyright and moral rights for this work are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This work cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Enlighten: Theses https://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] Ideas of Spiritual Ascent and Theurgy from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico Kirsty Laura Pattison MA (Hons) Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of MTh (by Research). School of Critical Studies College of Arts University of Glasgow Supervisors Prof Charlotte Methuen Dr Mia Spiro October 2020 Declaration of Originality Form – Research Degrees This form must be completed and signed and submitted with your thesis. Name Kirsty Laura Pattison ............................................................................................................. Student Number ........................................................................................................... Title of degree MTh (by Research) .................................................................................................. Title of thesis Ideas of Spiritual Ascent from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico .................................. The University's degrees and other academic awards are given in recognition of a student's personal achievement. All work submitted for assessment is accepted on the understanding that it is the student's own effort.
    [Show full text]
  • Download PDF (598.6
    Index A Protrepticus 121, 122, 163, 233 Topica 233 Abraham 23, 211 ἐνέργεια Aetius 6, 7, 89, 90, 91, 92, 93, 94, Arius 5, 6, 9, 10, 46, 48, 49, 50, 95, 96, 97, 98, 114, 115, 51, 52, 53, 54, 55, 56, 57, 119, 150, 151, 159, 166, 58, 59, 60, 61, 62, 63, 64, 167, 204, 228, 233 65, 66, 68, 69, 70, 73, 76, knowledge of God 78, 79, 86, 89, 116, 119, knowledge of substance (ὀυσία) 137, 161, 227, 228, 238, Syntagmation 7, 89, 115, 159, 241, 242, 243 166, 233 arian controversy 25, 34, 49, Aghiorgoussis M. 200, 238 70, 77, 137, 139, 140, 146, Alcinous 39, 40, 41, 45, 131, 233 148, 149 Anatolios, K. 76, 238 attributes of God 36, 101, 114, Andia Y. de 238 141 Anomeans 6, 7, 8, 9, 34, 45, 89, Creation ex nihilo 57 119, 140, 219, 221, 225, (Father and Son) will and wish 228 (βούλημα καί θέλημα) 56 Aristotle 10, 11, 13, 31, 40, 42, Monad and Diad 51 81, 92, 93, 94, 95, 103, negative theology 5, 9, 10, 55, 104, 119, 120, 121, 122, 60, 62, 64, 68, 69, 161, 227 123, 124, 125, 126, 127, status of the Son of God 2 131, 132, 134, 138, 144, Thalia 54, 62, 67 148, 152, 159, 160, 161, Armstrong A.H. 40, 238 163, 164, 169, 177, 197, Athanasius 34, 48, 57, 62, 64, 66, 204, 233, 237, 238, 239, 69, 71, 72, 73, 74, 75, 76, 240 77, 79, 90, 146, 147, 227, Analytica Posteriora 233, 237 233, 234, 238, 239, 240, Analytica Priora 233 241 Categoriae 233 Contra Gentes 74, 233 De anima 122, 233 De decretis Niceane synodi 65, De generatione animalium 233 233 De interpretatione 169, 233 De Incarnatione 71, 74, 233 Ethica Nicomachea 233 De Synodis Arimini in Italia et knowledge of substance (ὀυσία) Seleuciae in Isauria 234 Metaphysica 233 245 Tomasz Stpie and Karolina Kochaczyk-Boniska - 9783631757369 Downloaded from PubFactory at 09/26/2021 05:34:38AM via free access Epistula ad episcopos Aegypti at theory of names 6, 166, 229, Libyae 234 239 Epistula ad Serapionem 234 worship and knowledge 99 knowledge of God 69, 71, 72, negativetheology 73, 77 Beeley Ch.
    [Show full text]
  • Unknown God, Known in His Activities EUROPEAN STUDIES in THEOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY and HISTORY of RELIGIONS Edited by Bartosz Adamczewski
    18 What can man know about God? This question became one of the main Tomasz Stępień / problems during the 4th-century Trinitarian controversy, which is the focus Karolina Kochańczyk-Bonińska of this book. Especially during the second phase of the conflict, the claims of Anomean Eunomius caused an emphatic response of Orthodox writers, mainly Basil of Caesarea and Gregory of Nyssa. Eunomius formulated two ways of theology to show that we can know both the substance (ousia) and activities (energeiai) of God. The Orthodox Fathers demonstrated that we can know only the external activities of God, while the essence is entirely incom- prehensible. Therefore the 4th-century discussion on whether the Father and the Son are of the same substance was the turning point in the development Unknown God, of negative theology and shaping the Christian conception of God. Known Unknown God, Known God, Unknown in His Activities in His Activities Incomprehensibility of God during the Trinitarian Controversy of the 4th Century stopibhuarly Jewish Sources Tomasz Stępień is Associate Professor at the Faculty of Theology, Cardi- Karolina Kochańczyk-Bonińska · nal Stefan Wyszyński University in Warsaw. He researches and publishes / on Ancient Philosophy, Early Christian Philosophy, Natural Theology and Philosophy of Religion. European Studies in Theology, Karolina Kochańczyk-Bonińska is Assistant Professor at the Institute of Philosophy and History of Religions the Humanities and Social Sciences, War Studies University in Warsaw. She researches and publishes on Early Christian Philosophy and translates Edited by Bartosz Adamczewski patristic texts. Stępień Tomasz ISBN 978-3-631-75736-9 EST_018 275736-Stepien_TL_A5HC 151x214 globalL.indd 1 04.07.18 17:07 18 What can man know about God? This question became one of the main Tomasz Stępień / problems during the 4th-century Trinitarian controversy, which is the focus Karolina Kochańczyk-Bonińska of this book.
    [Show full text]
  • Athens and Byzantium: Platonic Political Philosophy in Religious Empire Jeremiah Heath Russell Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2010 Athens and Byzantium: Platonic political philosophy in religious empire Jeremiah Heath Russell Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Russell, Jeremiah Heath, "Athens and Byzantium: Platonic political philosophy in religious empire" (2010). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 2978. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/2978 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. ATHENS AND BYZANTIUM: PLATONIC POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN RELIGIOUS EMPIRE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Jeremiah Heath Russell B.A., The Southern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2001 M. Div., The Southern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2003 M.A., Baylor University, 2006 August, 2010 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation was not possible without the numerous sources of support that I received throughout my graduate studies. First, I must thank my major professor, James R. Stoner, Jr., whose encouragement was there from my earliest days at LSU until the completion of this program. He is a model intellectual with an uncanny ability to identify the heart of the matter and to offer penetrating questions. My commitment to the importance of the political, reflected in this dissertation, I owe to him.
    [Show full text]
  • The Platonist Christianity of Marius Victorinus
    religions Article The Platonist Christianity of Marius Victorinus Stephen A. Cooper Department of Religious Studies, Franklin & Marshall College, Lancaster, PA 17604-3003, USA; [email protected] Academic Editor: Warren Smith Received: 18 August 2016; Accepted: 20 September 2016; Published: 1 October 2016 Abstract: Marius Victorinus is the first representative of Platonist Christianity in the Latin church whose works display knowledge of Plotinus and Porphyry. Scholarship prior to the work of Pierre Hadot in the mid-twentieth century tended to treat him as an isolated figure, ignored by later Latin Christians who knew better how to moderate their Platonist borrowings. Scholars since then have been more willing to see Victorinus as earnest Christian who let himself be guided by the community standards of the church as laid out in the biblical canon and creedal definitions. Recent work on Victorinus’ sources has shown him to be more eclectic in his use of philosophical sources than previously thought and for that reason more creative in formulating his Platonist–Christian synthesis. After reviewing important lines of development in scholarship on Victorinus, this article focuses on his Platonist-inspired teaching about the soul as expressed in the three genres of his Christian works: theological treatises, hymns, and scriptural commentaries. The consistent “insider” stance of Victorinus in all of these different genres of theological writings suggests that the extremely Platonist character of his theology, when considered in light of
    [Show full text]
  • Numenius and Greek Sources of Justin's Theology Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX
    Numenius and Greek Sources of Justin's Theology ! Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX ! Introduction Someone estimated that there have been about 23,000 Christianities. I would venture to say further that there are probably as many Christianities as there are believers claiming to be Christians. Such a statement, however, is not productive for the evaluation of evolution of a religion. It would be better if we could differentiate some general patterns in the development of a key religious doctrine. It seems that the evolution of Christianity can be analyzed in terms of four general patterns: 1. Jewish messianism with the figure of the messiah as a glorified man and the expected earthly Kingdom of God. This is the basic message of the Gospels. 2. Hellenistic Christianity in its two forms: in one the messiah figure was transformed into cosmic Greek Logos; and the other Gnostic, in which Logos is only one of many divine manifestations. 3. Trinitarian or syncretic Christianity which tends to reemphasize the unitarian character of the divinity preserving the Greek triadic speculations and incorporating especially the Egyptian triune doctrine. 4. Servetian unitarian Christianity which interprets divinity and its manifestations as a historical, modalistic process. My interest in studying Christianity is focused on the evolution of this religion and finding the sources of theological doctrines and links between its various stages. Justin Martyr (114-165 C.E.) is the first Christian apologist who speculated on religious matters in philosophical terms of his time and developed one of the first systems of Christian theological thought.i Due to his background in Greek schooling, he reinterpreted the story of the New Testament in terms of Greek religious-philosophical concepts just like Philo reinterpreted the Old Testament, and followed his road to Hellenization of the Hebrew myth.
    [Show full text]
  • Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-19495-3 — Monastic Education in Late Antiquity Edited by Lillian I
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-19495-3 — Monastic Education in Late Antiquity Edited by Lillian I. Larsen , Samuel Rubenson Index More Information Index Abraham, Bishop of Carrhae, 246 Aquila, 164, 293 Acacius, 58 Arcadius, 155 Aelius Theon, 187, 209 Archiadas, 250 Aëtius, 57 Arian, 43, 75 Agrippa, 286 Arians, 40, 53, 58, 59, 66, 154, 169 Aland, 287 Aristobulus, 259 Alcibiades, 250, 261 Ariston of Chios, 231 Alexandria, 40, 51, 53, 55, 56, 61, 70, 89, 153, Aristotelian, 167, 168 154, 155, 160, 178, 179, 181, 239, 249, 262 Aristotle, 54, 56, 57, 58, 105, 154, 164, 166, 167, al-Hakim, 180 168, 176, 180, 236, 249, 250, 261, 262, 273 Amato, 183 Aristoxenus, 236, 251 Amélineau, 296 Arsenius, 102, 103, 155, 180, 219, 220, 221, Amelius, 240 223, 333 Amheida, 77 Asclepiodotus of Alexandria, 261 Ammonius, 61, 71 Asmis, 227, 229 Ammoun, 70 Athanasius, 34, 35, 36, 37, 38, 39, 40, 41, 42, 43, Anaxagoras, 260 46, 47, 48, 49, 50, 51, 56, 153, 154, 156, 168, Andragathius, 57 234, 236, 237, 256, 288, 320 Anselm of Canterbury, 284, 285 Athenaeus of Naucratis, 228 Antinoopolis, 77 Athenian, 57, 241, 245, 248, 253 Antioch, 45, 49, 55, 57, 105, 237, 239, 240, Athens, 55, 237, 241, 242, 249, 250, 252, 242, 249 254, 255 Antiochus of Ascalon, 245 Augustine, 35, 42, 50, 51, 167, 168, 230, 238, Antisthenes, 231, 232, 244 261, 318, 319 Antony, 18, 22, 26, 31, 35, 36, 37, 38, 39, 40, 41, Avita, 276 42, 43, 45, 47, 48, 49, 50, 51, 57, 71, 75, 100, Azéma, 240 102, 103, 154, 184, 221, 222, 223, 232, 234, 235, 236, 256, 259, 297, 325, 332 Bács, 126 Antony, translator,
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of the Egyptian One God in Neoplatonism and the Greek Magical Papyri
    2021 The god Amun. The Great Harris Papyrus, Dyn. XX, British Museum. The Ascent to the Hidden One: The Reception of the Egyptian One God in Neoplatonism and the Greek Magical Papyri Word Count: 39,935 Tiana Blazevic The University of Adelaide Department of Classics, Ancient History and Archaeology Table of Contents Declaration 3 Abstract 4 Acknowledgements 5 Abbreviations (used in the notes and appendices) 6 Introduction 7 The Research Aims 8 The Background: The Supreme Being, ritual acts, and power dynamics 10 The Sources 12 The Greek Magical Papyri: Background and problems of authorship 14 Methodology 16 Chapter Overview 19 Chapter 1 21 1.1 Introduction: Historical Context 21 1.2 Egyptian Mouthpieces: Plato and Egypt 24 1.3 A Greek Egypt: Plutarch’s On Isis and Osiris 28 1.4 Orientalising discourse in Iamblichus and Porphyry 31 1.5 Thinking with the Egyptians: The Egyptian priests in the exchange between Porphyry and Iamblichus. 33 1.6 Conclusion 36 Chapter Two 38 2.1 Introduction 38 2.2 Amun in the Hymns & Egyptian Theology 39 2.3 The Evolution of the One God 43 2.4 Comparing Cosmogonies: Egyptians and Neoplatonist 45 2.5 Creation and Manifestation: New Sources Analysed 46 2.6 Creation and the One God 49 2.7 The One and All: New Evidence 53 2.8 Egyptian Theology in Neoplatonic Terms 55 2.9 Conclusion 61 Chapter Three 63 Introduction 63 3.1 Communing or Coercing? Ritual Mastery and Magic 63 3.2 Theurgy, Theosophy and Ritual Authority 67 3.3 Knowledge of the Gods: Porphyry the High Priest of Philosophy 70 3.4 Ritual Mastery and the
    [Show full text]
  • Numenius of Apamea on Moses: an Allegorical Interpretation
    Numenius of Apamea on Moses: An Allegorical Interpretation This paper gives a new interpretation of one of the fragments of the second- century Middle Platonist Numenius of Apamea. Fragment 9a (des Places) retells the story of Moses and his leadership of the Jewish Exodus, and in particular his battle with the Egyptian priests Iannes and Iambres. Moses is called “Musaeus,” and is described as “most able to pray to God.” The Egyptian priests with whom he contends are “second to none in wizardry (mageuein).” Iannes and Iambres are the grammatical subject of this fragment. This has led some to assume that the Egyptian priests should be taken as the heroes of this passage, that they are the sympathetic characters attempting to save the Egyptians from the wizard Musaeus (see Petty ad loc). There are several reasons why this interpretation should be rejected. First of all, the name “Musaeus” suggests Orphic ties for the Jewish prophet. Second, and most importantly, there is a contrast that Numenius sets up between Musaeus and his prayer to god as opposed to the Egyptian priests and their magic. It is obvious who should be the hero of the passage: Musaeus prays to god. If God is good, then the “most able to pray to God” must be a good agent. Opposed to prayer is the magic of the Egyptians. Here we see implied a radical opposition. I propose a Platonic allegorical interpretation to this passages: Musaeus’ power to pray represents the power of Platonic Providence in the world. The Egyptians’ magic must be the opposite of this Providence.
    [Show full text]