Replicator Dynamics for Optional Public Good Games Christoph Hauertwz,Silviademontewy, Josef Hofbauerw and Karl Sigmundnw8

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Replicator Dynamics for Optional Public Good Games Christoph Hauertwz,Silviademontewy, Josef Hofbauerw and Karl Sigmundnw8 J. theor. Biol. (2002) 218, 187–194 doi:10.1006/yjtbi.3067, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Replicator Dynamics for Optional Public Good Games Christoph Hauertwz,SilviaDeMontewy, Josef Hofbauerw and Karl Sigmundnw8 w Institute for Mathematics, University of Vienna, Strudlhofgasse 4, A-1090 Vienna, Austria z Department of Zoology, University of British Columbia, 6270 University Boulevard, Vancouver, BC, Canada V6T1Z4 y Department of Physics, Danish Technical University, DK-2800 Kgs. Lyngby, Denmark and 811ASA, A-2361 Laxenburg, Austria (Received on 8 October 2001, Accepted in revised form on 12 April 2002) The public goods game represents a straightforward generalization of the prisoner’s dilemma to an arbitrary number of players. Since the dominant strategy is to defect, both classical and evolutionary game theory predict the asocial outcome that no player contributes to the public goods. In contrast to the compulsory public goods game, optional participation provides a natural way to avoid deadlocks in the state of mutual defection. The three resulting strategiesFcollaboration or defection in the public goods game, as well as not joining at allFare studied by means of a replicator dynamics, which can be completely analysed in spite of the fact that the payoff terms are nonlinear. If cooperation is valuable enough, the dynamics exhibits a rock-scissors-paper type of cycling between the three strategies, leading to sizeable average levels of cooperation in the population. Thus, voluntary participation makes cooperation feasible. But for each strategy, the average payoff value remains equal to the earnings of those not participating in the public goods game. r 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. Introduction In this article, we present another mechanism to Most theories on the emergence of cooperation achieve sizeable levels of cooperation in a popula- among selfish individuals are based on kin tion. The following investigation is based on the . selection (Hamilton, 1963), group selection public goods game (see Fehr& G achter, 2002; (Wilson & Sober, 1994) and reciprocal altruism Kagel & Roth, 1995) which represents a natural (Trivers, 1971). In all three models, cooperative extension of the prisoner’s dilemma to an arbitrary behavioris attained throughbasic mechanisms number of players (see Boyd & Richerson, 1988; of discrimination enabling individuals to target Dawes, 1980; Hauert & Schuster, 1997). their altruistic acts towards certain partners In a typical public goods game, an experi- only. menter gives 20 dollars to each of eight players. The players may contribute part or all of their money to some common pool. The experimenter then triples this amount and divides it equally n Corresponding author. Institute for Mathematics, Uni- among the eight players, irrespective of the versity of Vienna, Strudlhofgasse 4, A-1090 Vienna, Austria. Tel.: +43-3-4277-50612; fax: +43-1-4277-9506. amount of theirindividual contribution.If all E-mail address: [email protected] (K. Sigmund). players contribute maximally, they will end up 0022-5193/02/$35.00/0 r 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. 188 C. HAUERT ET AL. with 60 dollars each. But each individual is faced whetherto participatein the public goods game with the temptation to exploit, as a free rider, or not. [For a similar approach in the prisoner’s the contributions of the co-players. Hence, the dilemma see Batali & Kitcher(1995); Orbell& dominating strategy is to invest nothing at all. If Dawes (1993)]. Individuals unwilling to join the all players do this, they will not increase their public goods game are termed loners. These initial capital. In this sense, the ‘‘rational’’ players prefer to rely on a small but fixed payoff equilibrium solution prescribed to ‘‘homo oeco- Pl ¼ sc with nomicus’’ leads to economic stalemate. In actual experiments, players tend to invest a lot, how- 0osor À 1; ð2Þ ever: typically, in the first round, they invest 10 dollars or more (Fehr & Gachter,. 2002). such that the members in a group where all Public goods games are abundant in human cooperate are better off than loners, but loners and animal societies, and can be seen as basic are better off than members in a group of examples of economic interactions (see e.g. defectors. Binmore, 1994; Dugatkin, 1997). For the optional public goods game, there are thus three behavioral types in the population: (a) The Model the loners unwilling to join the public goods We considera largepopulation of players. game, (b) the cooperators ready to join the From time to time, N such players are chosen group and to contribute their effort, and (c) the randomly. Within such a group, players can either defectors who join, but do not contribute. contribute some fixed amount c ornothing at all. Assuming that groups form randomly, the pay- The return of the public good, i.e. the payoff to the offs for the different strategies Pc; Pd and Pl are players in the group, depends on the abundance of then determined by the relative frequencies x; y and z of the three strategies. cooperators. If nc denotes theirnumberamong the public goods players, the net payoff for coopera- tors Pc and defectors Pd is given by The Equations of Motion n Evolutionary game theory assumes that a P ¼Àc þ rc c; c N strategy’s payoff determines the growth rate of its frequency within the population. More n precisely, following (Weibull (1995), Schlag P ¼ rc c; d N (1998) and Hofbauer& Sigmund (1998), we postulate in ourmodel that playersusing where r denotes the interest rate on the common strategies i ¼ 1; y; n occasionally compare their pool. Fora public goods game deservingits name, payoff with that of a randomly chosen ‘‘model’’ we must have memberof the population, and adopt the strategy of their model with a probability 1 r N: ð1Þ o o proportional to the difference between the The first inequality states that if all do the same, model’s payoff and theirown, if this is they are better off cooperating than defecting; the positive (and with probability 0 otherwise). In second inequality states that each individual is the continuous time model, the evolution of the betteroff defecting than cooperating.Selfish frequencies xi of the strategies i is given by players will therefore always avoid the cost of X cooperation c; i.e. a collective of selfish players will x’i ¼ xixjðPi À PjÞð3Þ nevercooperate.Defection is the dominating j strategy. Hence both classical and evolutionary game theory predict that all players will defect, and with 1pi; jpn; which reduces to the replicator obtain zero payoff. equation We now extend the public goods game. In this ’ % optional public goods game, players can decide xi ¼ xiðPi À PÞ; ð4Þ OPTIONAL PUBLIC GOOD GAMES 189 P % where P ¼ xjPj is the average payoff in the game. In the case S ¼ 1 (no co-playershows up) population. we assume that the playerhas no otheroption To be precise, we consider a very large, well- than to play as a loner, and obtains payoff s: mixed population with three types of players: This happens with probability zNÀ1: Fora given loners, cooperators and defectors. From time to playerwilling to join the public goods game, the time, sample groups of N players are randomly probability of finding, among the N À 1 other chosen and offered to participate in a single players in the sample, S À 1 co-players joining public goods game. Note that in large popula- the group (S41), is tions, the probability that two players ever ! encounteragain can be neglected. Depending N À 1 ð1 À zÞSÀ1zNÀS: on their type, players either refuse to participate S À 1 orjoin the public goods game. In the lattercase, they eitherdefect, orcooperate.But, their The probability that m of these players are strategies are specified beforehand, and do not cooperators, and S À 1 À m defectors, is depend on the composition of the sampled ! group. In particular, we do not consider condi- x m y SÀ1Àm S À 1 tional strategies of the type: cooperate if and : x þ y x þ y m only if the group contains more than two cooperators, or the like. In that case, the payoff fordefectorsis rm=S: Each playeris sampled a numberof times, and Hence the expected payoff fora defectorin a obtains an average payoff which depends on his group of S players (S ¼ 2; y; N)is strategy as well as the composition of the entire ! population. This composition changes according r XSÀ1 x m y SÀ1Àm S À 1 to the replicator dynamics [see eqns (3) and (4)]. m S x þ y x þ y The intuition behind the dynamics is that m¼0 m occasionallyFand independently of the sam- r x pling of the public goods teamsFa randomly ¼ ðS À 1Þ : chosen player A compares his or her payoff with S x þ y that of anotherplayer B (also randomly chosen, Thus, within the entire population and not limited to ! the ‘‘public goods’’ groups to which A belonged), XN NÀ1 x N À 1 and adopts the strategy of B; if it yields a higher Pd ¼ sz þ r 1 À z S À 1 payoff, with a probability proportional to the S¼1 difference in their payoffs. Opportunities for 1 updating, i.e. changing the strategy, are sup- ð1 À zÞSÀ1zNÀS 1 À posed to occurmuch less frequentlythan S opportunities to play in a public goods group. x We emphasize that there are other reasonable ¼ szNÀ1 þ r game dynamics, but forthe replicatorequation 1 À z we can produce a full analysis. "# ! Forsimplicity and without loss of generality, XN N À 1 1 1 À ð1 À zÞSÀ1zNÀS we set the cost c of cooperation equal to 1: The S À 1 S payoff forlonersis then given by the constant S¼1 Pl ¼ s: N À 1 N and using ¼ S=N leads to S À 1 S In order to compute the payoff values for cooperators and defectors, we first derive the N NÀ1 x 1 À z probability that S of the N sampled individuals Pd ¼ sz þ r 1 À : ð5Þ are actually willing to join the public goods 1 À z Nð1 À zÞ 190 C.
Recommended publications
  • The Logic of Costly Punishment Reversed: Expropriation of Free-Riders and Outsiders∗,†
    The logic of costly punishment reversed: expropriation of free-riders and outsiders∗ ,† David Hugh-Jones Carlo Perroni University of East Anglia University of Warwick and CAGE January 5, 2017 Abstract Current literature views the punishment of free-riders as an under-supplied pub- lic good, carried out by individuals at a cost to themselves. It need not be so: often, free-riders’ property can be forcibly appropriated by a coordinated group. This power makes punishment profitable, but it can also be abused. It is easier to contain abuses, and focus group punishment on free-riders, in societies where coordinated expropriation is harder. Our theory explains why public goods are un- dersupplied in heterogenous communities: because groups target minorities instead of free-riders. In our laboratory experiment, outcomes were more efficient when coordination was more difficult, while outgroup members were targeted more than ingroup members, and reacted differently to punishment. KEY WORDS: Cooperation, costly punishment, group coercion, heterogeneity JEL CLASSIFICATION: H1, H4, N4, D02 ∗We are grateful to CAGE and NIBS grant ES/K002201/1 for financial support. We would like to thank Mark Harrison, Francesco Guala, Diego Gambetta, David Skarbek, participants at conferences and presentations including EPCS, IMEBESS, SAET and ESA, and two anonymous reviewers for their comments. †Comments and correspondence should be addressed to David Hugh-Jones, School of Economics, University of East Anglia, [email protected] 1 Introduction Deterring free-riding is a central element of social order. Most students of collective action believe that punishing free-riders is costly to the punisher, but benefits the community as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Recency, Records and Recaps: Learning and Non-Equilibrium Behavior in a Simple Decision Problem*
    Recency, Records and Recaps: Learning and Non-equilibrium Behavior in a Simple Decision Problem* DREW FUDENBERG, Harvard University ALEXANDER PEYSAKHOVICH, Facebook Nash equilibrium takes optimization as a primitive, but suboptimal behavior can persist in simple stochastic decision problems. This has motivated the development of other equilibrium concepts such as cursed equilibrium and behavioral equilibrium. We experimentally study a simple adverse selection (or “lemons”) problem and find that learning models that heavily discount past information (i.e. display recency bias) explain patterns of behavior better than Nash, cursed or behavioral equilibrium. Providing counterfactual information or a record of past outcomes does little to aid convergence to optimal strategies, but providing sample averages (“recaps”) gets individuals most of the way to optimality. Thus recency effects are not solely due to limited memory but stem from some other form of cognitive constraints. Our results show the importance of going beyond static optimization and incorporating features of human learning into economic models. Categories & Subject Descriptors: J.4 [Social and Behavioral Sciences] Economics Author Keywords & Phrases: Learning, behavioral economics, recency, equilibrium concepts 1. INTRODUCTION Understanding when repeat experience can lead individuals to optimal behavior is crucial for the success of game theory and behavioral economics. Equilibrium analysis assumes all individuals choose optimal strategies while much research in behavioral economics
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods Agreements with Other-Regarding Preferences
    NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PUBLIC GOODS AGREEMENTS WITH OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES Charles D. Kolstad Working Paper 17017 http://www.nber.org/papers/w17017 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02138 May 2011 Department of Economics and Bren School, University of California, Santa Barbara; Resources for the Future; and NBER. Comments from Werner Güth, Kaj Thomsson and Philipp Wichardt and discussions with Gary Charness and Michael Finus have been appreciated. Outstanding research assistance from Trevor O’Grady and Adam Wright is gratefully acknowledged. Funding from the University of California Center for Energy and Environmental Economics (UCE3) is also acknowledged and appreciated. The views expressed herein are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Bureau of Economic Research. NBER working papers are circulated for discussion and comment purposes. They have not been peer- reviewed or been subject to the review by the NBER Board of Directors that accompanies official NBER publications. © 2011 by Charles D. Kolstad. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceed two paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission provided that full credit, including © notice, is given to the source. Public Goods Agreements with Other-Regarding Preferences Charles D. Kolstad NBER Working Paper No. 17017 May 2011, Revised June 2012 JEL No. D03,H4,H41,Q5 ABSTRACT Why cooperation occurs when noncooperation appears to be individually rational has been an issue in economics for at least a half century. In the 1960’s and 1970’s the context was cooperation in the prisoner’s dilemma game; in the 1980’s concern shifted to voluntary provision of public goods; in the 1990’s, the literature on coalition formation for public goods provision emerged, in the context of coalitions to provide transboundary pollution abatement.
    [Show full text]
  • The Impact of Beliefs on Effort in Telecommuting Teams
    The impact of beliefs on effort in telecommuting teams E. Glenn Dutcher, Krista Jabs Saral Working Papers in Economics and Statistics 2012-22 University of Innsbruck http://eeecon.uibk.ac.at/ University of Innsbruck Working Papers in Economics and Statistics The series is jointly edited and published by - Department of Economics - Department of Public Finance - Department of Statistics Contact Address: University of Innsbruck Department of Public Finance Universitaetsstrasse 15 A-6020 Innsbruck Austria Tel: + 43 512 507 7171 Fax: + 43 512 507 2970 E-mail: [email protected] The most recent version of all working papers can be downloaded at http://eeecon.uibk.ac.at/wopec/ For a list of recent papers see the backpages of this paper. The Impact of Beliefs on E¤ort in Telecommuting Teams E. Glenn Dutchery Krista Jabs Saralz February 2014 Abstract The use of telecommuting policies remains controversial for many employers because of the perceived opportunity for shirking outside of the traditional workplace; a problem that is potentially exacerbated if employees work in teams. Using a controlled experiment, where individuals work in teams with varying numbers of telecommuters, we test how telecommut- ing a¤ects the e¤ort choice of workers. We …nd that di¤erences in productivity within the team do not result from shirking by telecommuters; rather, changes in e¤ort result from an individual’s belief about the productivity of their teammates. In line with stereotypes, a high proportion of both telecommuting and non-telecommuting participants believed their telecommuting partners were less productive. Consequently, lower expectations of partner productivity resulted in lower e¤ort when individuals were partnered with telecommuters.
    [Show full text]
  • Noisy Directional Learning and the Logit Equilibrium*
    CSE: AR SJOE 011 Scand. J. of Economics 106(*), *–*, 2004 DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9442.2004.000376.x Noisy Directional Learning and the Logit Equilibrium* Simon P. Anderson University of Virginia, Charlottesville, VA 22903-3328, USA [email protected] Jacob K. Goeree California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125, USA [email protected] Charles A. Holt University of Virginia, Charlottesville, VA 22903-3328, USA [email protected] PROOF Abstract We specify a dynamic model in which agents adjust their decisions toward higher payoffs, subject to normal error. This process generates a probability distribution of players’ decisions that evolves over time according to the Fokker–Planck equation. The dynamic process is stable for all potential games, a class of payoff structures that includes several widely studied games. In equilibrium, the distributions that determine expected payoffs correspond to the distributions that arise from the logit function applied to those expected payoffs. This ‘‘logit equilibrium’’ forms a stochastic generalization of the Nash equilibrium and provides a possible explanation of anomalous laboratory data. ECTED Keywords: Bounded rationality; noisy directional learning; Fokker–Planck equation; potential games; logit equilibrium JEL classification: C62; C73 I. Introduction Small errors and shocks may have offsetting effects in some economic con- texts, in which case there is not much to be gained from an explicit analysis of stochasticNCORR elements. In other contexts, a small amount of randomness can * We gratefully acknowledge financial support from the National Science Foundation (SBR- 9818683U and SBR-0094800), the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation and the Dutch National Science Foundation (NWO-VICI 453.03.606).
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Social Interactions
    Beta September 2015 version 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS Les Joueurs de Carte, Paul Cézanne, 1892-95, Courtauld Institute of Art A COMBINATION OF SELF-INTEREST, A REGARD FOR THE WELLBEING OF OTHERS, AND APPROPRIATE INSTITUTIONS CAN YIELD DESIRABLE SOCIAL OUTCOMES WHEN PEOPLE INTERACT • Game theory is a way of understanding how people interact based on the constraints that limit their actions, their motives and their beliefs about what others will do • Experiments and other evidence show that self-interest, a concern for others and a preference for fairness are all important motives explaining how people interact • In most interactions there is some conflict of interest between people, and also some opportunity for mutual gain • The pursuit of self-interest can lead either to results that are considered good by all participants, or sometimes to outcomes that none of those concerned would prefer • Self-interest can be harnessed for the general good in markets by governments limiting the actions that people are free to take, and by one’s peers imposing punishments on actions that lead to bad outcomes • A concern for others and for fairness allows us to internalise the effects of our actions on others, and so can contribute to good social outcomes See www.core-econ.org for the full interactive version of The Economy by The CORE Project. Guide yourself through key concepts with clickable figures, test your understanding with multiple choice questions, look up key terms in the glossary, read full mathematical derivations in the Leibniz supplements, watch economists explain their work in Economists in Action – and much more.
    [Show full text]
  • Section 3-Dynamic Gamesand Intellectual Property
    ECON 522 - SECTION 3-DYNAMIC GAMES AND INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY I Dynamic Games Dynamic games are just like static games, except players move sequentially rather than simulta- neously. The definition of Nash equilibrium is still the same (everyone is playing a best response), but now we can end up with NE that don’t make a lot of sense. In the example from class, a start up firm has to choose “enter” or “do not enter,” and the incumbent firm must choose to “fight” or “accommodate.” However, we end up with a strange NE in which the new firm chooses not to enter and the incumbent chooses fight, even though the first firm should figure that a rational incumbent firm would never actually fight should the first firm enter the market. Thus we intro- duced the idea of sequential rationality: everyone believes everyone will behave rationally at every point in time. This leads to a “refinement” of Nash equilibrium, which we call subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE), which is just a NE in which everyone is behaving sequentially rationally. We solve these games using backwards induction, which just means we start from the end of the game and see what choices people would make if they ever reach those end situations, and we work our way back up to the beginning. You can use this method to solve a lot of strategic interactive games, such as tic-tac-toe, or checkers. I.1 Back to a static game- the Public Goods Game from class p Setup: There are 100 people with identical preferences represented by: u = 10 X − x, where X is the total amount of money (including what that individual contributes) donated for a public park, and x is the amount donated by the individual.
    [Show full text]
  • Success Rates in Simplified Threshold Public Goods Games - a Theoretical Model
    Success rates in simplified threshold public goods games - a theoretical model by Christian Feige No. 70 | JUNE 2015 WORKING PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS KIT – University of the State of Baden-Wuerttemberg and National Laboratory of the Helmholtz Association econpapers.wiwi.kit.edu Impressum Karlsruher Institut für Technologie (KIT) Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften Institut für Volkswirtschaftslehre (ECON) Schlossbezirk 12 76131 Karlsruhe KIT – Universität des Landes Baden-Württemberg und nationales Forschungszentrum in der Helmholtz-Gemeinschaft Working Paper Series in Economics No. 70, June 2015 ISSN 2190-9806 econpapers.wiwi.kit.edu Success rates in simplied threshold public goods games a theoretical model Christian Feigea,¦ aKarlsruhe Institute of Technology (KIT), Institute of Economics (ECON), Neuer Zirkel 3, 76131 Karlsruhe, Germany Abstract This paper develops a theoretical model based on theories of equilibrium selection in order to predict success rates in threshold public goods games, i.e., the probability with which a group of players provides enough contri- bution in sum to exceed a predened threshold value. For this purpose, a prototypical version of a threshold public goods game is simplied to a 2 ¢ 2 normal-form game. The simplied game consists of only one focal pure strat- egy for positive contributions aiming at an ecient allocation of the threshold value. The game's second pure strategy, zero contributions, represents a safe choice for players who do not want to risk coordination failure. By calculat- ing the stability sets of these two pure strategies, success rates can be put in explicit relation to the game parameters. It is also argued that this approach has similarities with determining the relative size of the strategies' basins of attraction in a stochastic dynamical system (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods Games and Psychological Utility: Theory and Evidence
    School of Business Economics Division Public goods games and psychological utility: Theory and evidence Sanjit Dhami, University of Leicester Mengxing Wei, University of Leicester Ali al-Nowaihi, University of Leicester Working Paper No. 16/17 Public goods games and psychological utility: Theory and evidence. Sanjit Dhami Mengxing Weiy Ali al-Nowaihiz 10 November 2016 Abstract We consider a public goods game which incorporates guilt-aversion/surprise- seeking and the attribution of intentions behind these emotions (Battigalli and Dufwenberg, 2007; Khalmetski et al., 2015). We implement the induced beliefs method (Ellingsen et al., 2010) and a within-subjects design using the strategy method. Previous studies mainly use dictator games - whose results may not be robust to adding strategic components. We find that guilt-aversion is far more im- portant than surprise-seeking; and that the attribution of intentions behind guilt- aversion/surprise-seeking is important. Our between-subjects analysis confirms the results of the within-subjects design. Keywords: Public goods games; psychological game theory; surprise-seeking/guilt- aversion; attribution of intentions; induced beliefs method; strategy method; within- subjects design. JEL Classification: D01 (Microeconomic Behavior: Underlying Principles); D03 (Be- havioral Microeconomics: Underlying Principles); H41 (Public Goods). Corresponding author. Division of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, Uni- versity Road, Leicester. LE1 7RH, UK. Phone: +44-116-2522086. Fax: +44-116-2522908. E-mail: [email protected]. yDivision of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, University Road, Leicester, LE1 7RH. Fax: +44-116-2522908. Email: [email protected] zDivision of Economics, School of Business, University of Leicester, University Road, Leicester.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Dynamics in the Public Goods Games with Switching
    CHAOS 28, 103105 (2018) Evolutionary dynamics in the public goods games with switching between punishment and exclusion Linjie Liu,1 Shengxian Wang,1 Xiaojie Chen,1,a) and Matjaž Perc2,b) 1School of Mathematical Sciences, University of Electronic Science and Technology of China, Chengdu 611731, China 2Faculty of Natural Sciences and Mathematics, University of Maribor, Koroška cesta 160, SI-2000 Maribor, Slovenia; Complexity Science Hub Vienna, Josefstädterstraße 39, A-1080 Vienna, Austria (Received 8 August 2018; accepted 23 September 2018; published online 9 October 2018) Pro-social punishment and exclusion are common means to elevate the level of cooperation among unrelated individuals. Indeed, it is worth pointing out that the combined use of these two strategies is quite common across human societies. However, it is still not known how a combined strategy where punishment and exclusion are switched can promote cooperation from the theoretical perspective. In this paper, we thus propose two different switching strategies, namely, peer switching that is based on peer punishment and peer exclusion, and pool switching that is based on pool punishment and pool exclusion. Individuals adopting the switching strategy will punish defectors when their numbers are below a threshold and exclude them otherwise. We study how the two switching strategies influence the evolutionary dynamics in the public goods game. We show that an intermediate value of the threshold leads to a stable coexistence of cooperators, defectors, and players adopting the switching strategy in a well-mixed population, and this regardless of whether the pool-based or the peer-based switching strategy is introduced. Moreover, we show that the pure exclusion strategy alone is able to evoke a limit cycle attractor in the evolutionary dynamics, such that cooperation can coexist with other strategies.
    [Show full text]
  • Cooperation in the Finitely Repeated Prisoner's Dilemma
    Cooperation in the Finitely Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma Matthew Embrey Guillaume R. Fr´echette Sevgi Yuksel U. of Sussex ................................ NYU ................................... UCSB June, 2017 Abstract More than half a century after the first experiment on the finitely repeated prisoner’s dilemma, evidence on whether cooperation decreases with experience–as suggested by backward induction–remains inconclusive. This paper provides a meta-analysis of prior experimental research and reports the results of a new experiment to elucidate how coop- eration varies with the environment in this canonical game. We describe forces that a↵ect initial play (formation of cooperation) and unraveling (breakdown of cooperation). First, contrary to the backward induction prediction, the parameters of the repeated game have a significant e↵ect on initial cooperation. We identify how these parameters impact the value of cooperation–as captured by the size of the basin of attraction of Always Defect–to account for an important part of this e↵ect. Second, despite these initial di↵erences, the evolution of behavior is consistent with the unraveling logic of backward induction for all parameter combinations. Importantly, despite the seemingly contradictory results across studies, this paper establishes a systematic pattern of behavior: subjects converge to use threshold strategies that conditionally cooperate until a threshold round; and conditional on establishing cooperation, the first defection round moves earlier with experience. Sim- ulation results generated from a learning model estimated at the subject level provide insights into the long-term dynamics and the forces that slow down the unraveling of cooperation. We wish to thank the editor, anonymous referees, James Andreoni, Yoella Bereby-Meyer, Russell Cooper, Pedro Dal B´o, Douglas DeJong, Robert Forsythe, Drew Fudenberg, Daniel Friedman, P.J.
    [Show full text]
  • THE HUMAN SIDE of MECHANISM DESIGN a Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont
    THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley December 4, 2008 [email protected] http://www.econ.berkeley.edu/~mcfadden/index.shtml ABSTRACT This paper considers the human side of mechanism design, the behavior of economic agents in gathering and processing information and responding to incentives. I first give an overview of the subject of mechanism design, and then examine a pervasive premise in this field that economic agents are rational in their information processing and decisions. Examples from applied mechanism design identify the roles of perceptions and inference in agent behavior, and the influence of systematic irrationalities and sociality on agent responses. These examples suggest that tolerance of behavioral faults be added to the criteria for good mechanism design. In principle-agent problems for example, designers should consider using experimental treatments in contracts, and statistical post-processing of agent responses, to identify and mitigate the effects of agent non-compliance with contract incentives. KEYWORDS: mechanism_design, principal-agent_problem, juries, welfare_theory JEL CLASSIFICATION: D000, D600, D610, D710, D800, C420, C700 THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden1 1. Introduction The study of mechanism design, the systematic analysis of resource allocation institutions and processes, has been the most fundamental development
    [Show full text]