<<

arXiv:1705.07201v1 [quant-ph] 19 May 2017 ie ytesetu of spectrum the by given iesoa ibr pc iha rhnra ai fui vectors unit of notation) basis bra-ket orthonormal Dirac’s an with space Hilbert dimensional oosrals o xml,tesi faspin-1 a of the example, For . to hl ti ntestate the in is it while ehnc.We nobservable an When mechanics. of ftesse saui etrin vector unit a is system the of ehia esn,ti utotnb igdHletsae 1 8 [1, space, Hilbert rigged a subalgebra be some often must this reasons, technical nauiayfsin hti,testate the is, That fashion. unitary a in o-ntr aho:i esrmn fteobservable the of measurement state a the if in fashion: non-unitary a the sw ih xeti lsia rbblt hoy ahr fastate a if rather, theory; classical in ar expect might resulting we the as that is mechanics interpreting h state the hsi h usual the is This of eigenspace hntepoaiiis hsgvsrs otewl-nw hnmnno phenomenon well-known the to rise gives This probabilities. the than |h b ntr function unitary | Φ Ψ codn oteuulrlso unu ehnc,asse norm system a mechanics, quantum of rules usual the to According ealta unu ytmmyb ecie yaHletspace Hilbert a by described be may system quantum a that Recall e od n phrases. and words Key A | 2 ( rbblt amplitude probability a i sgvnby given is hntepoaiiyo nigtesse ntestate the in system the finding of probability the then , | Ψ ncasclrltvsi hsc a ea mretsymmet level. emergent quantum an the be on c may hold that physics possibility struct relativistic the classical cone discuss in causal we Finally, a level. states, o classical causation entangled of superluminal of algebra of the measurements hypothesis of tent an out with topology even a a that of with show out space level classical a the constructing on by disc about come then could We manifold interpretation. time inequali many-worlds Bell’s Rovelli the and including and paradox, paradox mechanics resulting EPR the the to solutions th as some on such emphasis results careful in placing volved theory, quantum in Abstract. 1 i | Ψ + i | Ψ b hntepoaiiyo obtaining of probability the then A i | Ψ ASLT N UNU THEORY QUANTUM AND CAUSALITY ilsteresult the yields orsodn oteeigenvalue the to corresponding U O h | 2 i ebgnwt re umr fise nonee involvin encountered issues of summary brief a with begin We xo fmeasurement of ( Ψ ) ftesl-don prtr on operators self-adjoint the of t | .Hwvr hnasse smaue,tesaecagsin changes state the measured, is system a when However, ). 2 | hti,w r digtepoaiiisapiue rather amplitudes probabilities the adding are we is, that , P | Ψ a t unu hsc,cuaiy esrmn,Hletspace. Hilbert measurement, causality, physics, Quantum i i P ffidn h ytmi h state the in system the finding of | . u a A i i If . | and Ψ 1. | i LK .WINTER K. BLAKE unu theory Quantum a 2 a | i A where , d hntesse hne otestate the to changes system the then , i H i h paddw ttsrsetvl.A respectively. states down and up the , sa ievlefor eigenvalue an is ∈ codn oteuulrlso quantum of rules usual the to According . O 1 smaue,tepsil ucmsare outcomes possible the measured, is | P Ψ( nqatmter.Tedffiut in difficulty The theory. quantum in a i t ) stepoeto prtrot the onto projection the is i a / a sgvnby given is i atcei ecie yatwo- a by described is particle 2 i stersl fameasurement a of result the as h quantity The . H prtr in Operators . uaiya understood as ausality srltoa quantum relational ’s A ywihde not does which ry | supin in- assumptions e n h ytmi in is system the and , Φ r rsso the on arises ure system, quantum s o space- a how uss nocn consis- enforcing A i y ecritique We ty. srals and bservables, U | hnw esr it measure we when hl h ytmis system the while Φ ( 1 oehrwith together 11] , t i ) | ilb ie by given be will Ψ(0) h ie y(using by given | Φ o additive, not e Ψ O | i Ψ lyevolves ally correspond i = quantum f i g o some for a scalled is P H | a Ψ i state 1 | (for Ψ i + i . 2 BLAKE K. WINTER interference, as well as to the well-known difficulty in interpreting the concept of measurement in .

2. EPR, Bell, and causality The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox in quantum theory is a result which shows that ordinary quantum theory, assuming that our universe is a single universe, must either involve hidden variables, or else there must be a mechanism which involves superluminal causation. The original result is found in [7]. Note that the assumption that our universe is a single universe simply means that all observers involved are single observers, and they are the same observers at each point in the history considered, and it does not say anything about whether parallel universes exist or not. This assumption is denied by the many-worlds interpretation, [2], which we will discuss in Sec. 3. Theorem 1. Quantum theory in a single universe without hidden variables requires a superluminal mechanism to enforce consistent measurements, [7]. . Proof. As an example, consider two spin-1/2 particles. The Hilbert space describing their spins will be the tensor product of two copies of the Hilbert space with basis |ui and |di. Thus, the Hilbert space will have a basis consisting of four vectors: |u0i |u1i, |u0i |d1i, |d0i |u1i, |d0i |d1i. Suppose these particles are produced at a certain point in and sent off in opposite directions at close to the , hitting two detectors which are separated by a spacelike interval. Suppose furthermore that their spins, prior to hitting the detectors, are described by the 1 vector ( √2 (|u0i |u1i + |d0i |d1i). Then when results are compared, either both particles are found to have been spin up, or both have been found to be spin down. But this requires either that there be local hidden variables telling the particles which state they should collapse into upon measurement, or else some superluminal mechanism to enforce their correlation.  On the other hand, Bell showed that local hidden variables are incapable of reproducing the results of quantum mechanics. Theorem 2. No local hidden variable theory can reproduce the measured results of quantum mechanics. See [3] for a proof of this theorem, and [5] for an experiment demonstrating that the quantum mechanical results are experimentally verified. Bell’s theorem seems to frequently be cited as proof that hidden variables cannot be local (though non-local hidden variables, or hidden variables with superluminal causal enforcement mechanisms, can reproduce the results of quantum mechanics, e.g. [4]). However, it is often overlooked that the EPR result says that without hidden variables, there must still be some nonlocal enforcement mechanism, pro- vided that our universe remains a single universe through history, and provided that correlations require some real causal mechanism of enforcement.

3. Relational Quantum Mechanics and Many-Worlds Here we will discuss two methods for trying to resolve the above issue. The first, relational quantum mechanics, attempts to do this in a single universe. It thus CAUSALITYANDQUANTUMTHEORY 3 ends up violating the supposition that every correlation has some real mechanism of enforcement underlying it, and appears logically unsound. The second does away with the assumption that our universe is a single universe. We begin with the notion of relational quantum mechanics, which relies on the idea that the split of the physical universe into quantum systems and classical observers is relative or relational and has been suggested by Rovelli, [10]. According to this interpretation, a state vector exists only relative to an observer. Observer A may be a part of observer B’s state vector (and vice verse). There are two problems with this approach. First, it does not define what systems will actually give rise to observers. Therefore, it depends, like the Copenhagen interpretation, on arbitrarily inserting observers into the physical universe. However, it is possible that this problem could be eventually resolved in a satisfactory manner. Second, it does not explain why two observers will agree whenever they compare experimental results. As an example, suppose there are a pair of spin-1/2 particles, a and b, which are entangled so they are both spin up or both spin down. Suppose observer A measures the spin of particle a and observer B measures the spin of particle B. Then according to observer A, measuring particle a causes the state vector to collapse to a state where particle b has exactly one spin, while observer B sees measuring particle b to cause his state vector to collapse particle a to a state with only one spin. When A and B compare their results, A sees B’s measurement as being caused by A’s state vector, while B sees A’s measurement as being caused by the collapse of B’s state vector. Rovelli argues that this is no different than the case of chronological ordering in , in which two observers may disagree about which event precedes another. Therefore, Rovelli is comfortable with the fact that A and B disagree about the cause of correlation between A’s results and B’s results. However, we maintain that the two cases are quite different. In special relativity, chronological order is no longer fixed, but there is still a well-defined causal order between events. Two observers in special relativity will agree about the causes of a chain of events, even though they might disagree on the chronological order. Ac- cording to our understanding of Rovelli’s relational quantum mechanics, however, the question ”what actually causes there to be a correlation between A’s measure- ments and B’s measurements” has no answer. A and B will disagree about the cause. Relational quantum mechanics is therefore incompatible with the philosoph- ical tenet that there is an objective or real cause for the correlation between the measurements of the two observers. The only method that we can see to try to salvage both the relational interpre- tation and the objectivity of causes is to add in a many-worlds type interpretation, [2]. In order to avoid any kind of spacelike causes, we might posit that when ob- server A goes to meet observer B, the act of comparing results causes observer A to branch into a universe with a compatible version of observer B. Note that we cannot say that A was already in that universe from the moment they made the first measurement, without returning to the need to enforce spacelike correlations. If A went into a universe where B already had a compatible measurement, then there is a spacelike correlation being enforced: which universe A goes into at the moment of initial measurement is determined by the measurement of (the many copies of) B at a spacelike interval away. Thus, we should instead hypothesize that 4 BLAKE K. WINTER

A moves into the appropriate universe, with its compatible version of observer B, only when A and B meet to compare their results. One problem with the many-worlds interpretation is quantum erasure. Quantum erasure occurs when a measurement is erased, which also results in the state vector no longer being collapsed. It has been experimentally observed, [12, 14]. However, according to the many-worlds interpretation, the new branch of the universe should only have the collapsed state vector. The fact of quantum erasure suggests that the old state vector must also somehow be available to the new branch of the universe, in case such an erasure happens. Alternately, one might argue that real observations can never be erased, and that in the experiments done (such as in [12, 14]) there was no actual observation that was erased. This would necessitate the hypothesis that we might experimen- tally differentiate between real observations and mere entanglements between an experiment and the observational apparatus. As such, this would make predictions that are empirically different from those of traditional quantum mechanics. It should be noted, of course, that the issue of quantum erasure is not a problem only for the many-worlds interpretation, but for any interpretation of quantum mechanics.

4. Relativistic invariance on the classical level as an emergent property 4.1. Spacetime from quantum theory. The problem of quantizing general rel- ativity is one which has had a rocky history, due to numerous technical problems. For some discussion of the attempts made so far, we refer the reader to [11]. Here we will merely note how a spacetime with a Lorentzian structure of causal cones could come about from a quantum theory. Ordinarily, of course, a quantum theory is constructed on a spacetime manifold. However, we will here show how a quantum theory naturally gives rise to a space with a topology, and why this will, on the classical level, have causal cones built into the Poisson bracket structure. Let us assume that we have some quantum theory with a (rigged) Hilbert space V and an algebra of observables O, in the . Let C be a the sub-algebra of O which is physically interpreted as the Heisenberg-picture operators measuring field strengths, that is, ”position” operators (as opposed to, for example, momentum operators). We will create a topological spacetime from this in the following manner. Let M be a set whose elements consist of minimal non-empty intersections of complete sets of commuting observables in C (these complete sets of commuting observables are essentially Cauchy data). Note that this associates elements of C with elements of M: each element of C will belong to a set which is an element of M. The elements of M will form the points of the spacetime. To topologize M, we note that a complete set of commuting observables should define a (spacelike) hypersurface. Also, given a point x ∈ M, the set of points y ∈ M such that the elements of C associated with y commute with the elements of C associated with x should form an open set. Finally, each point should be a closed set. We may give M the coarsest topology induced by these requirements. Remark 3. If we apply this technique to non-relativistic quantum theories, we end up with M being one-dimensional, and spacelike hypersurfaces consist of single points. CAUSALITYANDQUANTUMTHEORY 5

In other words, if the intersection of any two distinct complete sets of commuting observables in C is empty, then the result would be a one-dimensional topology. This suggests that even if there were a causal foliation of spacetime, nonetheless as long as space is not 0-dimensional, there would still be a Lorentzian-type of structure on the commutation relations of operators at various points. That is, an operator in C associated with a given point x will commute with operators on many different ”spacelike” hypersurfaces in M. The points with which it does not commute would form an analog of a . This would lead to a light cone type of structure on the classical level, where the commutators become Poisson brackets. Since measurements cannot themselves transmit classical information, it is not surprising that this would mean that on the classical level, the transmission of information would be restricted to these cones (barring some discovery of how to exploit the finer causal ordering of M to send information faster).

Remark 4. This cone structure may have odd consequences in , since such a structure of causal cones will generally determine a metric up to a conformal factor, [9]. It is not clear how this may affect such theories; more work on this might yield interesting results.

4.2. Emergent symmetries. It should be noted that a non-local enforcement mechanism need not involve an actual foliation of spacetime by spacelike slices to define a causal order. Indeed, one could try to posit that the enforcement mechanism were still in some sense relativistically invariant, as is done with the transactional interpretation of Cramer, [6]. However, there would still be some causal ordering beyond that given by the non-vanishing Poisson brackets of classical variables, for the following reason: Suppose that, in the EPR setup, instead of simply having two particles, we used three, all entangled so they must all be found to be spin up or all be found to be spin down. Now suppose the third particle is sent in the same direction as the second particle, but slightly slower, so that it is measured at a point which is in the timelike future of the measurement of the second particle, but still spacelike separated from the measurement of the first particle. The measurement of the sec- ond particle causally precedes the measurement of the third particle, but involves a causal enforcement on the first particle’s measurement. Therefore, the first par- ticle’s measurement appears to have to causally precede the measurement of the third particle, even though these are spacelike related events. This may not fully give a causal-ordering foliation of the entire spacetime manifold, but it does give rise to an ordering of some discrete subset of measurements, which is stronger than the classical causal ordering of those events.

Theorem 5. A superluminal enforcement mechanism for keeping measurements consistent, which behaves as indicated above, will result in a stronger causal ordering of measurements than would be expected classically.

Note: by stronger, we mean here that two events which take place at points in spacetime which are not ordered by the classical partial ordering, will be ordered by this quantum causal ordering. Thus, the quantum causal ordering is a partial order relation which contains the classical partial ordering as a subset. We cannot, however, rule out the possibility that one might do away with some of the assumptions above about how such a superluminal enforcement mechanism 6 BLAKE K. WINTER would behave, which might avoid this result. However, the assumptions made above seem reasonable. However, we argue that this result is not necessarily surprising or problematic. Indeed, there are many instances where a symmetry on one scale is broken at a smaller scale, or where a classical symmetry is broken on the quantum scale. For an example of the former, which does not even involve quantum physics, consider a physical model of billiard balls. Such a physical model can be made assuming that each ball is a perfect sphere, with the inherent rotational symmetry which that entails. However, on a microscopic level, the balls exhibit some degree of unevenness. This unevenness breaks the symmetry, but it is irrelevant at the scales involved in the model. When it comes to quantum mechanics, it is not uncommon to find anomalies. These are symmetries on the classical level which do not apply on the quantum level. For example, the chiral anomaly appears in certain theories of fermions with chiral symmetry on the classical level: this symmetry may be broken on the quantum level. See [13] for a discussion of this phenomenon. Perhaps the most obvious example of a broken symmetry is the commutativity of position and momentum, which exists on the classical level, but not on the quantum level. Therefore, it does not appear to us to pose a problem to hypothesize that there are superluminal causal enforcement mechanisms involved in measurements involv- ing , which do not necessarily obey classical relativistic sym- metries. In particular, these violations of classical symmetries would only appear on the level of measurements, rather than on the level of the unitary evolution of the system. Therefore they would be expected to vanish classically, since in the classical limit, measurements become moot due to the deterministic nature of the classical limit. As seen in Sec. 4.1, a relativistic style of causal cones is a natural consequence of a the commutator relations of a quantum field theory. Therefore: even if we posit superluminal causal correlations for measurements, on the classi- cal level we might expect to see Poisson brackets which correspond to a system of causal cones. Since measurements of entangled states cannot themselves be used to transfer information, this naturally results in classical information being restricted to transmission within said cones. On the other hand, it is important to emphasize that the results of EPR logically require local hidden variables, a branching multiverse, or a superluminal mechanism to enforce consistency. Bell’s result shows that the first of these options is empiri- cally false, which logically leaves the latter two options. This is a fact which should not be overlooked, paradoxical as it may seem.

References [1] J.P. Antoine, Quantum Mechanics Beyond Hilbert Space, appearing in Irreversibility and Causality, Semigroups and Rigged Hilbert Spaces, Arno Bohm, Heinz-Dietrich Doebner, Piotr Kielanowski, eds., Springer-Verlag, ISBN 3-540-64305-2, (1996) [2] J. Barrett and P. Byrne, eds., The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Collected Works 19551980 with Commentary, Princeton University Press, (2012) [3] J.S. Bell, On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox, Physics Vol. 1, No. 3, 195-200, (1964) [4] D. Bohm, A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of ’hidden variables’ I, 85: 166179, (1952) [5] J.F. Clauser, A. Shimony, Bell’s theorem: experimental tests and implications, Reports on Progress in Physics. 41: 18811927, (1978) CAUSALITYANDQUANTUMTHEORY 7

[6] J. Cramer, The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics, Reviews of Modern Physics 58, 647688, July (1986) [7] A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, Can quantum-mechanical description of physical be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47 777, (1935) [8] R. de la Madrid, The role of the rigged Hilbert space in Quantum Mechanics, Eur. J. Phys. 26, 287, (2005) arXiv:quant-ph/0502053 [9] M. Rainer, Cones and causal structures on topological and differentiable manifolds, Journal of Mathematical Physics 40(12), 6589-6597, (1999) [10] C. Rovelli: Relational quantum mechanics, International Journal of , 35, 1637, (1996) arXiv:quant-ph/9609002 [11] T. Thiemann, Modern canonical quantum (Cambridge monographs on mathematical physics), Cambridge University Press, (2008) [12] S.P. Walborn et al., Double-slit quantum eraser, Phys. Rev. A 65 (3): 033818, 2002, arXiv:quant-ph/0106078 [13] S. Weinberg, The Quantum Theory of Fields. Volume II: Modern Applications. Cambridge University Press, (2001) [14] K. Yoon-Ho, R. Yu, S.P. Kulik, Y.H. Shih, and Marlan Scully, A delayed choice quantum eraser, Physical Review Letters 84: 15, (2000), arXiv:quant-ph/9903047

Oakland University, [email protected]