Public Discussion in the Deliberative System: Does It Make Better Citizens?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Public Discussion in the Deliberative System: Does It Make Better Citizens? B.J.Pol.S. 37, 587–618 Copyright © 2007 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/S0007123407000336 Printed in the United Kingdom Public Discussion in the Deliberative System: Does It Make Better Citizens? DONALD D. SEARING, FREDERICK SOLT, PAMELA JOHNSTON CONOVER AND IVOR CREWE* In democratic theory, the practice of discussing public affairs has been associated with desirable consequences for citizenship and democracy. We use Anglo-American survey data to examine twelve hypotheses about psychological foundations for four general conditions that such discussions might promote: autonomous citizens, political legitimacy, good representation and democratic communities. Our data combine detailed measures of public discussion with measures of more of its hypothesized civic consequences than have heretofore been available. They also enable us to probe, using specialized samples, causal inferences suggested by our analyses of random samples in our British and American communities. Six of the hypotheses are supported, including at least one regarding each of the four general liberal democratic conditions we investigate. From Aristotle and John Stuart Mill to contemporary democratic theory, the practice of discussing public affairs has been associated with desirable consequences for citizenship and democracy.1 We use Anglo-American survey data to examine four sets of hypotheses about psychological foundations for the liberal democratic conditions that such discussions have been said to promote: autonomous citizens, political legitimacy, good representation and democratic communities. The first set of hypotheses suggests that discussing public affairs helps to educate autonomous citizens by inculcating independence and internal efficacy.2 In particular, the * Searing and Conover, Department of Political Science, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill; Solt, Department of Political Science, University of Southern Illinois at Carbondale; Crewe, University of Essex. The authors are grateful to The Spencer Foundation for financial support. For valuable comments on this article, they are indebted to Albert Weale and reviewers for the Journal, to the Politics Study Group of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, and to the Conference on Empirical Approaches to Deliberative Politics, European University Institute, Florence. 1 Aristotle, The Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (New York: Harper, 1862), and On Liberty (New York: Bobbs Merrill, 1956); John Dewey, The Public and Its Problems (New York: Holt, 1927); Harold Lasswell, Democracy Through Public Opinion (New York: Bantam, 1941); Dennis F. Thompson, The Democratic Citizen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970); Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984); Ju¨rgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, 2 vols. (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1987); Jane Mansbridge, ‘Everyday Talk in the Deliberative System’, in Stephen Macedo, ed., Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 211–42; James S. Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1991); John Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000); Stephen Macedo, ‘Introduction’, in Macedo, ed, Deliberative Politics, pp. 3–16; Albert Weale, ‘Party Competition and Deliberative Democracy’, in Judith Bara and Albert Weale, eds, Party Competition and Political Democracy: Essays in Honour of Ian Budge (London: Routledge, 2006), pp. 271–86; Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996); Thomas A. Spragens, Reason and Democracy (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1990). 2 Mill, On Liberty; David Held, Models of Democracy (Oxford: Polity Press, 1987); Joshua Cohen, ‘Democracy and Liberty’, in Jon Elster, ed., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 185–231. 588 SEARING, SOLT, CONOVER AND CREWE more that citizens encounter different points of view, face to face, the more they are likely to examine their own views and thereby develop the autonomy needed for effective liberal citizenship. The next set of hypotheses suggests that discussing public affairs builds political legitimacy for democratic institutions by drawing citizens towards consensus on fundamental values and rules of the game. At the end of the day, even those who still disagree with public policies may nevertheless accept them because of their satisfaction with having been involved in discussions about these matters.3 The third set of hypotheses turns to electoral contexts to link political talk with good representation. It suggests that such discussions improve the knowledge and skills that citizens need to evaluate candidates and issues intelligently, and that the experience of discussing public affairs strengthens their desire to participate in electoral activity.4 Finally, the strongest claims focus on the democratic community to argue that deliberation should be regarded as a fundamental act of citizenship,5 because it fosters the mutual understanding, tolerance and public spiritedness that citizens require to live and work together successfully. Our data provide an exceptional opportunity to survey this extensive terrain and to investigate specific claims found here, because they combine theoretically oriented and detailed measures of discussion with measures of more of its hypothesized civic consequences than have heretofore been available. They also enable us to probe, using specialized samples, causal inferences suggested by our analyses of random samples in our British and American communities. THEORY Much of the recent empirical interest in political talk has been stimulated by the ‘deliberative turn’ in democratic theory, which, during the 1990s, drew attention to contexts for discussing public affairs and to deliberative activities that occur or might occur within them. Mansbridge and Habermas suggest we think about all these practices as a ‘deliberative system’ that educates, constructs, filters, adopts, applies and discards political ideas. At its core is political talk within institutions like national courts, parliaments and civil service departments.6 Around this core and linked with it is the political talk between constituents and government officials and within political parties, interest groups and the 3 Joshua Cohen, ‘Deliberation and Political Legitimacy’, in James Bohman and William Rehg, eds, Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997); Cohen, ‘Democracy and Liberty’; Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation; Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1980); Bruce Ackerman ‘Why Dialogue?’ Journal of Philosophy, 86 (1989), 5–22; Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action; Seyla Benhabib, ‘Models of Public Space: Hannah Arendt, the Liberal Tradition and Jurgen Habermas’, in Craig Calhoun, ed., Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992). 4 William Galston, ‘Liberal Virtues’, American Political Science Review, 82 (1988), 1277–90; Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement; Barry Holden, Understanding Liberal Democracy (Hemel Hempsted, Herts.: Philip Allen, 1988); Robert A. Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1985). 5 Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958); Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age; Spragens, Reason and Democracy. 6 Mansbridge, ‘Everyday Talk in the Deliberative System’; Ju¨rgen Habermas, ‘Concluding Comments on Empirical Approaches to Deliberative Politics’, Acta Politica, 40 (2005), 385–92; Ju¨rgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1989). Public Discussion in the Deliberative System 589 media. The model’s third ring consists of political talk that occurs among activists, attentive publics and general publics. To situate the theoretical significance of our investigation in this third ring, several further distinctions are needed. Mansbridge’s and Habermas’s visions span a communica- tive spectrum from ‘structured deliberation’ to ‘public discussion’ to ‘casual political talk’. All three forms of political talk are found in each of the three systemic contexts. But some forms are more common in some contexts than in others. Structured deliberation involves listening carefully to the views of others, explaining one’s own views to them and taking time together to think over a matter thoroughly. This exercise finds its most systematic expression in ideal deliberative models constructed by political theorists for purposes of normative inquiry. Structured deliberation is, however, sometimes approximated in core deliberative institutions like parliaments and civil service departments.7 It has also been approximated in research settings where democratic deliberations are artificially or experimentally constructed for ordinary citizens.8 Public discussion, by contrast, refers to extended conversations about political issues, which are less structured by rules, participants or moderators, but which are importantly conducted in ‘public’ settings where participants are likely to encounter a range of different perspectives. This mode of political talk is commonly found in elite
Recommended publications
  • The Power of Ideas and the Perception of Political
    The Power of Ideas and the Perception of Political Karl-Heinz Breier (University of Vechta, Germany) “The own horizon is narrowed without the knowledge and practise in the studies of the great political thinkers. In order to perceive the actual situation of the world as something new, the traditional amplitude of political thinking is necessary.”1 As we assemble here in Bloomington to compare different kinds of government, we know that Karl Jaspers who is born in Oldenburg, the city I am living now, stresses an important and very significant issue. Jaspers speaks of the “amplitude of passed Political Thought” and anyone who is dealing with his political thinking knows that the amplitude of Political Thought characterizes his work. It is absolutely clear for Jaspers – and Eric Voegelin verbalized that in the New Science of Politics to the point – that “the contraction of political science to a description of existing institutions”2 must be avoided. Both, Jaspers as well as Voegelin, recognize the strong connection between political phenomena and their interpretation on the basis of political theory. The objects of our Political Science, according to that, not only are the incidents of actual politics; they also include patterns of understanding that allow us to gain access to the diversity of all political phenomena. Jaspers gets to the heart of this in “The Idea of the University”: “After examinations, one quickly forgets. The decisive factor after this is not the body of fact learned, but one’s judgement. What matters then is not factual knowledge by itself but the ability and initiative to go out and get the facts on one’s own, to think about them effectively, to know what questions to ask.”3 That is to say: Whoever wants to understand politics, according to Jaspers, must realize that the world of phenomena consists of a categorical order.
    [Show full text]
  • Citizenship Denationalized (The State of Citizenship Symposium)
    Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies Volume 7 Issue 2 Article 2 Spring 2000 Citizenship Denationalized (The State of Citizenship Symposium) Linda Bosniak Rutgers Law School-Camden Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ijgls Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Bosniak, Linda (2000) "Citizenship Denationalized (The State of Citizenship Symposium)," Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies: Vol. 7 : Iss. 2 , Article 2. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ijgls/vol7/iss2/2 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Citizenship Denationalized LINDA BOSNIAK° INTRODUCTION When Martha Nussbaum declared herself a "citizen of the world" in a recent essay, the response by two dozen prominent intellectuals was overwhelmingly critical.' Nussbaum's respondents had a variety of complaints, but central among them was the charge that the very notion of world citizenship is incoherent. For citizenship requires a formal governing polity, her critics asserted, and clearly no such institution exists at the world level. Short of the establishment of interplanetary relations, a world government is unlikely to take form anytime soon. A good thing too, they added, since such a regime would surely be a tyrannical nightmare.2 * Professor of Law, Rutgers Law School-Camden; B.A., Wesleyan University; M.A., University of California, Berkeley; J.D., Stanford University.
    [Show full text]
  • Jihad Vs. Mcworld: How Globalism and Tribalism Are Reshaping the World by Benjamin R
    Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies Volume 20 Article 7 12-1-2002 Jihad vs. McWorld: How Globalism and Tribalism are Reshaping the World by Benjamin R. Barber Fred Donaldson Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/sigma Recommended Citation Donaldson, Fred (2002) "Jihad vs. McWorld: How Globalism and Tribalism are Reshaping the World by Benjamin R. Barber," Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies: Vol. 20 , Article 7. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/sigma/vol20/iss1/7 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sigma: Journal of Political and International Studies by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW: JIHAD VS. MCWORLD AND DEMOCRACY FRED DONALDSON JIHAD VS. Me WORLD: How GLOBALISM AND TRIBALISM ARE RESHAPING THE WORLD. Benjamin R. Barber, New York: Ballantine Books, 1996. 389pp. The cover of the book Jihad vs. Me World, Illinois (25). Through the process of economic by Benjamin Barber, shows a veiled Muslim globalization, "American" cars can be built in woman holding a can of Pepsi. This photograph Japan, while "Japanese" cars are built in Amer­ illustrates the stark contrast between two simul­ ica. Anecdotal statistics, cited by Barber, bolster taneous and very active global forces: Jihad, or his evidence regarding the occurrence of tribalism, and McWorld, or economic globaliza­ McWorld. McDonald's restaurants serve 20 mil­ tion. Barber successfully shows the occurrence lion customers around the world every day, of McWorld and Jihad through the use of which is more than the people in Greece, ire­ examples, statistics, and observations.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism and the Common Good a Hayekian Perspective on Communitarianism
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 Liberalism and the Common Good A Hayekian Perspective on Communitarianism —————— ✦ —————— LINDA C. RAEDER In the end, given liberty to learn, men will find out that freedom means community. —William Aylott Orton n recent years, a spirited
    [Show full text]
  • Comment: Volunteering and Community Service
    SMITH_FMT.DOC 06/22/00 9:28 AM VOLUNTEERING AND COMMUNITY SERVICE STEVEN RATHGEB SMITH* I INTRODUCTION Today, the subject of volunteering and community service is at the heart of contemporary debate among scholars, policymakers, and practitioners on the future of American social policy. This debate is framed, in part, by the language of decline and presents voluntarism as a remedy. For example, many scholars suggest that the capacity of local communities to solve their own problems has been undermined by the growth of the federal government and the professionalization of public services.1 To reverse this slide, many scholars and policymakers are calling for an increased reliance on community volunteers and largely volunteer, religious organizations to provide service. More voluntarism, in short, will help American society. Robert Putnam argues persuasively for more voluntarism for another reason.2 He observes that participation in voluntary groups and associations such as the Kiwanis Club, the Girl Scouts, and bowling leagues has fallen significantly in the post-war era. In his view, voluntary organizations with a high degree of interpersonal contact are critical to building a vibrant civil society. Thus, more voluntarism, especially in organizations where a person can build a long-term relationship with others in the community, should be very beneficial for society as a whole. Voluntarism can create social capital—that is, social networks of trust and cooperation—that can then promote greater political involvement and citizen participation in public affairs. The civic infrastructure, broadly defined, will be stronger. Other scholars supportive of voluntarism worry about threats to individual liberties and freedoms associated with the growth of the state.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of "Liberal Republicanism": Why Group-Based Remedies and Republican Citizenship Don't Mix Cynthia V
    College of William & Mary Law School William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Faculty and Deans 1991 The Limits of "Liberal Republicanism": Why Group-Based Remedies and Republican Citizenship Don't Mix Cynthia V. Ward William & Mary Law School, [email protected] Repository Citation Ward, Cynthia V., "The Limits of "Liberal Republicanism": Why Group-Based Remedies and Republican Citizenship Don't Mix" (1991). Faculty Publications. 273. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/273 Copyright c 1991 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs COMMENTARY THE LIMITS OF "LIBERAL REPUBLICANISM": WHY GROUP-BASED REMEDIES AND REPUBLICAN CITIZENSHIP DON'T MIX Cynthia V. Ward* After decades of remarkable consensus on the need for state inter­ vention to remedy the wrongs committed against disadvantaged groups in America, the civil rights coalition has reached a fork in the road. The liberal effort to redeem constitutional promises of equality to women and minorities has focused on gaining access for those groups to the bargaining table of interest-group politics, allowing them the chance to press their claims and exert their influence on legislators and adminis­ trators.1 Today, legal and political scholars survey our political land­ scape and proclaim both achievement-the recognition of each citizen's equality under the law2-and defeat-the failure to erase race- and gen­ der-based inequalities throughout society.3 While the "discrete and in- * Yale Law School. I owe many thanks to Bruce Ackerman, for whose class this essay was originally written and whose criticism and advice have been invaluable.
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Democracy in Crisis: Promise Or Peril? Edited by Trevor Norris
    Philosophical Inquiry in Education, Volume 24 (2016), No. 1, pp. 110–114 Review of Strong Democracy in Crisis: Promise or Peril? Edited by Trevor Norris. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2016 SAMANTHA DEANE Loyola University Chicago An Ode to Benjamin Barber and Strong Democracy Trevor Norris’s edited volume Strong Democracy in Crisis: Promise or Peril? is a collection of critical essays that extends Benjamin Barber’s work on strong democracy into the complex terrain of contemporary democratic theory. Barber is best known for his 1984 book Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age, but this is not to say his scholarship ends here; Barber has devoted his life to prefacing, re-framing, and re-imagining what it might mean to generate democratic communities. Serving a dual purpose, this text is also a Festschrift of sorts: each essay honors Barber’s friendship by taking up his characteristic hope that the future will be paved with more decency and democracy. Collectively, the twelve essays in Strong Democracy in Crisis marshal three sets of concerns regarding the realization of strong democracy: 1) the very possibility of practicing strong democracy; 2) the influence of Barber’s Rousseauian outlook on the desirability of Barber’s political vision; and 3) the plausibility of enacting strong democracy in the increasingly commercial and globalized world. The text also features three disciplinary interludes that collectively problematize the practice of making political theory. After summarizing the key points of each chapter, I will highlight a few gaps in the volume’s presentation of democratic crises. In calling attention to these gaps, my intent is to point toward openings for continued scholarship on the possibility and plausibility of strong democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of a Communitarian Morality
    The Idea of a Communitarian Morality Philip Selznickt During the past few years, and especially since the publication of Alasdair MacIntyre's After Virtue in 1981, we have seen a renewed attack on the premises of liberalism.' There is nothing new about such criticism. A long list of writers-Hegel, Marx, Dewey, and many others, including several Popes-have recoiled in various ways from what seemed to be an impoverished morality and an inadequate understanding of human society. The contemporary criticism has raised some new issues and has been sparked, in no small degree, by a spate of impressive writing in legal, moral, and social philosophy-writing that has reaf- firmed the liberal faith in moral autonomy and in the imperatives of rationality. I refer, of course, to the work of John Rawls, Robert Nozick, and Ronald Dworkin. The new critics are called communitarian, an echo of similar views expressed in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries by English liberals like John A. Hobson and L.T. Hobhouse, and American pragmatists, especially John Dewey. Yet the communitarian idea is vague; in contemporary writing it is more often alluded to and hinted at than explicated. Furthermore, there are communitarians on both left and right. The quest for a communitarian morality is a meeting ground for conservatives, socialists, anarchists, and more ambiguously, welfare liber- als. Serious issues of social policy are at stake. It seems important, there- fore, to explore what a communitarian morality may entail. For if we shoot these arrows of the spirit we should know, as best we can, where they will light.
    [Show full text]
  • Dædalus Coming up in Dædalus: Dædalus on Life Anthony Kenny, Thomas Laqueur, Shai Lavi, Lorraine Daston, Paul Rabinow, Robert P
    Dædalus coming up in Dædalus: Dædalus on life Anthony Kenny, Thomas Laqueur, Shai Lavi, Lorraine Daston, Paul Rabinow, Robert P. George, Robert J. Richards, Nikolas Rose, John Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences Broome, Jeff McMahan, and Adrian Woolfson Fall 2007 on nature Leo Marx, William Cronon, Cass Sunstein, Daniel Kevles, Bill McKibben, Harriet Ritvo, Gordon Orians, Camille Parmesan, Margaret Schabas, and Philip Tetlock & Michael Oppenheimer 2007: on the public interest Fall on the E. J. Dionne Jr. Why the public interest matters now 5 on cosmopolitanism Martha C. Nussbaum, Margaret C. Jacob, A. A. Long, Pheng Cheah, public interest William A. Galston An old debate renewed 10 Darrin McMahon, Helena Rosenblatt, Samuel Scheffler, Arjun Adam Wolfson From James Madison to Abraham Lincoln 20 Appadurai, Rogers Smith, Peter Brooks, and Craig Calhoun Nathan Glazer Reflections on an elusive goal 30 plus poetry by Ted Richer, C. D. Wright &c.; ½ction by Chris Abani, Jagdish Bhagwati Some implications for economic policy 37 Wesley Brown, Alix Ohlin &c.; and notes by Phyllis Coley, Don Gary Hart The commonwealth ideal 45 Harrán, Richard Kraut, Ian Ayres &c. Christine Todd Whitman Governing in the public interest: then & now 51 Robert N. Bellah Ethical politics: reality or illusion? 59 Amy Gutmann The dangers of extremist rhetoric 70 Lance Taylor Economists & the wealth of nations 79 poetry Molly McQuade Spring’s So Sad, We Want to Know Why 88 ½ction Mary Gordon Dilly 89 dialogue Cornel West & D. Graham Burnett On Melville’s The Con½dence-Man 101 notes Omer Bartov on Eastern Galicia’s past & present 115 Harriet Ritvo on the animal turn 118 U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • WWS 325/AMS 350 -- Civil Society in the United States and Other Places
    WWS 325/AMS 350 -- Civil Society and Public Policy Spring, 2004 Syllabus Prof. Stanley N. Katz 428 Robertson Hall Ph: 258-5637 [email protected] Wednesdays, 1:30-4:20 p.m. Robertson Hall This is a course designed to introduce undergraduate students to the remarkable resurgence of attention to the associational and voluntary sector which Alexis de Tocqueville identified a century and a half ago as the distinctive characteristic of American society. For the past twenty years or so, increasing interest in this sector has been displayed by politicians and scholars, and the sector has come to be praised on all sides. Alas, it has not been understood as much as it has been admired. Furthermore, the end of the Cold War and the collapse of most socialist states has led to international enthusiasm for the building of civil society by means of voluntary non-profit activity, in the belief that strong civil societies would promote democracy. The real question is which comes first, civil society or democracy. We will begin by closely examining the concepts of civil society and social capital – civil society as it has been redefined since the end of the Cold War, and social capital as it have been developed by Robert Putnam and other social scientists. We will then focus on the network of institutions called the Third (or not-for-profit) Sector, in order to see how Americans organize themselves in the space between the state and the market. Finally, we will contrast American behavior with that in other societies, notably of the formerly socialist nations.
    [Show full text]
  • Hasidic Public Schools in Kiryas Joel
    The Draw and Drawbacks of Religious Enclaves in a Constitutional Democracy: Hasidic Public Schools in Kiryas Joel JUDITH LYNN FAILER' INTRODUCTION Recent work in political and constitutional studies has celebrated the salutary effects of robust civil societies for democracies.' Robert Putnam, for example, has described how Italian communities with stronger civic traditions have political leaders who are less "elitist" and are "more enthusiastic supporters of political equality" while their citizens' political involvement is characterized by "greater social trust and greater confidence in the law-abidingness of their fellow citizens than... citizens in the least civic regions."' William Galston makes a case for how civic organizations in civil society can foster the development of liberal virtues Jean L. Cohen and Andrew Arato have argued that civil society is "the primary locus for the potential expansion of democracy under 'really existing' liberal-democratic regimes." 4 * Assistant Professor of Political Science and American Studies, Indiana University-Bloomington. Prepared for presentation at a symposium on Civil Society, Indiana University School of Law, March 29, 1996. Thank you to Fred Aman and Steve Conrad for their generous invitation. I am grateful to Jane Mansbridge for helping me think through the ways by which Kiryas Joel poses particular challenges in democratic theory as an enclave group. Thank you also to Mark Brandon, Dana Chabot, David Orentlicher, and Jean Robinson for helpful conversations in preparation of this article, and to Jeffrey Isaac and Sanford Levinson for their suggestions for revisions. 1. For the purposes of this paper, Iam following John Gray's definition of "civil society" as "that sphere of autonomous institutions, protected by a rule of law, within which individuals and communities possessing divergent values and beliefs may coexist in peace." JOHN GRAY, POST LIBERALISM: STUDIES IN POLITICAL THOUGHT 157 (1993).
    [Show full text]
  • Benjamin R. Barber, Fear's Empire
    Terence D. J. Banks Review Essay The White House’s Burden: Benjamin R. Barber, Fear’s Empire by Terence D. J. Banks ear’s Empire is one of several scholarly responses to the portentous Fhistorical moment of 9/11 and its political aftermath. In this insightful book the distinguished academic and political commentator Benjamin Barber presents an impassive analysis of the unapologetically truculent turn in American national security policy. Besides seeking to show why the current objectives of the current White House administration are ultimately unsustainable, Barber also outlines a long term strategy for the maintenance of global security and, by extension, American power and influence: In place of the current policy of “preventive war” (the prerogative of Pax Americana), Barber proffers “preventive democracy” (the imperative of Lex Humana). Tariq Ali in his Clash of Fundamentalisms has recently observed the way that many liberal American commentators, caught up in the current maelstrom of superpatriotism, are anxious not to appear out of step with the prevailing mood for fear of not being heard. In these doleful days, the Chomskys, Sontags and Vidals are sadly few and far between. Benjamin Barber’s Fear’s Empire also bears the marks of having negotiated this self-imposed censorship. By stating that his express purpose is to show how America’s national interest may be best served, and by not ruling out the use of pre- emptive strikes in the war against terrorism (but always as a last resort, and not against a sovereign state), Barber earns enough points to allow him to deliver a crushing ideological critique of the contemporary American right in what amounts to a defense of Enlightenment values against neoconservative romantic idealism.
    [Show full text]