A VERY GOOD CRITICAL REVIEW ESSAY Original Word Count

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A VERY GOOD CRITICAL REVIEW ESSAY Original Word Count Tompkins 1 A VERY GOOD CRITICAL REVIEW ESSAY Original Word Count: 1,800 -- but shortened here by DB, using ellipses (“[. ]”) A Historical Perspective on Sophocles’ Antigone Sophocles’ tragic drama Antigone was written around 420 B.C.E. but is as relevant today was it would have been to the original Athenian audience. The story of the archetypal rebel who stares down the tyranny of the state is timeless. Antigone is a girl who as the play begins has two paths she can follow. She can get married to the son of the King, have children, and live happily ever after. Or she can ignore the specific dictates of the King, bury the rotting corpse of her brother and ultimately be put to death for it. It is easy to see how the specific actions of Antigone are still relevant. Despite the relevancy of battle against tyranny, there are certain elements that may be lost on a contemporary audience. My question is: it is important, in trying to get a true sense of the tragedy of the play, to have a better understanding of what Sophocles was trying to articulate to his original audience? I will be taking a look at two secondary sources which should give different perspective of the historical context of the play and help answer the question of what Sophocles was trying to articulate to his original audience. First I will look the “The Wrath of Creon: Withholding Burial in Homer and Sophocles” by H. A. Shapiro. The second text I will examine is “Replaying Antigone: Changing Patterns of Public and Private Commemoration at Athens c. 440–350” by Sarah Brown Ferrario. Upon assessing each source, I will re-evaluate my research question in light of the information covered. Tompkins 2 H. A. Shapiro’s essay “The Wrath of Creon: Withholding Burial in Homer and Sophocles” compares the behavior of Homer’s Achilles and Sophocles’ Creon in relation to the withholding of burial. In both cases, Shapiro contends that each character is guilty of undertaking actions that are “overstepping the bounds of appropriate behavior for mortals” (Shapiro 120). He deals specifically with the decision to give burial in one case and withhold it in another. Shapiro looks at the historical record of black-figure vases to discuss the way these actions were perceived in ancient Athens. It is easy to make the connections that Shapiro wishes to make since his argument is laid out in an organized and logical manner. He specifically analyzes the decision of Creon to withhold burial by illustrating the similarity to the treatment of Hector’s body by Achilles in the Iliad. He attempts to answer the question of whether Sophocles’ original audience would have indeed been aware of the Homeric implications (121). In relation to this linkage, he explains: “I believe there is also some visual evidence to support this parallel and to suggest that the issue of burial and its refusal was one of which the Athenians was keenly aware” (122). The visual evidence is the black-figure vase paintings. There are fifteen version of the portrayal of the treatment of Hector’s body still in existence. The visual presentation of this evidence is important in helping establish the link Shapiro wishes to make. To further the connection between the two stories and Sophocles original audience, Shapiro introduces Aeschylus’ Seven against Thebes, in which the story of Eteocles and Polyneices is first introduced, giving context to the original story. Shapiro gives adequacy to his argument by augmenting his argument with the background of the original story. He asserts that in Aeschylus’ depiction, the withholding of burial was not a major theme. He goes on to state that the theme of withholding burial was added by Sophocles (126). Shapiro slowly works his Tompkins 3 way through the layers of context to get to his major assertion: Antigone was not a political statement. The crux of his argument hinges on the fact that the issue is a specifically Theban problem. Shapiro, in making his argument, notes that “[t]he issue of Polyneices’ burial is entirely internal to Thebes: his is a hero who fell attacking his own city in a power struggle with his brother and now lies unburied on Theban soil. No power outside Thebes is involved in any way” (127-8). Given the manner in which the argument is laid out and the quality of the background information, it not hard for a reader to accept the thesis of the author. Despite the fact that Shapiro makes his argument in a concise, logical manner, it is hard question if the original audience would have made the same connections. It is possible to look at the documentation that he provides and identify that scope of the evidence. This does not translate back to the original audience. It would be speculative and require something of a leap of faith to assume that the Athenian audience of Sophocles would have connected the same dots. Yet, that is not to say that he does not make an objective argument. The documentation is well presented, the sources support his argument well, and it is just hard to make the necessary leap. Where he may have provided more detail was the distinction that he makes between the religious and the political aspects. He makes his argument that the implication of the Creon’s actions are not political (or would not have been perceived as political), yet he does not follow up with a detail explanation of his argument. Sarah Brown Ferrario contends in her essay “Replaying Antigone: Changing Patterns of Public and Private Commemoration at Athens C. 440-350” that changing attitudes due to cultural changes in Greece precipitated a change in the perception of the Antigone. Ferrario frames this argument by looking at Demosthenes’ statement that Creon had given good advice. Tompkins 4 Ferrario makes a detailed argument about the changing attitudes in Athens from the time of Sophocles (specifically during the reign of Pericles) and the orator/statesman Demosthenes (after the Peloponnesian War). She does this by looking at the “commemorative practices” of these two distinct periods. The way in which the information is laid out leaves no question about the sufficiency in terms of the argument. [A BIT MORE EVIDENCE AS TO “WHY” WOULD BE HELPFUL HERE.] There is a vast amount of data relating to the specific aspects of the funerary monuments and means of commemoration. The overriding question may become is there too much information, does the initial thesis warrant the depth of detail provided to paint a clear picture of the changing attitudes? By contrast, the basic premise of the argument is predicated upon the words of Demosthenes, [. ] The documentation of the changes in funerary practices suggests documentary accuracy. In making the case that funerary practices changed, the author devotes significant energy providing explicit detail of the shift from the era before the Peloponnesian War until the era following it. [ . ]The full scope of the discussion of the commemoration that Ferrario discusses is too broad to mention here, but the scholarly fashion is which the information is documented firmly establishes the objectivity of the author. The full extent of the argument is rooted in the question of what changed in the perception from the time the drama was first produced [ . .] . To this end, Ferrario undertakes a detailed excavation of the landscape of commemoration, showing how the change in funerary methods invariably reflects the cultural changes that would have given birth to Demosthenes’ statement. The methodical way in which the author looks at the data and then documents it, provides a credible foundation upon which to make an argument. Ferrario faces challenges when attempting to link the fifth-century “commemorative media that presented significant invocation of individual memorialization” (105) to the forth- Tompkins 5 century burial with emphasis on the “positions of individuals within the oikos” (105) eventually back to Demosthenes’ perception of Creon’s actions. The challenge here is not the authority, documentation, or sufficiency of data, but rather a matter of logic. My own perspective of what Sophocles was trying to articulate to his Athenian audience is that hubris and tyranny have to be challenged. To fully understand that reactions of the original Athenian audience, it is necessary to understand why Antigone would wake up on her wedding day and decide should would rather die than allow her brother to go unburied another day. For this point might be lost on modern audiences. Though the archetypical image of the individual standing bravely against the forces of tyranny would be retained, the cultural aspects would be lost in translation. I concede that my perspective might be a bit broad, and Ferrario goes more in-depth, making cultural connections and differentiating the “religious” from the “political.” My reply to the matter of “religious” versus “political” is that, irrespective of how one categorizes the matter, the overriding issue relates to one’s basic humanity and how one responds to it. History is defined by characters like Antigone who risk everything to resist tyranny. Her character is differentiated nicely by Sophocles in form of Ismene, the meek sister, who in some way defines most of us—just wanting to get through the day, making no waves. The issue involved is base emotion and the dignity afforded to each person, and how we as individuals choose to deal with it. To this same end, Ferrario makes a compelling argument for how there was a shift in perception of Creon, and how that cultural shift can be identified by looking at the funerary practices. In response to Ferrario, I would assert that, well over a thousand years later in a culture far removed from the Athens of Sophocles and Demosthenes, the fundamental opposition of tyranny still resonates.
Recommended publications
  • Ancient Greece Webquest
    Name ___________________________________ Pd _____ Ancient Greece WebQuest Part 1: The Life of Sophocles Directions: As you look through the web pages assigned for Part 1, answer the following questions. Website #1 - Sophocles Biography (http://www.online-literature.com/sophocles) 1. What was the City Dionysia? 2. In what year did Sophocles enter his first City Dionysia? How old was he at the time? 3. Besides being a playwright, name at least three other professions or positions Sophocles held in Greek society. 4. How many total plays did Sophocles write? How many still exist in their entirety? 5. What percentage of Sophocles’ works still exist? (This is a math question - use the equation: total still existing total works = percent that still exist) 6. What is considered Sophocles’ greatest work? Website #2 - Sophocles Timeline (http://www.theatrehistory.com/ancient/sophocles002.html) 1. In what year was Sophocles born? How many years ago was his birth from our current year? (HINT: Note that Sophocles lived during B.C.; the years from 0 to our current year are A.D.). 2. In what year did Sophocles presumably write Oedipus the King and Oedipus at Colonus? 3. In what year did Sophocles first exhibit Antigone? Part 2: Greek Life Directions: As you look through the web pages assigned for Part 2, answer the following questions. Website #1 – Greek Democracy (http://www.carlos.emory.edu/ODYSSEY/GREECE/home.html) 1. From what two Greek words do we get the word democracy? 2. What is a polis, and what was the most powerful polis in ancient Greece? 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancient Greeks and Modern Realism: Ethics, Persuasion, and Power
    978–0–19–955627–4 02-Duncan-Bell-ch02 OUP299-Duncan-Bell (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) 26 of 40 June 9, 2008 16:4 2 The Ancient Greeks and Modern Realism: Ethics, Persuasion, and Power Richard Ned Lebow 2.1. INTRODUCTION There is widespread recognition that the realist tradition reached its nadir in neo- realism. In his unsuccessful effort to transform realism into a scientific theory, Kenneth Waltz, father of neorealism, denuded the realist tradition of its complex- ity and subtlety, appreciation of agency, and understanding that power is most readily transformed into influence when it is both masked and embedded in a generally accepted system of norms. Neorealism is a parody of science.1 Its key terms like power and polarity are loosely and haphazardly formulated and its scope conditions are left undefined. It relies on a process akin to natural selection to shape the behaviour of units in a world where successful strategies are not necessarily passed on to successive leaders and where the culling of less successful units rarely occurs. It more closely resembles an unfalsifiable ideology than it does a scientific theory, and its rise and fall has had little to do with conceptual and empirical advances. Its appeal lay in its apparent parsimony and superficial resemblance to science; something that says more about its adherents that it does about the theory. Its decline was hastened by the end of the Cold War, which appeared to many as a critical test case for a theory that sought primarily to explain the stability of the bipolar world.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirement
    Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Ruby Blondell, Chair Deborah Kamen Alexander Hollmann Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics Department Allison Das ii ©Copyright 2015 Allison E. Das Allison Das iii University of Washington Abstract Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E. Das Chair of Supervisory Committee Dr. Ruby Blondell Classics Department Introduction This project is intended as an examination of medical language and imagery in the speeches of Demosthenes, with special attention given to his speeches against his political opponent Aeschines, Against the False Embassy (19) and On the Crown (18). In Chapter 1, I contextualize his use of such language and imagery by exploring the influence of Hippocratic medicine on fourth- and fifth-century non-medical literature. I argue that the shared anxieties of medicine and politics, namely that both arts demand quick action and foresight on the part of the good practitioner, and the rich new vocabulary of suffering and disease, made Hippocratic medicine an enticing model for the political writer, that is, the historian, philosopher, and orator. Demosthenes' medical language and imagery should thus be seen as part of a tradition of analogizing the two arts, which began during the circulation of the first Hippocratic treatises and continued well into and past his own day. Allison Das iv In Chapter 2, I look at medical language and imagery in Demosthenes' prosecution of Aeschines for political misconduct during the Second Embassy to Philip II of Macedon, On the False Embassy.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E
    Health, Harm, and the Civic Body: Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E. Das URING HIS LIFETIME, Demosthenes saw the meteoric rise of Macedon under Philip II. Eventually, he would D also witness its ascendency under Philip’s son, Alex- ander. Throughout the course of his political career, Demos- thenes took a hard line, aggressive stance towards Macedon. But for years he would face considerable pushback from fellow politicians for his dogged pro-war policies, notably because of Athens’ participation in a series of unsuccessful and expensive military campaigns, which left its citizens hesitant to openly embrace yet another war.1 Facing what he perceived to be an apathetic public response, Demosthenes aimed to persuade the Athenian people that war with Macedon was necessary. In this paper, I examine one of his persuasive (and ultimately defensive) strategies: medical language and imagery. First, I turn to Demosthenes’ deliberative speeches. Inspired by and working in a rich tradition of analogizing politics and medicine, Demosthenes, I argue, uses medical language and imagery to shame the Athenians into supporting his policies. In the second half, I look at Demosthenes’ defense of these same policies in arguably his most famous forensic speech, On the Crown (Dem. 18). To accomplish this, I argue, Demosthenes ap- propriates the Hippocratic medical concept of prognôsis. In doing so, I contend, he moves the definition of political excellence 1 I. Worthington, Demosthenes of Athens and the Fall of Classical Greece (Oxford 2013) 65–67. ————— Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 59 (2019) 340–367 2019 Allison E. Das ALLISON E.
    [Show full text]
  • Literary Quarrels
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics (1) The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia Benjamin Acosta-Hughes University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Version 1.2 © Benjamin Acosta-Hughes, [email protected] (2) Literary Quarrels Susan Stephens Stanford University Version 1.0 © Susan Stephens Abstract: Scholars have long noted Platonic elements or allusions in Callimachus' poems, particularly in the Aetia prologue and the 13th Iambus that center on poetic composition. Following up on their work, Benjamin Acosta-Hughes and Susan Stephens, in a recent panel at the APA, and in papers that are about to appear in Callimachea II. Atti della seconda giornata di studi su Callimaco (Rome: Herder), have argued not for occasional allusions, but for a much more extensive influence from the Phaedo and Phaedrus in the Aetia prologue (Acosta-Hughes) and the Protagoras, Ion, and Phaedrus in the Iambi (Stephens). These papers are part of a preliminary study to reformulate Callimachus' aesthetic theory. 1 The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia* This paper prefigures a larger study of Callimachus and Plato, a study on which my Stanford colleague Susan Stephens and I have now embarked in our co-authored volume on Callimachus.1 Awareness of Platonic allusion in Callimachus is not new, although its significance has not really been appreciateda close reading of the two authors remains a real desideratum, and it is indeed this need that we hope our work will one day fulfill. The main focal points of the present paper are two passages of Callimachus, and two passages of Plato, that, read together, configure a remarkable intertextual dialogue on poetry, reading, and the inspired voice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Greek Plays Sixteen Plays by Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides 1St Edition Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    THE GREEK PLAYS SIXTEEN PLAYS BY AESCHYLUS, SOPHOCLES, AND EURIPIDES 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Mary Lefkowitz | 9780812993004 | | | | | The Greek Plays Sixteen Plays by Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides 1st edition PDF Book I read it over and over. Reviewed here. I remember trying to explain how real the intensity of emotion, the tragedy, the stupid arrogance felt. The footnote apparatus is more thorough than the typical reader wants or needs, but it doesn't get in the way. All in all, though, this is a collection of sixteen works of great importance to the development of drama. Tanaya Sen rated it it was amazing Sep 28, More filters. Who would have guessed one of the first recorded plays in history would engender sympathy for a mortal enemy and be written from their point of view. Many people have that thing you studied in high school that just clicked, that opened worlds and brought passion. Vandiver was intriguing especially as a contrast to Sophocles's famous Oedipus the King. The fo The book has decent paper and binding. I also re-read Thucydides, an unexpectedly tedious experience - so entered the book with the fear that the magic had gone. I've read about four of them. I took it to Greece with me, read Hippolytus as the plane descended, sat in the Theatre of Dionysus and read Medea's main monologue in the heat, returning to consume Oedipus at Colonus in a cooler early evening. But the footnotes - well - many of the footnotes are excellent, especially those relating to translation issues and meter.
    [Show full text]
  • Sophocles, Antigone Chronology 480-358 BCE Classical Greece 480
    Lecture 7 Classical Greece WC 90-105 PP 113-121: Sophocles, Antigone Chronology 480-358 BCE Classical Greece 480 Athens burned to the ground by Persians 479 Greeks victorious at the battle of Plataea 478-404 Delian League ca. 460 becomes heavy-handed 431-404 Peloponnesian War Star Terms: trireme Acropolis Socrates Geog Terms Athens Delian League Peloponnesus A. Parthenon (Athens), 447-438 BCE geometric harmony, civic architecture, home of Pallas Athena, patroness of Athens The Parthenon stands as one of the greatest monuments in the Classical world. Phidias, a leading Athenian artist of his generation and a friend of Pericles, supervised the sculptural decorations. Completed in 432 BCE as a temple to Athena, the patron goddess of Athens, the Parthenon celebrates Athena in her aspect as a virgin goddess. Parthenos, Greek for ‘virgin.’ Much like the Mesopotamian ziggurat, the Greek temple was a communal symbol of reverenct for the gods, but, whereas the ziggurat enforced the separation of priesthood and populace, the Greek temple united religious and secular domains. Its damaged state reflects centuries of neglect and misuse. In the 5th century CE the Parthenon became a Christian church, and in the 15th century the Turks conquered Athens and converted the temple into a mosque. They stored gunpowder in the building! When it was shelled by artillery in 1687, most of the interior and many sculptures were destroyed. This building is significant because it represents the grand aspirations of Pericles and his ambition to make Athens the center of the Greek world. When the Delian League, originally a voluntary confederation of Greek city-states bound together as a common defense organization (think NATO) became a military tool of its largest and most powerful member Athens (think America) the treasury was moved from Delos, an important island dedicated to the god Apollo, to Athens, the Athenian Empire had begun.
    [Show full text]
  • Sophocles (496–406 BCE)
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Departmental Papers (Classical Studies) Classical Studies at Penn 2010 Sophocles (496–406 BCE) Sheila Murnaghan University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers Part of the Classics Commons Recommended Citation Murnaghan, S. (2010). Sophocles (496–406 BCE). The Oxford Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece and Rome, http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acref/9780195170726.001.0001 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/127 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Sophocles (496–406 BCE) Abstract Sophocles’ plays stand out for their portraits of isolation. They showcase characters cut off from others by their difficult personalities andy b the circumstances of disease, disgrace, criminality, defiance of authority, exile, bereavement, and early death. Yet from what we can tell, these conditions were quite unlike Sophocles’ own experience. Though the ancient biographies of poets are late and often unreliable, our evidence supports the summary given by Sophocles’ biographer of an enviable life: “he was illustrious both in life and in poetry, he was well educated and raised in comfortable circumstances, and he was chosen for political offices and embassies.” Disciplines Arts and Humanities | Classics This other is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/127 Oxford Reference The Oxford Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece and Rome Edited by Michael Gagarin Publisher: Oxford University Press Print Publication Date: 2010 Print ISBN-13: 9780195170726 Published online: 2010 Current Online Version: 2010 eISBN: 9780195388398 Sophocles (496–406 BCE), Athenian tragedian. Sophocles’ plays stand out for their portraits of isolation.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Macedonians
    Ancient Macedonians This article is about the native inhabitants of the historical kingdom of Macedonia. For the modern ethnic Greek people from Macedonia, Greece, see Macedonians (Greeks). For other uses, see Ancient Macedonian (disambiguation) and Macedonian (disambiguation). From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia ANCIENT MACEDONIANS ΜΑΚΕΔΌΝΕΣ Stag Hunt Mosaic, 4th century BC Languages. Ancient Macedonian, then Attic Greek, and later Koine Greek Religion. ancient Greek religion The Macedonians (Greek: Μακεδόνες, Makedónes) were an ancient tribe that lived on the alluvial plain around the rivers Haliacmonand lower Axios in the northeastern part of mainland Greece. Essentially an ancient Greek people,[1] they gradually expanded from their homeland along the Haliacmon valley on the northern edge of the Greek world, absorbing or driving out neighbouring non-Greek tribes, primarily Thracian and Illyrian.[2][3] They spoke Ancient Macedonian, a language closely related to Ancient Greek, perhaps a dialect, although the prestige language of the region was at first Attic and then Koine Greek.[4] Their religious beliefs mirrored those of other Greeks, following the main deities of the Greek pantheon, although the Macedonians continued Archaic burial practices that had ceased in other parts of Greece after the 6th century BC. Aside from the monarchy, the core of Macedonian society was its nobility. Similar to the aristocracy of neighboring Thessaly, their wealth was largely built on herding horses and cattle. Although composed of various clans, the kingdom of Macedonia, established around the 8th century BC, is mostly associated with the Argead dynasty and the tribe named after it. The dynasty was allegedly founded by Perdiccas I, descendant of the legendary Temenus of Argos, while the region of Macedon perhaps derived its name from Makedon, a figure of Greek mythology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Victory Ode in the Theatre *
    The victory ode in the theatre * By the middle of the fifth century the victory ode had reached the end of its life as a major commissioned song form. After Pindar and Bacchylides, the sung epinician attracts no major poetic talent, with the unique exception of the victory ode for Alcibiades attributed to Euripides. Paradoxically, at a time when the Panhellenic elite had ceased to pay for celebratory songs for public performance, the epinician found a new lease of life in – of all places – democratic Athens, a state where it had never had a pronounced presence in its original form. 1 The surviving epinician corpus contains two victory odes for Athenians, one performed outside Athens for an exile ( P.7), the other very brief ( N.2). Athens is not alone in showing little collective interest in the large scale compositions which were so welcome in Aigina, for instance, and there are many cities which unlike Athens are unrepresented in our epinician corpus. 2 But there was evidently no market in Athens for lavish performances in celebration of individual athletic victories. This did not prevent the diffusion (in some form) of (at least some) high profile odes for non-Athenian victors among a large enough portion of the population to allow fifth century comic poets to allude to them without fear of losing their audience. 3 The genre also finds resonance in both historiography and in oratory.4 Probably there is no single explanation for this continued reverberation in the collective memory. The role of lyric song in education and relaxation is part of the answer.
    [Show full text]
  • Sophoclessophocles
    SophoclesSophocles •Sophocles’ Life and Work •The Oedipus Myth •The Plot of Oedipus the King •Sophocles’ Oedipus the King SophoclesSophocles LifeLife andand WorkWork •born ca. 495 BCE and died 406 BCE •thus, Sophocles witnessed the glories of the Classical Age: –the Persian Wars –the construction of the Parthenon –the birth of Greek philosophy –but also the Peloponnesian War – however not the siege of Athens in 404 BCE which ended the Peloponnesian War SophoclesSophocles LifeLife andand WorkWork •• SophoclesSophocles was born into a wealthy family and never had to work for a living •he dedicated his entire life to public service and writing plays •as a youth, he led the procession celebrating the Greek victory in the Second Persian War (479 BCE) SophoclesSophocles LifeLife andand WorkWork •Sophocles was elected to high office in Athens several times •late in life, he was heralded a “hero” named DexionDexion (“the Receiver”) for having sheltered the sacred snake of Aesclepius, the god of healing •to be declared a “hero” was the highest honor a person could receive in ancient Athens SophoclesSophocles LifeLife andand WorkWork •early in his playwriting career, Sophocles won first place at the Dionysia, along the way defeating the veteran Aeschylus •Sophocles then went on to win a record number of first places in playwriting •he was clearly the most beloved and respected playwright in the generation following Aeschylus SophoclesSophocles LifeLife andand WorkWork •the philosopher Aristotle tells us that Sophocles introduced the thirdthird
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of God in Aeschylus and Sophocles
    The idea of god in Aeschylus and Sophocles Autor(en): Kitto, H.D.F. Objekttyp: Article Zeitschrift: Entretiens sur l'Antiquité classique Band (Jahr): 1 (1954) PDF erstellt am: 08.10.2021 Persistenter Link: http://doi.org/10.5169/seals-660953 Nutzungsbedingungen Die ETH-Bibliothek ist Anbieterin der digitalisierten Zeitschriften. Sie besitzt keine Urheberrechte an den Inhalten der Zeitschriften. Die Rechte liegen in der Regel bei den Herausgebern. Die auf der Plattform e-periodica veröffentlichten Dokumente stehen für nicht-kommerzielle Zwecke in Lehre und Forschung sowie für die private Nutzung frei zur Verfügung. Einzelne Dateien oder Ausdrucke aus diesem Angebot können zusammen mit diesen Nutzungsbedingungen und den korrekten Herkunftsbezeichnungen weitergegeben werden. Das Veröffentlichen von Bildern in Print- und Online-Publikationen ist nur mit vorheriger Genehmigung der Rechteinhaber erlaubt. Die systematische Speicherung von Teilen des elektronischen Angebots auf anderen Servern bedarf ebenfalls des schriftlichen Einverständnisses der Rechteinhaber. Haftungsausschluss Alle Angaben erfolgen ohne Gewähr für Vollständigkeit oder Richtigkeit. Es wird keine Haftung übernommen für Schäden durch die Verwendung von Informationen aus diesem Online-Angebot oder durch das Fehlen von Informationen. Dies gilt auch für Inhalte Dritter, die über dieses Angebot zugänglich sind. Ein Dienst der ETH-Bibliothek ETH Zürich, Rämistrasse 101, 8092 Zürich, Schweiz, www.library.ethz.ch http://www.e-periodica.ch V H. D. F. KITTO The Idea of God in Aeschylus and Sophocles THE IDEA OF GOD IN AESCHYLUS AND SOPHOCLES Our survey has now reached a period in which the poets' religious and philosophical thought is fully conscious. But we shall do well to remember how they expressed that thought, and how we, in our turn, must try to recover it.
    [Show full text]