The Epistemic Parity of Religious-Apologetic and Religion-Debunking Responses to the Cognitive Science of Religion

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Epistemic Parity of Religious-Apologetic and Religion-Debunking Responses to the Cognitive Science of Religion religions Article The Epistemic Parity of Religious-Apologetic and Religion-Debunking Responses to the Cognitive Science of Religion Walter Scott Stepanenko Department of Philosophy, John Carroll University, University Heights, OH 44118, USA; [email protected] Abstract: Recent work in the cognitive science of religion has challenged some of the explanatory assumptions of previous research in the field. Nonetheless, some of the practitioners of the new cognitive science of religion theorize in the same skeptical spirit as their predecessors and either imply or explicitly claim that their projects undermine the warrant of religious beliefs. In this article, I argue that these theories do no additional argumentative work when compared to previous attempts to debunk religious belief and that these recent debunking efforts are very much motivated by methodological commitments that are shared with canonical research. I contend that these argumentative strategies put debunkers very much on an epistemic par with religious apologists: both advocate responses to the cognitive science of religion that are primarily motivated by methodological commitments. Keywords: epistemology; religious experience; cognitive science of religion Citation: Stepanenko, Walter Scott. 2021. The Epistemic Parity of 1. Introduction Religious-Apologetic and The discourse around the cognitive science of religion (CSR) creates the impression Religion-Debunking Responses to the that religion debunkers are in an epistemically superior position relative to religious Cognitive Science of Religion. apologists. A great deal of philosophical and theological work in the literature is dedicated Religions 12: 466. https://doi.org/ to the construction of debunking arguments motivated by CSR evidence and apologetic 10.3390/rel12070466 responses to these arguments. In this article, I argue that the reality of the epistemic situation is quite different, and that religious apologists and religion debunkers are in Academic Editor: Mark Webb very similar epistemic positions. To make this case, I first explicate some features of Received: 18 May 2021 traditional research projects developed in CSR. I then contrast these projects with more Accepted: 22 June 2021 recent developments in the field. I argue that both projects motivate debunking arguments Published: 25 June 2021 in which methodological commitments rather than first-order scientific evidence are doing much of the argumentative work. I explain that these are commitments that most religious Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral apologists reject and that the debate over the implications of CSR comes down to the with regard to jurisdictional claims in viability of various methodological commitments. Insofar as CSR itself cannot settle published maps and institutional affil- these issues and debates over these commitments are philosophically live, I conclude that 1 iations. religious apologists and religion debunkers are on an epistemic par with respect to CSR. 2. Canonical Cognitive Science of Religion The canonical cognitive science of religion (CCSR) can best be described as a research 2 Copyright: © 2021 by the author. program that is committed to the scientific investigation of religion. Defined in this way, Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. CCSR need not involve a commitment to debunk, undermine, or otherwise defeat religious This article is an open access article beliefs.3 In fact, defined in this way CCSR does not necessarily require practitioners to distributed under the terms and develop projects that fix their explanatory scope on religious belief(s). For example, this conditions of the Creative Commons definition of CCSR covers explanatory projects that involve a coarse-grained explanatory Attribution (CC BY) license (https:// scope that is concerned with offering accounts of the ubiquity and/or persistence of reli- creativecommons.org/licenses/by/ gious behavior.4 However, many practitioners in CCSR take their work to have implications 4.0/). Religions 2021, 12, 466. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12070466 https://www.mdpi.com/journal/religions Religions 2021, 12, 466 2 of 12 for the warrant of religious belief. For example, Bloom(2009) suggests that CCSR cannot refute theism, but that CCSR can “still tell us something about the rationality, or lack thereof, of religious believers” (p. 126). Nonetheless, different practitioners pursue differ- ent explanatory strategies. Some theorists advocate adaptationist accounts of religion.5 For these theorists, the ubiquity and persistence of religious belief and behavior are explained by appealing to the ways that they contribute to evolutionary fitness. Other theorists advocate by-product accounts of religion.6 For these theorists, the ubiquity and persis- tence of religious belief and behavior are explained by appeal to the accidental outcomes produced by the normal functioning of otherwise adaptive cognitive processes. Despite these differences, there is quite a bit more common theoretical ground than the distinction between these two approaches implies. Many adaptationists fix their explanatory scope on extant monotheistic traditions, while many by-product theorists are most concerned with explaining the ubiquity of beliefs in supernatural persons. In this way, adaptationists often subsume by-product theories and imply that cognitive by-products are later co-opted by organized traditions where they play the role of exaptations. To see this, consider a CCSR account following along lines suggested by Boyer(2002) and Norenzayan(2013): Human beings are animals just like any other animal, and just like every animal constrained by evolutionary processes of natural selection, human beings must survive long enough to reproduce and pass down their genes to the next generation. However, survival is no easy matter. Threats abound in most environments and every animal needs to be prepared to fend them off or evade them. Therefore, an animal will be well-suited for its environment if it is prone to identify threats. This makes agency detection very important. If an animal fails to detect a threat, it will be eaten and therefore unable to reproduce and pass down its genes to the next generation. However, if an animal is very sensitive to possible threats, it might flee more times than it needs to, but the only cost would be calories. Therefore, natural selection would favor trigger-happy animals over agency-insensitive animals, but the trigger-happy animals would be likely to overattribute agency. They would possess minds tailored to identify agents where there are none. If these animals are social animals, they would also possess minds tailored to attribute mental states wherever they detect agency. These animals would be prone to identify agents where there are none and to attribute various goals or desires to these agents. Therefore, these animals would be predisposed for belief in invisible, but imaginary, persons. The existence of such persons is surprising, given that they are like other persons these animals know in most respects except for the fact they are invisible, but the concept of an invisible agent is not so extravagant that it is difficult to remember. Therefore, the recognition of surprising invisible agents would be easy to transmit because the concept is captivating and easy to remember. Thus, belief in such agents could spread across a population. As it does, this belief could ratchet up the solidarity amongst the members. Belief in these invisible agents could then become a sign of one’s group affiliation, but it could also become a way of keeping people in line. Group members cannot always monitor one another’s behavior, but an invisible agent can stand in for them. The more that agent knows and sees, the more it can police, but it can only police that behavior if it has the intention and power to do so. Therefore, a group that believed in one invisible agent with as much power, knowledge, and goodness as possible might be able to coerce cooperation in a way that another group without that belief could not. Groups with such beliefs might therefore outcompete groups without such beliefs, and as a result, they could more successfully reproduce and spread across various regions such that over time and space, an entire race of progeny would exist with the genetic predisposition for their belief system. Such a story captures the most crucial theoretical elements in various theories in CCSR. That it is a coherent story is one reason for its popularity amongst theorists, but what is most important for present purposes is the identification of various theoretical postulates therein. First, we have various cognitive processes producing the “raw materials” for religious belief. Chief among these is the hyperactive agency detection device, or HADD. HADD is the cognitive process that is responsible for producing belief in agents, but it Religions 2021, 12, 466 3 of 12 is unreliable. It detects agents in more cases than those in which an agent is actually present, but that is not all. HADD is expanded by theory of mind (ToM). ToM involves various cognitive processes that are responsible for attributing mental states to agents. Together HADD and ToM dispose individuals to believe in persons who are not there. These beliefs could be transient, but they are minimally counterintuitive (MCI): they violate categorical expectations but in only a few respects. They are surprising, but because they only minimally violate categorical expectations, they are easy to remember. They can therefore
Recommended publications
  • Disgust: Evolved Function and Structure
    Psychological Review © 2012 American Psychological Association 2013, Vol. 120, No. 1, 65–84 0033-295X/13/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0030778 Disgust: Evolved Function and Structure Joshua M. Tybur Debra Lieberman VU University Amsterdam University of Miami Robert Kurzban Peter DeScioli University of Pennsylvania Brandeis University Interest in and research on disgust has surged over the past few decades. The field, however, still lacks a coherent theoretical framework for understanding the evolved function or functions of disgust. Here we present such a framework, emphasizing 2 levels of analysis: that of evolved function and that of information processing. Although there is widespread agreement that disgust evolved to motivate the avoidance of contact with disease-causing organisms, there is no consensus about the functions disgust serves when evoked by acts unrelated to pathogen avoidance. Here we suggest that in addition to motivating pathogen avoidance, disgust evolved to regulate decisions in the domains of mate choice and morality. For each proposed evolved function, we posit distinct information processing systems that integrate function-relevant information and account for the trade-offs required of each disgust system. By refocusing the discussion of disgust on computational mechanisms, we recast prior theorizing on disgust into a framework that can generate new lines of empirical and theoretical inquiry. Keywords: disgust, adaptation, evolutionary psychology, emotion, cognition Research concerning disgust has expanded in recent years (Ola- selection pressure driving the evolution of the disgust system, but tunji & Sawchuk, 2005; Rozin, Haidt, & McCauley, 2009), and there has been less precision in identifying the selection pressures contemporary disgust researchers generally agree that an evolu- driving the evolution of disgust systems unrelated to pathogen tionary perspective is necessary for a comprehensive understand- avoidance (e.g., behavior in the sexual and moral domains).
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroscience, Psychology and Religion : Illusions, Delusions, and Realities About Human Nature Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    NEUROSCIENCE, PSYCHOLOGY AND RELIGION : ILLUSIONS, DELUSIONS, AND REALITIES ABOUT HUMAN NATURE PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Malcolm Jeeves | 204 pages | 01 Apr 2009 | Templeton Foundation Press,U.S. | 9781599471471 | English | Radnor, United States Neuroscience, Psychology and Religion : Illusions, Delusions, and Realities About Human Nature PDF Book In this volume, Malcolm Jeeves and Warren S. Psychology of Religion Newsletter , 31 , 1—8. To the extent that this relational-deictic stance represents a cognitive default, however, it may still serve as a strong foundation for religious cultural notions. History can be written at any magnification. A critical examination. However, the basic insight that psychological processes depend on neural activity has a clinical base dating back at least to the seventeenth century, to the work of Thomas Willis, whose multifaceted neurological work led him to tie human desires and instincts, memory and imagination, reason and volition to the brain and central nervous system. Religious motivation reduces perceived responsibility for and morality of good deeds. James K. Content Metrics. God is watching you: Priming God concepts increases prosocial behavior in an anonymous economic game. Nov 30, Timothy Wilson rated it really liked it. Of course, questions like this are not only the stuff of film and literature. This article has been cited by other articles in PMC. A historical database of sociocultural evolution. Miles rated it liked it Jun 03, Privacy Statement. Sign in to annotate. Failures to observe the laws of the Kivung are said to delay the miracle of returning ancestors. A latent capacity for evolutionary innovation through exaptation in metabolic systems. Humans should therefore be equipped by natural selection with biased agency-detection mechanisms—what J.
    [Show full text]
  • What Cognitive Science of Religion Can Learn from John Dewey
    contemporary pragmatism 15 (2018) 387-406 brill.com/copr What Cognitive Science of Religion Can Learn from John Dewey Hans Van Eyghen vu Amsterdam [email protected] Abstract I use three ideas from philosopher John Dewey that are of service for Cognitive Science of Religion (csr). I discuss how Dewey’s ideas on embodied cognition, embedded cog- nition can be put to work to get a fuller understanding of religious cognition. I also use his ideas to criticize csr’s reliance on the modularity of mind thesis Keywords cognitive science of religion – modularity of mind – embodied cognition – embedded cognition, John Dewey – religious cognition Introduction Cognitive science of religion is a fairly young discipline with the aim of study- ing the cognitive basis of religious belief. Despite the great variation in theo- ries a number of common features can be distilled and most theories can be situated in the cognitivist and modular paradigm. In this paper, I investigate how cognitive science of religion (csr) can be improved by using insights from philosopher John Dewey. I focus on Dewey because he offered important in- sights in cognition long before there was cognitive science and because his ideas are widely influential in the recent enactivist movement. The relevance of Dewey’s thought for csr will be discussed under three headers: embodied- ness, embeddedness and anti-modularity. I will first give a brief overview of the most influential theories in csr. Then I will discuss how existing theories in csr can be improved on the first two points and criticized on the third. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi 10.1163/18758185-01503007Downloaded from Brill.com09/25/2021 09:33:53AM via free access 204221 388 Van Eyghen The Cognitive Science of Religion Cognitive science of religion is a fairly young discipline (from the 1990’s on- wards) with the aim of studying the cognitive basis of religious belief.
    [Show full text]
  • Morality Is for Choosing Sides
    CHAPTER 18 Morality Is for Choosing Sides Peter DeScioli Robert Kurzban Why did moral judgment evolve? To help people choose sides when conflicts erupt within groups with complex coalitions and power hierarchies. Theories of inorality have largely tried to ex­ What, then, might be the benefits gained plain the brighter side of behavior, answer­ tl1rough moral judgn1e11ts? Consider a situ­ i11g questio11s about wl1y people behave ii1 atio11 in wl1ich a perso11 accuses so1neo11e of ways that are kind, generous, and good. Our witchcraft, such as in Arthur Miller's The proposal focuses not on explaining n1oral Crucible. Specifically, suppose tl1at a you11g, behavior but, rather, on explaining inoral low-status wo1na11 accuses an older, more judgn1ent. Co11sider son1eone readi11g a pron1i11ent wo111an of witchcraft. Other news story abot1t a rnan who pays a woman members of the commt1nity can respond in to have sex with him. Many people wot1ld a few different ways. judge-in an intuitive way (Haidt, 2012)­ One obviot1s move for a self-interested that both the man's and woman's actions are observer is to curry favor with the higher­ n1orally wrong. O t1r interest lies in the ex­ status wornan. Choosing sides based on sta­ planation for these and similar judgments. tus often occurs in very hierarchical groups Theories that atte1npt to explain moral such as tl1e inilitary (Fiske, 1992). It is also behavior often point to altruism or benefits observed i11 11onl1uma11 ani111als: For i11- (de Waal, 1996; Krebs, 2005; Ridley, 1996; stance, hyenas join fights and st1pport the Wright, 1994). The theory of reciprocal al­ higher-statt1s and more formidable fighter truism (Trivers, 1971), for instance, explains (Holekamp, Sakai, & Lt1ndriga11, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Biases Explain Religious Belief, Paranormal Belief, and Belief in Life’S Purpose ⇑ Aiyana K
    Cognition 129 (2013) 379–391 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Cognitive biases explain religious belief, paranormal belief, and belief in life’s purpose ⇑ Aiyana K. Willard , Ara Norenzayan 1 Department of Psychology, The University of British Columbia, 2136 West Mall, Vancouver, BC V6T 1Z4, Canada article info abstract Article history: Cognitive theories of religion have postulated several cognitive biases that predispose Received 4 March 2013 human minds towards religious belief. However, to date, these hypotheses have not been Revised 25 July 2013 tested simultaneously and in relation to each other, using an individual difference Accepted 27 July 2013 approach. We used a path model to assess the extent to which several interacting cognitive tendencies, namely mentalizing, mind body dualism, teleological thinking, and anthropo- morphism, as well as cultural exposure to religion, predict belief in God, paranormal beliefs Keywords: and belief in life’s purpose. Our model, based on two independent samples (N = 492 and Religion N = 920) found that the previously known relationship between mentalizing and belief is Cognitive biases Paranormal belief mediated by individual differences in dualism, and to a lesser extent by teleological think- Purpose ing. Anthropomorphism was unrelated to religious belief, but was related to paranormal belief. Cultural exposure to religion (mostly Christianity) was negatively related to anthro- pomorphism, and was unrelated to any of the other cognitive tendencies. These patterns were robust for both men and women, and across at least two ethnic identifications. The data were most consistent with a path model suggesting that mentalizing comes first, which leads to dualism and teleology, which in turn lead to religious, paranormal, and life’s-purpose beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Supernatural Beliefs Commitment Devices for Intergroup Conflict?
    Are Supernatural Beliefs Commitment Devices For Intergroup Conflict? Robert Kurzban John Christner University of Pennsylvania Robert Kurzban Department of Psychology 3720 Walnut St. Philadelphia PA 19104 (215) 898‐4977 [email protected] Abstract. In a world of potentially fluid alliances in which group size is an important determinant of success in aggressive conflict, groups can be expected to compete for members. By the same token, individuals in such contexts can be expected to compete for membership in large, cohesive groups. In the context of this competition, the ability to signal that one cannot change groups can be a strategic advantage because members of groups would prefer to have loyal allies rather than confederates who might switch groups as conditions change. This idea might help to explain why members of certain kinds of groups, especially competitive ones, use marks, scars and other more or less permanent modifications of their bodies to signal their membership. To the extent that people with these marks have difficulty joining rival groups, these marks are effective in signaling one’s commitment. It is possible that the public endorsement of certain kinds of beliefs have the same effect as marks. In particular, there are certain beliefs which, when endorsed, might make membership difficult in all but one group. This idea is proposed as an explanation for supernatural beliefs. Are Supernatural Beliefs Commitment Devices? Arguably the most important political event of the albeit still young 21st century was a case of intergroup conflict in which supernatural beliefs played a pivotal role. The attack on the World Trade Center in New York City, the Pentagon in Washington DC, and the foiled attack by the hijackers of United Airlines Flight 93 on September 11th, 2001, was motivated by intergroup conflict, but made possible in no small part because the perpetrators had beliefs about the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • Can the Social Scientists Be Saved? Should They?
    Evolutionary Psychology human-nature.com/ep – 2006. 4: 102-106 ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Book Review Can the social scientists be saved? Should they? A review of Missing the Revolution: Darwinism for Social Scientists by Jerome H. Barkow (Ed.). 2006. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. 302 + vii. $49.95 (hardcover). Satoshi Kanazawa, London School of Economics, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE, United Kingdom. Email: [email protected]. I began my graduate career in the Department of Sociology at the University of Washington, where the great sociobiologist Pierre van den Berghe taught all his career. I was a stupid SSSM (“Standard Social Science Model”) sociology graduate student then, and I joined the chorus of the confederacy of dunces to ridicule Pierre’s sociobiological work. More than a decade later, I discovered evolutionary psychology on my own by reading Wright's The Moral Animal, and converted to it overnight. When I began working in EP, I apologized to Pierre for having been too dense to see the light a decade earlier, and told him my grand plan to introduce EP into sociology and revolutionize social sciences. Pierre was encouraging but cautious. He told me that he had tried to do that himself a quarter of a century earlier but to no avail. Sociologists were just too stupid to understand the importance of biology in human behavior, a view that he has expressed in print (van den Berghe, 1990), and he eventually left the field in disgust. Blinded by youthful optimism and ambition, I did not heed Pierre’s cautionary words and tried very hard to introduce EP into sociology.
    [Show full text]
  • See No Evil, Speak No Evil? Morality, Evolutionary Psychology, and the Nature of International Relations Brian C
    See No Evil, Speak No Evil? Morality, Evolutionary Psychology, and the Nature of International Relations Brian C. Rathbun and Caleb Pomeroy Abstract A central theme in the study of international relations is that anarchy requires states set aside moral concerns to attain security, rendering IR an autonomous sphere devoid of ethical considerations. Evolutionary and moral psychology, however, suggest that morality emerged to promote human success. It is not despite anarchy but because of anarchy that humans have an ethical sense. Our argument has three empirical implications. First, it is almost impossible to talk about threat and harm without invoking morality. Second, state leaders and the public will use moral judgments as a basis, indeed the most important factor, for assessing international threat, just as research shows they do at the interpersonal level. Third, foreign policy driven by a conception of international relations as an amoral sphere will be quite rare. Word embeddings applied to large political and non-political corpora, a survey experiment in Russia, surveys of the Chinese mass public, and an in-depth analysis of Hitler’s foreign policy thought suggest that individuals both speak evil, condemning aggressive behavior by others, and see evil, screening for threats on the basis of morality. The findings erode notions of IR as an autonomous sphere and upset traditional materialist-ideational dichotomies. A frequent theme in international relations (IR) theory is that foreign affairs is an amoral realm where everyday ethical norms know no place. Under anarchy, ethical considerations must be set aside because morality’s restraints hinder the necessary pursuit of egoistic interests through the use of threats and violence.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Science 2011
    Cognitive Science 2011 press.princeton.edu contents 1 general interest A Message from the Editor 4 psychology 5 social science It is with great pleasure that, on behalf of my colleagues at Princeton University Press, I introduce our inaugural cognitive 8 philosophy science catalog. The books here exemplify the quality of schol- 10 biology arship that we prize, and reflect the interdisciplinary approach that we take to publishing. Indeed, cognitive science—an in- 11 best of the backlist terdisciplinary field connecting research within the humanities, 13 index/order form social science, and science—is a natural fit for the Press. As demonstrated in the following pages, our cognitive science publishing includes work from psychologists and neurosci- entists, philosophers of mind, evolutionary biologists, and social scientists of all stripes. This catalog highlights recent and forthcoming books by established and diverse voices such as Max Bazerman and Ann Tenbrunsel, Patricia Churchland, Nicho- las Humphrey, Michael Corballis, Paul Thagard, Louise Barrett, and Thomas Seeley, as well as the newcomer Robert Kurzban, whom Steven Pinker calls “one of the best evolutionary psy- chologists of his generation.” Also featured here are important classic works by authors such as Frans de Waal, Jean-Pierre Changeux, Richard Gregory, Richard Thaler, Robert Shiller, Peter Singer, and Thomas Henry Huxley. Unifying all of these authors and books, past and present, is an effort to provide a clearer understanding of the relationship between the brain, the mind, individual behavior, social interaction, and social institutions. We believe that this catalog heralds a bright future for our cognitive science program, and we hope that within these pages you will find books and ideas that inspire and enlighten.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Nature & Human Diversity Syllabus – Part II: Topics
    1/10/2017 Human Nature & Human Diversity Philosophy 253 (01:730:253) & Cognitive Science 253 (01:185:253) Spring Term 2018 Syllabus – Part II: Topics & Assignments Part II of the Syllabus is a WORK IN PROGRESS; it will be updated frequently during the term. Assigned readings and videos will change as we discover better material. (Suggestions are ALWAYS welcome!) Dates will inevitably be adjusted as we find that some topics need extra discussion and debate while others can be covered more quickly. Changes in Part II of the Syllabus will be announced in lecture, in the Announcements on Sakai, and via e-mail. Books to buy: 1. Jonathan Haidt, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion, Pantheon Books, 2012. 2. Joseph Henrich, The Secret of Our Success: How Culture Is Driving Human Evolution, Domesticating our Species, and Making Us Smarter. Princeton University Press. These book are available at the Rutgers Barnes & Noble bookstore. They can also be purchased on-line are often less expensive on-line. All other readings for the course will be available on the Sakai site for the course. Topics & Readings: January 18 Lecture topic: Introduction to the Course: A Very Brief Discussion of the Mechanics of the Course What Is Human Nature? An Overview of the Topics We’ll Be Exploring (Part 1) Reading (to be completed prior to the lecture): Course Syllabus, Parts I & II; Policies on Behavior in the Classroom; Grading Scale Videos i) To be viewed before the lecture: Judgment Day: Intelligent Design on Trial (available on Sakai in the Streaming Video folder) – from the beginning thru 1:00:25 ii) In lecture: The Science of Sex Appeal: Part 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Is There a Law Instinct?
    Washington University Law Review Volume 87 Issue 2 2009 Is There a Law Instinct? Michael D. Guttentag Loyola Law School Los Angeles Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview Part of the Jurisprudence Commons Recommended Citation Michael D. Guttentag, Is There a Law Instinct?, 87 WASH. U. L. REV. 269 (2009). Available at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview/vol87/iss2/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Law Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IS THERE A LAW INSTINCT? MICHAEL D. GUTTENTAG ABSTRACT The widely held view is that legal systems develop in response to purposeful efforts to achieve economic, political, or social objectives. An alternative view is that reliance on legal systems to organize social activity is an integral part of human nature, just as language and morality now appear to be directly shaped by innate predispositions. This Article formalizes and presents evidence in support of the claim that humans innately turn to legal systems to organize social behavior. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................ 270 I. THE LAW INSTINCT HYPOTHESIS ......................................................... 276 A. On the Three Essential Features of a Legal System ................ 277 1. Distinguishing Legal Systems from Other Types of Normative Behavior......................................................... 279 2. Distinguishing the Law Instinct Hypothesis from Related Claims ................................................................ 280 3. The Normativity of Law ................................................... 281 4. The Union of Primary Rules and Secondary Rules ......... 282 5.
    [Show full text]
  • The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook
    Brooklyn Law Review Volume 75 Issue 2 SYMPOSIUM: Article 4 Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care? 2009 The aN tures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr Recommended Citation Bailey Kuklin, The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook. L. Rev. (2009). Available at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr/vol75/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Brooklyn Law Review by an authorized editor of BrooklynWorks. The Natures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin† One of the abiding lessons from postmodernism is that reason does not go all the way down.1 In the context of this symposium, one cannot deductively derive a universal morality from incontestible moral primitives,2 or practical reason alone.3 Instead, even reasoned moral systems must ultimately be grounded on intuition,4 a sense of justice. The question then † Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School. I wish to thank the presenters and participants of the Brooklyn Law School Symposium entitled “Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care?” and those at the Tenth SEAL Scholarship Conference. Further thanks go to Brooklyn Law School for supporting this project with a summer research stipend. 1 “Simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern as incredulity toward metanarratives.” JEAN-FRANCOIS LYOTARD, THE POSTMODERN CONDITION: A REPORT ON KNOWLEDGE xxiv (Geoff Bennington & Brian Massumi trans., 1984). “If modernity is viewed with Weberian optimism as the project of rationalisation of the life-world, an era of material progress, social emancipation and scientific innovation, the postmodern is derided as chaotic, catastrophic, nihilistic, the end of good order.” COSTAS DOUZINAS ET AL., POSTMODERN JURISPRUDENCE 16 (1991).
    [Show full text]