<<

Hypatia, Inc.

!"#!$%&'"(%)*&#%+#,(-).)/01#2&0)")/0#("3#45/%67('#89&+': !5%9+';/<=#>5-)"3(#4?#,&(-9 @&*)&A&3#A+'B;/<= C+5'-&=#D:E(%)(F#G+$?#HF#I+?#JF#2&0)")/0#("3#,&(-&#;CE')"KF#LHHM=#http://www.jstor.org/stable/3810175 . !--&//&3=#JJRSLRJSLT#LT=NU

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Hypatia, Inc. and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Hypatia.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions An Alternativeto ? Feminismand Just-War Theory

LUCINDA J. PEACH

Only rarelyhave feminist theorists addressed the adequacyof just-wartheory, a set of principlesdeveloped over hundreds of yearsto assessthe of goingto war and the moralityof conductin war. Recently,a few feministscholars have found just-wartheory inadequate, yet theirown counterproposals are also deficient. I assess feministcontributions to just-war theorizing and suggest ways of strengthening,rather thanabandoning, this moral approach to war.

INTRODUCTION

Womenhave traditionallybeen excludedfrom involvement in war.War has been consideredalmost exclusively a male enterprise:fought by men, with and againstother men, for male-definedpurposes and ends. Culturally,traditional ideasabout gender roles identifymen with warand soldiering,and women with and mothering. Women remain largelyabsent from ethical and policy debatesregarding when to go to war,how to fight a war,and whether resorting to war is morallyjustifiable. In recent years,several feminists have challenged this traditional genderizeddichotomy between war and peace, as well as the validity of the male-conceived theories that assessthe moralityof war.In this paper,I evaluate feminist criticismsof one of these male-generatedtheories, that of just-war.1 After having no discernibleimpact on foreignpolicy analysisof any armed conflict for many years,just-war theory suddenlygained national prominence and recognition in relation to the Persian Gulf War. The theory developed over many centuries in Christian theology and internationallaw into a set of criteriadesigned to determinewhen, and to what extent, limited participation in armedconflict maybe moral.Just-war theorists generally share with pacifists a basicpresumption opposing war as morallywrong (see Miller 1991, 117;Cady 1989). However,whereas pacifist perspectives share a firm belief that war is

Hypatiavol. 9, no. 2 (Spring 1994) © by LucindaJ. Peach

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 153

never a moral means to achieve potentially just goals, those subscribingto just-wartheory are open to being persuadedthat war may be morallyjustified in certain circumstances.Both of these positions contrast with the views of "warists"or "warrealists," who considermorality to be irrelevant,inapplicable, or ineffective in relation to war (see Cady 1989, xi-xii).2 In our gender-struc- tured society, warism has been the culturally dominant and presumptively correct view (see Cady 1989, chap. 1). There are undoubtedlymyriad problems with attemptingto generalizea "fem- inist perspective"about just-wartheory, given the varietyof differentfeminist perspectivesabout the moralityof war.Popular conception and actualpractice alike align women with peace and pacifism,not with a positionthat acceptswar as potentiallymoral. For example,women have been and continue to be more actively involved than men in peace movements.3Recent public opinion polls indicatethat women aremore oriented to peacefulresolution of disputesthan are men, reflectingan average15 to 20 percent"gender gap" on the issueof military involvement and the use of force (see Gallagher1993; Branscombeand Owen 1993;Baxter and Lansing1983, 56-57, 196).4Women's social protest movements have achievedsignificant political leverage from their identification as "naturally" more peacefulthan men, basedon their relationshipto childbearingand child- rearing(see Ruddick1989; Pierson 1988; Swerdlow 1989). But despite the historical and ideological alignmentsbetween women (and feminists) and peace, not all women, even feminist women, are pacifists.5 Political scientist Jean Bethke Elshtain,for instance, expresslydenies that she is a pacifist, arguing that some wars have been necessary and that it is not possible to transcend "collective violence in defense of the state" (Elshtain 1987, 257). Feminist theorist Sara Ruddickaligns herself more with pacifism, especially in denouncing just-wartheory for its legitimation of certain forms of violence. However, she argues that "threatenedpeoples [may] not have alternative nonviolent ways of protecting what they and getting what they need" (Ruddick 1989, 139). Ruddickand Elshtainagree with St. Augus- tine, an early Christian Church Fatherwho is consideredto be the "founder" of just-wartheory within the Christian tradition (see Kehoe 1986, 156), that war may be an element necessaryto peace, rather than completely separate from it (Ruddick 1989, 137; Elshtain 1987, 253). Even those women who do characterizethemselves as pacifists may have radically diverse reasons for doing so, some of them drawing on just-war reasoning (see Cady 1989, chap. 4; Miller 1991, 104-05). Further, as Elshtain discusses, the notion of women's innate or natural orientation to peace and pacifism needs to be questioned as a product of a gender system that serves to maintain men as strong warriorsand women as weak and passive peacemakers, thereby perpetuating war rather than bringing peace. These factors suggest that a feminist appraisalof the just-wartheory is an importantcomponent of feminist theorizingabout war and peace.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 154 Hypatia

Only a few feminist scholarshave yet explicitly addressedjust-war theory. Nonetheless, there have been a few significant feminist critiques of various elements found in just-warthinking. Forexample, Elshtainand Ruddickhave both pointed to some specific deficiencies with traditionaljust-war thinking and have proposedalternative frameworksfor analyzingthe morality of war. In this article, I arguethat manyof the feministcriticisms that have been waged againsttraditional just-war theory are well taken.Notwithstanding the validity of these "deconstructive"efforts, however, to date no adequateconstructive feminist alternative has been proposed. Rather than reject and/or replace traditionaljust-war theory, I argue,feminist principles and insights can and should provide a much needed reconceptualizationand revitalizationof the applicationof just-warcriteria. I begin with a brief backgroundof just-wartheory, including three classic contrastingapproaches: those of Augustine, Reinhold Niebuhr,a mid-twenti- eth-century Protestanttheologian, and Michael Walzer,a contemporarysec- ular social and political theorist. Although by no means exhaustive of the complete spectrumof just-warideas, these three views do exemplify some of the more significant strands and influences, both theological and secular, historical and contemporary,of the tradition. I then discuss significant ways in which traditionaljust-war thinking is deficientfrom a feministperspective. I use Elshtain'sand Ruddick'salterative approachesto the moralityof war to illustratehow feministefforts to replacejust-war theory have been inadequatethus far.In the finalpart of the article,I outlinehow feministperspectives and insights can providea frameworkfor revitalizingthe applicationof just-wartheory.

THE JUST-WARTRADITION

The manyvariants of just-wartheory which have been developedover the past millenniumdiffer in the specificcriteria used to determinethe moralityof war (both in generaland in relationto particularconflicts), the burdenof evidence necessaryto satisfythose criteria,and the relation between criteriaand their relative weight.6Nonetheless, there is generalagreement that just-waranalysis entails two sets of criteria:one govering the moralityof goingto war (the jus ad bellum),the otherthe actualconduct ofwar (the jus in bello). There is alsosignificant agreementthat the jus ad bellumcriteria include some or all of the following: 1. a just cause (self-defenseor defense of others); 2. right authority(determination to go to war is made by the appropriate governing officials); 3. right intention (must be to reestablishpeace); 4. proportionality(between meansemployed in fightingand ends or goals to be achieved);

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 155

5. relative justice (in acknowledging that no participant in war has absolutejustice on their side); 6. last resort (all other alternatives for have been exhausted); and

7. a reasonablehope for success. There is also substantialconsensus that the jus in bellocriteria require: 1. "discrimination"between combatants and noncombatants and the permissibilityof intentionally killing only the former,thus according noncombatantsimmunity; and

2. "proportionality"of means and ends in relation to particularbattles and strategiessuch that the benefits of going to war or conduct of a particularstrategy or mission within the war must outweigh its harms. Because many of these criteria are quite vague and general in scope, their applicationhas resultedin significantlydifferent determinations regarding the morality of particularwars, including the recent Persian Gulf conflict (see Sizemore 1992; Johnson and Weigel 1992; Geyer and Green 1992; Decosse 1992). Augustine concluded that Christian participationin killing is permissible when: ( 1) the cause is just;(2) appropriateauthority (in his case, the monarch) determines that undertakingwar is necessaryto prevent or punish injustice; and (3) the intention is to restorepeace (see Hartigan1966, 199). In Niebuhr's view, justice-a moral good necessary for life in a sinful world-requires Christiansto participatein war to defend innocent victims of aggressionand securefreedom for the oppressed(Niebnhr and Dun 1955, 77). In contrast to these theological approaches,Walzer's secular theory pre- sumes that the defense of is the only legitimate reason for war (Walzer 1977, 72). His just-war approach makes the criteria of just cause central, and downplays the moral significance of the traditional criteria of proportionalityand last resort(Walzer 1982, 548), even though he admitsthat "everymilitary history is a tale of violence and destructionout of all relation to the requirements of combat" (Walzer 1977, 130). All three of these approachesare subject to significantfeminist criticisms.

FEMINISTCRITICISMS OF JUST-WAR THEORY

Feministcriticisms of just-wartheory are clusteredaround several concerns: its relation to realism;its failureto insist that all criteriahave been satisfiedin accordancewith rigorousstandards, especially in relation to attemptingnon- violent alternatives;its tendency to abstractionand to dichotomize reality in

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 156 Hypatia

accordancewith gendereddistinctions; and the priorityit accordsto the state and to state authority vis-a-vis the individual. I will evaluate each of these criticismsin turn. Realism.Realism is the political perspectivethat human nature makes war inevitable and unavoidable.Realism influencesjust-war thinking by creating a presumption that resort to war may be necessary.7Realist attitudes thus enhance the possibility that a just-waranalysis will result in the conclusion that the use of armedforce is justified.Augustine's and Niebuhr'stheologically based perspectivesare both realist in viewing war as a necessaryremedy for human sinfulness.8Although Walzerexplicitly intends his theory of human rights to provide an alternative to realism, he also tends to fall into realist modes of thought, evidenced by his failure to give more than cursoryand pessimisticconsideration to alternativesto war (see Walzer 1977, 329-35). Many feminist scholarshave criticizedthe realistelements of interational relations theory in general, and just-warthinking in particular(see Ruddick 1989, 1987, and 1983;Tickner 1991; Grant and Newland 1991). In Ruddick's view, the realistparadigm misrepresents human beings as "primarilycenters of dominating and defensive activity trying to achieve a stable autonomy in threatening hierarchies of strength" (Ruddick 1989, 183). Both she and Elshtain condemn realism'spessimism about human nature and blindness to the possibility of thinking in any terms other than war (Ruddick 1989, 136, 150; Elshtain 1985, 40-41).9 ForElshtain, traditional just-war theory is not problematicso much because it is itself realist as because it is anachronisticand no longer able to provide meaningfullimits to war in a worldgoverned by realist assumptions(Elshtain 1985, 47). Given the contemporaryconditions of war,which include changes in the nature of political bodies, international relations, and "the totalistic deadlinessof weapons" (Elshtain 1985, 46), just-wartheory continually gets co-opted by the realistparadigm (Elshtain 1987, 166-67). As an example, she cites Walzer'sreliance on viewing as an "immeasurableevil" to justify the overridingof in bellorestraints during the British saturationbombing of Germancities in WorldWar II. She also points out how he uses the threat of nuclear war to justify a continuing "supremeemergency" that legitimates the immoraluse of deterrencestrategy (Elshtain 1985, 46).l0 Ruddickand Elshtain'scriticisms accord with those of other feminist think- ers who challenge the realist view of human nature as a male notion about men (see Grant and Newland 1991; Grant 1991, 9; Tickner 1991). Elshtain specificallyattributes just-war theory's restriction of the rangeof "symbolicand narrativepossibilities" for thinking about conflict to realism's"suppression of female-linked imagery"(Elshtain 1987, 88; Elshtain 1985, 41). Whether or not one accepts such claims that prevailingconceptions of human nature are male-biased,or that women have differentnatures or roles (either culturally or biologically constructed), these feminist perspectivespersuasively suggest

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 157

that realismprovides an unduly limited view of human nature,one which can conceive of war as the only solution to conflict. Failureto ConsiderAlternatives to War.The "lastresort" criteria of just-war theory requiresthat meaningful alternativesto armed force have been tried and failed beforeresort to armedforce can be morallyjustified. But in line with their realist orientation, many just-wartheorists fail to consider alternatives to war fully (see Ruddick 1987; McMahon 1991). Augustine'sjust-war theory lacks any exhortation that non-violent methods of restoring peace be attempted prior to the use of armed force. Niebuhr'srealist and theological presuppositionsunderlie his conclusion that pacifismis not a feasible alterna- tive to armedforce. In his view, no form of pacifism is adequateto deal with human self-interest and the will to power (Niebuhr 1940, 5, 25; see Miller 1991, 107).11 Among contemporaryjust-war theorists, the last resort criterion is often ignored or viewed, as Walzerdoes, as a "prudential"matter to be left to the discretionof governmentofficials (see Tikkun1991). BecauseWalzer considers nonviolent resistanceto be dependent upon adherence to just-warprinciples by those with the means and the will to use violence, he gives only minimal considerationto pacifist alternativesto war.He is cynical about the effective- ness of nonviolent approachesto conflict resolution, arguing that they can only succeed if a number of preconditionsexist, including the willingness- always uncertain-of the aggressorto abide by the war convention (Walzer 1977,330-35). Where such preconditionsdo not exist, "collapses into violence directed at oneself" (Walzer1977, 332). The U.S. Catholic bishops are distinctive among contemporaryjust-war theorists in seriouslyconsidering the possibilityof nonviolent alternativesto war and the escalation of conflicts. Their statement in The Challengeof Peace includes proposalsfor a nuclearfreeze, weapons reductions, arms control, and political and economic policies to enhance human rights and dignity (NCCB 1983). In addition, the bishops consider peace to be a duty, not merely "an optional commitment" (136). They are thus more progressive than most just-wartheorists in having a vision that reaches towardpeace, and not just the next war.Yet Walzercriticizes the Catholic Bishopsfor their emphasison the requirement of last resort, claiming that it is "an endlessly receding possibility,invoked mostly by people who would prefernever to aggres- sion with force. After all, there is always something else to do, another diplomatic note, another meeting" (Walzer 1991, 14; see Tikkun1991, 40). Thus, despite his purportedopposition to realism,Walzer ultimately does not take the possibilityof alternativesto war any more seriouslythan Augustine or Niebuhr. Ruddick opposes this tendency among just-war theorists to reject the morality of as an alternative to war (Ruddick 1989, 174-75). Elshtain recognizesthat the lack of any enforcement mechanism to

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 158 Hypatia

insurethat contact and attemptsat negotiatedsettlement have been attempted before armed force may be utilized makes just-war theory subject to being manipulatedas a prop for the promotion of "armedcivic virtue"rather than as a constrainton war(Elshtain 1992, 43). The failureof mostjust-war theorists to seriouslycontemplate alternativesto waris thus radicallydeficient fromthe perspectiveof pacifist feminists and others opposed to a knee-jerkmilitaristic responseto civil strife. AbstractThought. The media and the military'sportrayal of the PersianGulf War-a conflict Walzerconcludes was a just war-as a video gameusing "smart bombs"to perform"precision" or "surgical"strikes against "strategictargets" rather than as the use of deadly weapons resultingin the bloody slaughterof thousandsof human beings, civilians as well as soldiers,illustrates the kind of abstractthinking aboutwar that feministsaccuse just-war theorists of engaging in (see Elshtain 1992; Sizemore 1992, 947). Just-wartheorists tend to couch their analyses in terms of hypotheticals rather than with reference to actual conflicts. For example, Niebuhr'swork deservesElshtain's criticism that just- wartheorists fail to provideeither specific,concrete guidelinesfor determining when war is moral or narrativesto illustratewhether past warshave been just or not (e.g., Elshtain 1987, 159, 248-49; Elshtain 1985, 50). In contrast with this tendency of prevailingjust-war approaches to ignore how the criteriawould applyto actualwars, a numberof feminist theoriesstress the importanceof the concrete and particularover the universaland abstract (see Gilligan 1882;Noddings 1984;Ruddick 1987,93-97; Ruddick1989,139). Feminist analyses specifically reveal how abstraction in the application of just-wartheory has resultedin: (1) a neglect of the horrorsof warand its effects on individual bodies; (2) a perception of the enemy as "Other";and (3) a fixation on principlesof justice and rightsrather than the needs and interests of specific persons in particularconflicts. Ruddick perceives the abstractnessof just-wartheory as controlling "our perceptionsof war,turning our attention frombodies and their fate to abstract causes and rules for achieving them" (Ruddick 1989, 150). Nancy Hartsock finds that the tendency to ignore actual bodies has been prevalent in milita- ristic thinking throughout the history of Western philosophical thought, despite the fact that warrioringis a bodily activity (see Hartsock 1982). For example, in Augustine'soverall theological perspective,the self and the body have only a relative and temporaryvalue as partsof earthlyexistence. The evil of warthus does not inhere in physicaldeath, which will befalleveryone sooner or later, but rather in vices such as "love of violence," "revengefulcruelty," and "lustfor power"(Holmes 1969, 64), desiresthat are antithetical to eternal life in the heavenly City of God (Augustine 1984, 877).12 Nonetheless, Elshtain finds in Augustine "an exemplary alternative" to modern just-wartheorists because he emphasizessuffering and regret rather than the abstract and rationalist tenor of modem approaches "that stress

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 159

legalities, rights, and the power of human reason"(Elshtain 1987, 129, 132). The "modem" attitude is illustrated by the "technostrategic"discourse of nuclear defense professionals.Carol Cohn describesthe "utterabsence of the burning,explosive, flesh-tearing,radiation poisoning, life-annihilatingdevas- tation of nuclear war" in their rhetoric (Cohn 1989b, 156). The absence of such descriptions results in an ability to abstract nuclear weapons from the horrible reality of suffering they have the capacity to cause, and to legitimate the neglect of human bodies and lives (Cohn 1989a, 119, 135; Cohn 1989b).13 Carol Gilligan suggeststhat this capacity for abstractionalso enables the denial of sufferingbecause it replaces actual lives with hypothetical people (Gilligan 1977, 511). Many feminists counter the inattention just-wartheo- ristsgive to the horrorsof warby emphasizingthe enormoussuffering of actual individualswhich war entails, not only duringactual hostilities (e.g. Ruddick 1989, 157) but also by the military-industrialcomplex that preparesfor and perpetuateswars (see, e.g., Chapkis1981,36; Reardon1985; Brock-Utne 1985; Stephenson 1986, 86). As a contrast to abstractjust-war thinking, Ruddick describesmaternal thinking as generating"a sturdy antimilitaristic conception of the body"in which birth is privilegedover death (Ruddick 1987, 216). Another feminist criticism of the abstract character of much just-war theorizing is its portrayal of hostile forces as a one-dimensionally evil "Other."'4As "Other," the opposition can be perceived as inferior and "killable"alien beings, ratherthan as other humanssharing similar needs and desires.Although Walzerrecognizes the role that this perceptionof the enemy as less than human plays in enhancing the willingnessof human beings to kill one another (see, e.g., Walzer 1977, 139-43), he fails to see the far-reaching implications of this for the possibility of negotiating alternatives to armed conflict, or for assessingthe moralityof particularconflicts. Along with other militaristthinking, Ruddickcondemns just-wartheory's dependence on a conception of" 'enemies' abstractenough to be killable" (Ruddick 1989, 150), a conception in which "humanbodies are subordinated to abstractcauses, [and]different bodies are organizedaround abstract labels of civilian or soldier, 'the enemy' or allyi us or them" (146). Moral theorist Nel Noddings considers this problem to be more prevalent among men than women, since females are socialized in a way which emphasizesrelationality and connection more than separation and autonomy (Noddings 1989, 202). A third aspect of abstraction that has troubled feminists about just-war thinking is its privileging of abstractconcepts of rights and justice over and above those of love and caring (e.g., Gilligan 1982; Noddings 1984). For Augustine, war is just when necessaryto counter injustice and restorepeace, regardlessof the relative equities in the conflict (Augustine 1984, 862). For Walzer,going to war is only justifiedin orderto defendrights to life and liberty

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 160 Hypatia

(Walzer1977, 135). And in the normalcourse, the practiceof war is just only when it does not violate human rights (135). Elshtain specifically criticizes Walzer'stheory of rights as a foundationfor determiningthe moralityof war, contending that the applicationof a rights-basedapproach to the bombingsof Hiroshimais "impoverished"and "inadequateto describewhat happened on those dreadfuldays" (Elshtain 1985, 47).15 Many feminists reject such an emphasison rights and justice as relying on male-derivedand biased conceptions that fail to accord with the way human beings are actually constituted (e.g., Shanley 1983, 360; Shaughnessy 1988, 11). Feministlegal theoristJoan Shaughnessyargues that a focuson rightsfails "to recognizethat people do not exist in isolation,but ratherwithin a complex, imperfect social structure"(Shaughnessy 1988, 12). According to Gilligan, moral theories based on individual rights and justice promote relations of separationrather than connection. Separationis more likely to lead to alien- ation, and ultimatelyto war,since the originsof aggressivenesslie in the failure of connection. In her view, whereas"male" approaches are basedon rightsand justice, "female"approaches proceed on the basis of nonviolence (Gilligan 1982, 173-74). Again, even if one does not accept the genderedaspects of these criticisms, they nonetheless suggest that the tendency to abstract thinking among just-wartheorists makes the resortto armedforce more likely. DichotomizedThinking. Although not in the criteriathemselves, the appli- cation ofjust-wartheory reflects a dualistichierarchy of valuesprivileging male over female, the "spiritual"over the "earthly,"and the "State" over the "Individual."This dualism is readily evident in Augustine's validation of practicesin the earthlysphere which he condemns in the heavenly (including war), on the basis that these spheres constitute "two cities" governed by differentsets of laws (see Augustine 1984, 877-78). Like Augustine, Niebuhr privileges the individual'srelationship with an abstract, transcendent God over relationshipswith other persons.Noddings characterizesthis tendency as fostering separation and lack of connection between persons (see Noddings 1989, 200-201, 204). Feminists have also arguedthat such dualism privileges abstractspiritual conceptions over practicalearthly ones, and devalues the significanceof "this world"and its inhabitants (see, e.g., McFague 1987). Ruddick, for example, believes that the tendency to abstraction in just-war theory is fueled by Christianity'seschatological focus, which separatesthe "inner"spiritual life from the "outer"material one (Ruddick 1989, 134-36). Elshtain also objects to the dualismsof "good and evil" and "just and unjust"in official just-war rhetoric, which she claims is unable to restrainjudges from becoming execu- tioners under conditions of total war (Elshtain 1987, 157). One of Elshtain'smain criticismsof just-wartheory is its dualisticdiscourse of gender, which designates women as "beautifulsouls" in opposition to the just Christian (male) warrior(Elshtain 1985, 45). This genderedsplit operates

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 161

to constitute women as "civiccheerleaders", a "collective Other"in opposition to which men can be virilized as warriors(Elshtain 1985, 42-43). This split continues to operate in contemporaryjust-war theory, including that of the U.S. Catholic Bishops (see Segers 1985, 642). Elshtain also criticizesthe way just-wartheory dichotomizeswar and peace because it leads to a conception of peace as simply the absence of war rather than a "chastenedpatriotism" which would restrainthinking in waristterms. As Cohn notes, such attitudes about peace tend to confirm rather than belie the warist presumptionthat peace is "soft-headed"(Cohn 1989b, 128). Relationshipof the Individualto Authority.One hierarchalizeddichotomy in particularthat all three just-wartheories discussed here reflect is a privileging of the state over the individual, which justifies allowing the innocent to die for the "socialgood." Both Augustine and Niebuhr place a premiumon social orderand political stability.For Augustine, this counsels passive obedience to secularauthority (Augustine 1984, 870). ForNiebuhr, social ordermay some- times outweigh the obligation to pursuejustice, because "contemporarywar placesso manymoral values in incalculablejeopardy" (Niebuhr and Dun 1955, 78; Niebuhr 1956, 44). Although Walzerpurports to give primacyto individual rights, there is a tension in his just-wartheory between the rights of individualsand the rights of community. State's rights-to territorial integrity and political sover- eignty-can sometimes legitimately override individual rights in defense of communities (Walzer 1977, 253). His theory allows an exception to the ordinary protection of individual rights for cases of "supremeemergency," when an imminent grave emergencyto one's own people exists, as well as in the case of individual soldiers,who, Walzerargues, give up their rights when they enlist or agree to be conscripted. The privileging of authorityin just-wartheory also increases the risk that individualswill be viewed only instrumentally,as means sacrificedto the end of the state'swinning the war (see Davis 1987, 475). This is especiallyevident in Augustine'sview that the decision to undertakewar is one for the monarch, not the individual soldier. Civil disobedience and selective conscientious objection are illegitimate (see Langan 1984, 31). Similarly,in Walzer'sview, since soldierslose their human rights"simply by fighting"(Walzer 1977, 136), soldiersare a kind of "other"who can be freelysacrificed. This objectification makesit easierto justifytaking the lives of soldiers,whether throughwholesale slaughterof enemy troops, or the use of large numbersof one's own soldiers sacrificedkamikaze style, and may actuallyrisk the expansion and escalation of hostilities. Feminists are critical of such privileging of the state. Ruddick criticizes just-war's"unquestioning obedience as a virtue" (Ruddick 1989, 114). Simi- larly,Elshtain proposesthat the discourseof "armedcivic virtue"dominating just-war thinking needs to be replaced with a "politicized"discourse that

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 162 Hypatia

"questionsand is suspiciousof authority"(Elshtain 1987, 258). Feministshave noted that conservativeattitudes advocating maintenance of the statusquo- evident in much traditionaljust-war thinking-are often used to perpetuate unequalsocial relations,especially in respect to women and racial minorities. Further,some feminist moraltheories are founded on interpersonalrelations between individuals,suggesting a greaterconcern for individualwelfare than for social order and stability. In Noddings's theory of caring, for example, responsibilities to close relatives are primary,followed by an expanding, lessening degree of obligation toward those who are related less directly, through "circles and chains of caring" (see Noddings 1984; Gilligan 1982). These feminist critiquessuggest that just-wartheory's general emphasis on the good of the social orderat the expense of individualsis misplaced. These criticismsof just-wartheory demonstratethat it does not provide a satisfactorymethod for determiningthe moralityof warfor many feminists,at least as it has been appliedtraditionally. Yet, as the followingdiscussion reveals, feminist effortsto provide alternativeapproaches are also inadequate.

FEMINISTALTERNATIVES TO JUST-WARTHEORY

To date, there have been two notable nonpacifist feminist alternatives to just-wartheory: Elshtain's proposed "revitalized civic discourse"and Ruddick's "maternal peace politics." Elshtain proposes to reduce armed conflict by eliminating the paradigmof "armedcivic virtue" that underlies realist and just-warapproaches. This involves "devirilizing"war discourse(e.g., Elshtain 1985, 55) and retrieving "female-linkedimagery." It requiresformulating an alternative discourse which can "problematizewar narratives"and move beyond"the grandnarrative of armedcivic virtue"(Elshtain 1987, 251 ),16with its gendered dichotomy of males as warriorsand females as noncombatant peacemakers (Elshtain 1985, 50). In Elshtain'sestimation, this would give "men and women the opportunity to share risks as citizens, to take up nonviolence as a choice, not a given" (Elshtain 1987, 257). It is not evident how Elshtain'sproposed "revitalized civic discourse"would be an improvementon just-wardecision-making about the morality of U.S. involvement in recent conflicts. Women'sexemplary military performance in the Gulf Warcertainly broke down many traditionalgender stereotypes about women's ability to performas soldiersunder combat conditions, thus under- mining the paradigmof armedcivic virtue as an exclusively male domain. Yet breakingdown this genderdichotomy does not seem to have alteredthe macho attitudes that led to U.S. involvement in the Gulf, or resulted in the indis- criminatekilling of retreatingIraqi soldiers. Nor has it led to an enhanced role for women in policy-making on more recent conflicts, such as the war in Bosnia.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 163

Thus, in the end, Elshtain'sown proposal fails at the level of effecting practicaldecision-making. In addition,Elshtain fails to specifyclearly how she would amend, supplement, or replace just-wartheory, given her recognition that both just-wartheory and realismhave limited usefulness(Elshtain 1987, 248-49). Indeed, in her more recent work, she seems to embrace traditional just-wartheory more completely and uncriticallythan earlier(cf., e.g., Elshtain 1991b, 134, with Elshtain 1987), offeringit as a necessaryantidote to the lack of in-depth moral theorizingabout war by feminists. Ruddick acknowledgesthat just cause for war may exist and some battles may be necessary, but she contends that "there are entirely or principally nonviolent ways of fighting them that are at least as effective as violence" (Ruddick 1983, 475-76). Ruddick'sproposed alternative to just-wartheory is a "materal politics of peace"based on "maternalthinking." Maternal think- ing is constituted by the virtues of "maternalpractice": preservative love, fostering nurturance, and training and its latent peacefulness (Ruddick 1989, 40-56, 137).17 It requires that "peacemakersmust invent myriadnonviolent actions and then name, describeand supportthem" (139), includingnonviolent resistance(174-75). It also requiresan ongoing attention to human suffering(157). There are a numberof fundamentalproblems with Ruddick'sproposal. First, although it avoids the realist trap of undue pessimismabout human nature, it tends to fall into the opposite extreme of idealistically depicting mothers as basicallycaring towardtheir offspring,selflessly caring more for their children than for themselves, and presuming that nonmothers have similar caring capacities. Second, although she denies that her theory of maternalthinking is based on essentialist conceptions about women's biological natures (see Ruddick 1989, 40-41, 157), her argument that women are more suited to promote peace than are men tends in this direction by resting on women's capacityfor, and experience of, being mothers (see Code 1991, 91-93). Ruddick'sviews tend to replicate the essentialist and dichotomizingtend- encies in the work of "cultural"or "difference"feminists, who argue that relations of caring for others give women a "differentmoral voice" (e.g., Gilligan 1982; Noddings 1984). Ruddick assertsthat such differencesmake females "naturally"more oriented to peace than war.Dichotomizing tenden- cies that Ruddickcondemns in traditionaljust-war theory appearin her own contention that maternalpractice promisesdistinctive resourcesfor nonvio- lent alternativesto war becauseof the "primafacie opposition between mater- nal and military work," that "motheringbegins in birth and promises life" whereas "militarythinking is characterizedby its justification of organized, deliberate death" (Ruddick 1987, 247; Ruddick 1989, 148).18 Elshtain is critical of this type of move to "devirilizemale discourse"by replacingit with a "feminized"one, arguingthat "bothembody dangerous distortions" (Elshtain 1987, 258).

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 164 Hypatia

Third, Ruddick's approach fails to develop its implications fully or in concrete terms and thereby demonstrateits feasibility.Her theory remainsas abstractas the just-wartradition that she rejects. Her most specific claim is that "the practiceof motheringtaken as a whole" contributesto peace politics the qualities of attentiveness, realism and a positive attitude toward change (Ruddick1989, 220). Contraryto her own theoreticalprinciples, however, she fails to provide concrete, particular,non-abstract examples of when or how this nonviolent approachhas or could succeed. She generallyfails to provide an adequate connection between the private sphere of maternal practices involving relationships with one's own children and the public sphere of international relations between antagonistic, and often culturally alien, nation-states (Ruddick 1987, 57, 178, 254; see also Code 1991, 92-93). Ruddick'sproposed "maternalpeace politics" also proves deficient when appliedto the real life experienceof the Bosnianconflict. When formerfriends and neighborswho lived togetherpeacefully for yearsturn to rape and kill one another based on ethnic and religiousdifferences, it is difficult to see how a "practiceof mothering"could resolvethe conflict. Nor can Ruddick'sidealistic optimism about the power of maternalthinking to avert violent methods of resolving conflicts be viewed as reasonablein the light of some of the U.S.'s past militaryinterventions, including the two WorldWars. This discussionsuggests that neither Ruddicknor Elshtain have developed an alternative to just-war thinking which remedies the deficiencies in the tradition without contributing new problems.Ruddick and Elshtain do not hold an exclusive claim on feminist alternativesto traditionaljust-war theory. Nonetheless, the deficiencies in their attempts to replace traditionalcriteria suggest that the way to deal with traditional approaches may not be to eliminate them but to revise how they are applied.

A FEMINISTREVITALIZATION OFJUST-WAR THEORY

The feminist criticismsdiscussed do not suggesta need to develop radically new or different criteria for assessingthe morality of engagement in armed conflict fromthose offeredby traditionaljust-war theory. Rather, they aremore focused on altering the way the traditional criteria have been applied in specific situations. To that end, feminist criticisms and counterproposals suggesta numberof specific proposalsfor modifyingthe practicemore than the theoryof the just-warapproach to armedconflict. These proposalsare based on the positive dimensionsof the just-warcriteria already discussed rather than representingcompletely novel approaches. As an initial matter,feminist criticismssuggest that just-wartheory should not be premised on realist assumptions.This includes theologically derived conceptions of original sin and analogouslypessimistic secular appraisalsof human nature. Such negative conceptions tend to squelch consideration of

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 165

alternativesto war. However, unduly idealistic appraisalsof human (particu- larlyfemale) natureby some feministssuch as Noddings and Ruddickare also inaccurateand unproductive.Prudence dictates that the long historyand habit of human war-makingmust not be forgotteneither. Such a reconceptualizedunderstanding of humannature would have at least two desirableconsequences for just-wartheory. Including females as well as males in "humannature" (see Tickner 1991, 37; Ruddick 1989;Elshtain 1987) would enable just-wartheorists to considerthe nonviolent historicalpractices and sentiments of women, leading to an understandingwhich would assume neither that the natureof human beings makeswar inevitable nor completely unnecessary.In addition,such a revisedunderstanding of humannature would permit greateropportunities for attemptingnonviolent alternativesto armed conflict, without precludingconsideration of the possibilitythat resortto war might be necessary. A second majorimplication of feminist criticismsis that just-wartheorists shouldpay moreserious attention to pacifistarguments. As Cadyhas suggested, pacifism and just-warthinking are not radicallyopposed, but representtwo differentpositions along the same continuum (Cady 1989, 35-37). The influ- ence of pacifist perspectiveswould strengthen application of several just-war criteria.First, it would make "lastresort" more significant in just-wardeliber- ations, resulting in a greatereffort to exhaust all reasonablyeffective alterna- tives to the use of armed force. Given their insistence on attending to the sufferingof particularothers, feminist applicationsof "lastresort" might result in interpreting the preferabilityof alternatives to war in accordance with whether they result in less harm to the innocent (see McMahon 1991). The emphasis on collaboration in much feminist theory could also be creatively applied to the development of new international or multinational frameworksfor assessingif and when resortto armedforce is morallynecessary. However,these alternativesmust be consideredwith an awarenessof Walzer's admonition that the "lastresort" may never be reached,since somealternative always remains theoretically available, thus effectively making this criteria function to transformjust-war theory into a form of pacifism. A just-war theory chastened by pacifist influences would also involve strengthening the force accorded to the "proportionality"and "reasonable hope for success" requirements.This would entail replacing abstract and dualisticthinking with a more casuisticalattention to context and particular- ity, what Elshtain characterizesas "the living textures within which limited human beings think and act" (Elshtain 1987, 189). As Alan Geyer recognizes, the U.S.'s involvement in the PersianGulf War "no longer looks so justifiable once one begins examining in detail whether the facts warranted"the conclu- sion to go to war (Geyer 1991, 135). In keeping with feminist concerns with bodies and individual suffering, application of "proportionality"and "reasonablehope for success" would

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 166 Hypatia

requirea more comprehensiveexamination of the potential long-termconse- quences of contemplated intervention. Such considerationsshould highlight the impact on civilians. This includes not only their survival, but also the qualityof their lives and relationships,particularly if the environment and/or vital links to food, water,and basic services are damagedor destroyedduring the conflict. It also requiresan assessmentof the long-termprospects for peace and security in the surroundingregion. As Elshtain and others have pointed out, just-warprinciples were heedlesslybandied about duringthe Gulf War to provide a justificationfor U.S. involvement, without carefulattention to the many areasof uncertaintyand ambiguitythat existed (Elshtain 1992, 42). A morenuanced approachto just-wartheory would also give more attention to the requirementsof "rightintention" and "relativejustice" than has been done in the past. Niebuhr's caution against self-righteousnessis echoed by Ruddick'srecognition that "beingon the side of the good can fostera repressive self-righteousnessthat legitimateskilling or, alternatively,condemns violence without attending to the despair and abuse from which it arises"(Ruddick 1989, 135). Elshtain similarly predicts that our "warlikeway of thinking" cannot be altered until we abandon "grandteleologies of historical winners and losers,""triumphalist accounts of ourvictories," and "absolutemoralisms" as part of our identities (Elshtain 1987, 256). Feminist concern for relation- ships could help temper these tendencies in just-warthinking. In addition, feminist calls for a more particularized,contextualized, and individualizedapproach to warwould involve a breakdown(or at least a radical reconfiguration)of the dichotomies between male and female, combatantand noncombatant, soldier and citizen, ally and enemy, and state and individual which have dominated just-warthinking. Rather than relying on traditional dichotomies, a feminist application of just-warcriteria should emphasizethe effects of going to war on the lives of the particularindividuals who would be involved, whether soldier or civilian, enemy or ally, male or female. A feminist applicationof just-warcriteria in a situation like that of Bosnia, for example, would require military strategiststo focus more closely on the relations between the warringfactions than has been the case. Rather than concluding simply that intervention is inappropriatebecause none of the participantsis completely innocent, a feminist analysisof the conflict would examine the relative equities of the parties,the balance of power, the history and cultures of the region, the specific conduct of each of the parties which led to and has maintained hostilities, the degree to which each party has complied with the war convention, including its treatment of innocent civil- ians, the prospectsfor a long-termsettlement of hostilities through the use of armed intervention, the environmental impact of such intervention on the region, and so on. In particular,a feminist appraisalwould consider the rape of Bosnian Muslimwomen by Serbianmen as a seriouswar crime rivalingthat of deliberately injuring or killing innocent civilians. Such a fine-grained

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 167

analysisand attention to human sufferingwould likely result in a determina- tion that armed intervention, or at least additional military supportfor the Bosnian Muslims would be morally justified, despite a sturdy presumption againstviolence. Finally, a feminist approachto just-wartheory would entail reformulated understandingsof the properrelationship between the individualand the state. It would consider both the impact of war on individuals as well as the obligationsof both men and women to defend the nation. It should provide a formulationwith which the meritsof a particularmilitary engagement may be assessedby the individual soldiersand civilians involved in it as well by the relevant "authorities."In keeping with Elshtain'scriticisms, it would include a reassessmentof women'sexemption frommilitary combat and draftregistra- tion, as well as established laws governing conscientious objection and civil disobedience.

CONCLUSION

Feministcritiques have providedimportant challenges to several aspectsof traditional just-war theory. The discussion of the just-war approaches of Augustine,Niebuhr, and Walzerfrom a feministperspective reveals how weak and limited this tradition'svision of alternativesto waroften is, how distorted by realist and gender-biasedassumptions, how abstract and life-denying its applicationcan be. Yet, despite proficiencyat pinpointing a numberof signif- icant problemswith traditionaljust-war thinking, prominentfeminist alterna- tives proposedto date are themselves deficient in a numberof respects. In addition,feminist criticisms and alternativesdo not indicate any inherent deficiencies in the just-warcriteria themselves. They focus on the underlying assumptionsand problematic application of the theory, not the validity or appropriatenessof the criteria. Feminist principles suggest several ways in which traditionalapproaches to just-wartheorizing can be improved,leading to a more careful and consideredappraisal of when the use of armedforce is morallyjustified. Unless or until a feasiblefeminist alternativeto the just-war criteria is developed, feminists should work to revitalize, rather than under- mine, this long-standingapproach to the moralityof war.

NOTES

In additionto thankingthis volume'seditors, Duane Cady, Karen Warren, and copy editorTeresa Jesionowski, the authorwould like to thank the IndianaCenter for Global Peaceand World Change for my funding as a MacArthurScholar (1991-92); the Center's director,John Lovell,my ProjectAdvisor, D'Ann Campbell, and fellowMacArthur

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 168 Hypatia

Scholars, especially Todd Sullivan; doctoral advisorRichard B. Miller; and colleague JasonBeduhn for many helpfulcomments and suggestions. 1. By "feminist,"I generallymean a criticalperspective on the patriarchaland sexist dimensionsof society orientedto improvingthe statusof women. 2. These variousperspectives on war can be conceptualizedas located on a single continuum runningfrom absolutepacifism on one side, throughwarism on the other, with variousforms of pacifism,just-warism, and warrealism aligned next to one another in between (Cady 1989, 35-37). 3. The associationof women with peace and peace-movementsis a long-standing one, extending backas faras the classicalGreeks and Romans.See, e.g., Elshtain(1987, 139); Berkman(1990); Costin (1983). Many women'sgroups organizedin the early twentieth century had peace as a significant aspect of their agendas, including the Women'sPeace Union and the Women'sInternational League for Peace and Freedom (WILPF).In recentdecades, women have continuedto take the lead in mobilizingpeace organizationsworldwide. See Alonso (1993); Swerdlow(1989); Hunter (1991); Howes (1993); Reardon(1985, 86-87, 181). 4. Polls taken in relationto U.S. involvementin the PersianGulf Warindicate that this gap appearsto be growing. In December, 1990, men were about equally divided regardingwhether the United Statesshould attack Iraq, whereas women opposed military action by 73 percent to 22 percent.Women similarlyopposed surgical air strikesby 63 percent to 29 percent. Researchindicates that men in many westerncountries tolerate aggressivestands on internationaland domesticpublic policy issuesmore readily than do women (Brock-Utne 1985, 33). 5. Cadypoints out that pacifismis sometimesrejected because it is wronglyidentified as "passivism,"a passiveand inactive responseto aggression(Cady 1989, 11-12). Some women may reject pacifismbased on the official views of a cultural,social or religious group,as wasthe case with the NationalCouncil of CatholicWomen's support for just-war doctrinebetween the two worldwars (MacCarthy 1978, 27). Other womenhave rejected pacifismon realistgrounds (Elshtain 1985, 42). 6. Just-warprinciples are describedand analyzedby a numberof just war theorists, notablyin recent yearsby PaulRamsey (1968), MichaelWalzer (1977), William O'Brien (1981), JamesTurner Johnson (1981, xxii), and RichardMiller (1991, 13-15). 7. Duane Cady characterizesthis presumptionas "warism,"which he describesas leading to the abuse of certain just-warcriteria, especially the in bello principles of discriminationand proportionality(Cady 1989, 66-69). 8. ForAugustine, war is both the consequenceof sin as well as a remedyfor sin (see Miller 1991, 21). ForNiebuhr, war is a necessary"lesser of two evils" in a sinful world,a realitythat cannot be eradicatedin the earthlyrealm, "a world in which egoism,collective and individual,will never be completelyovercome" (Niebuhr 1933, 257). Niebuhrthus rejects,as contraryboth to the New Testamentand experience, views of "rationalists" who believe in the essentialgood of humanbeings (Niebuhr 1940, 6). 9. RichardMiller also criticizesthe tendencyof just-wartheory to consideronly war and not peace (Miller 1991, 122). 10. Despite Elshtain'srejection of the pacifistlabel, this criticismaccords with the view of technologicalor nuclearpacifists, who rejectthe notion of limitedwar as feasible in the light of the destructivepotential of moder weaponry(see Cady 1989, chap. 4). 11. Their exclusive focus on the individualethic of the love commandmentignores the sociopoliticalduty to promotejustice and is sociallyirresponsible (Niebuhr 1956,31; 76). Niebuhrcriticizes pacifism based on nonviolent resistanceof the sort advocatedby

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 169

Gandhi and Martin LutherKing, Jr.as a biblicallyheretical and disingenuouseffort to foundon love whatactually amounts to powerpolitics involving coercion (Niebuhr1940, 10-11). However,Niebuhr does validatenonresistant pacifism of sectarianperfectionists as providingan importantmoral voice that may temperthe tendencies of militariststo allow justice to eclipse love (Niebuhr 1940, 5, 25; see Miller 1991, 107). 12. In the City of God, "therewill be no animalbody to 'weighdown the soul' in its processof corruption;there will be a spiritualbody with no cravings"(Augustine 1984, 878). 13. Ruddickconsiders such technostrategicrationality as "onlyan extension, albeit a stunning one, of the abstractnessthat characterizesmilitary discourseas a whole" (Ruddick1989, 146). 14. Miller also discussesthis view in just-wartheory (1991, 59, 71, 235). Noddings suggeststhat this ability to constructkillable enemies resultsfrom our projectionof evil onto others without seeing how we are implicated(Noddings 1989, 193-99). Elshtain similarlyargues that both realismand pacifism promote polarizing "masculine" tendencies that deny the violence inside ourselvesand project it outwardonto "the Other"(1985, 51). 15. Not all of Walzer'sjust-war thinking is similarlyabstract and universalizing, however. He recognizesthat the rules of war are not universallyapplicable because moralityis alwaysconnected to a culture'stradition and history. Moral rules are necessarily shapedby referenceto that community'sparticular, concrete experienceof war (Walzer 1977, 24). However,this moreparticularist aspect of Walzerremains in tension with the centralityhe accordsto individualrights founded on abstractand generalizednotions of justice. 16. Carol Cohn also turns to discourseas a way of destabilizingand interrupting prevailingapproaches to war,claiming that deconstructionprovides an importantmeans of challenging the hegemony of strategicdiscourse as "the only legitimatelanguage for publiclydiscussing nuclear policy" (Cohn 1989a, 137;see Cohn 1989b, 154-55). 17. In Ruddick'sdefinition, motheringis not exclusive to women but includesany personwho is responsiblefor and significantlyinvolved in caringfor the lives of children (Ruddick1989, 40). 18. In this regard,Ruddick tends to slide from a recognition that the traditional identificationof women with peace is a myth to an unsupportedassertion that "women's distinctive peacefulness"has the potential to become "a reliable resourcefor peace" (Ruddick1983, 479).

REFERENCES

Alonso, Harriet. 1993. Peaceas a women'sissue: A historyof the UnitedStates movement for worldpeace and women's rights. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press. Augustine. 1984. City of God.Trans. Henry Bettenson. London: Penquin Books. Baxter,Sandra, and MarjorieLansing, ed. 1983. Womenand politics: The visiblemajority. Ann Arbor:University of MichiganPress. Berkman,Joyce. 1990. Feminism,war, and peace politics:The case of WorldWar I. In Women,militarism and war: Essays in history,politics and social theory, ed. Jean Bethke Elshtainand Sheila Tobias.Savage, Md.: Rowman & LittlefieldPublishers, Inc.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 170 Hypatia

Branscombe,Nyla and SusanOwen. 1993. Gun ownershipamong American women and its consequencesfor social judgment.In Womenand theuse of force.See Howes. Brock-Utne,Birgit, 1985. Educatingforpeace: A feministperspective. New York:Pergamon Press. Brock-Utne,Birgit, Julianne Traylor, and Aas Solveign, eds. 1986. Womenand Peace:A reportfrom a conference.Oslo: InternationalPeace ResearchInstitute. Cady, Duane. 1989. Fromwarism to pacifism:A moralcontinuum. Philadelpha: Temple UniversityPress. Chapkis,Wendy, ed. 1981. Loadedquestions: Women in themilitary. Amsterdam: Transna- tional Press. Code, Lorraine.1991. Review essay:Will the 'good enough' feministsplease stand up? SocialTheory and Practice 17(10): 85-104. Cohn, Carol. 1989a. Sex and death in the rational world of defense intellectuals.In Feministtheory in practiceand process, ed. Micheline Malson,Jean O'Barr, and Susan Westphal-Wihl.Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1989b. EmasculatingAmerica's linguistic deterrent. In Rockingthe ship of state: Towarda feministpeace politics, ed. Adrienne Harrisand YnestraKing. Boulder: WestviewPress. Costin, Lela. 1983. Feminism,pacifism, nationalism, and the Decadefor Women. In Womenand men's wars, ed. JudithStiehm. Oxford:Pergamon Press. Davis, G. Scott. 1987. Warcraftand the fragilityof virtue. Soundings70: 475-93. DeCosse, David, ed. 1992. But was it just?Reflections on themorality of the PersianGulf War.New York:Doubleday. Elshtain,Jean Bethke. 1985. Reflectionson warand politicaldiscourse: Realism, just war, and feminismin a nuclearage. PoliticalTheory 13(1): 39-57. . 1987. Womenand war. New York:Basic Books. .1991a. Feminismand war.Progressive 55(9): 14-16. .1991b. Ethics in the women'smovement. Annalsof the AmericanAcademy of Politicaland Social Science 515: 126-39. . 1992. Justwar and Americanpolitics. ChristianCentury 109(2): 41-44. Gallagher,Nancy. 1993. The gendergap in popularattitudes toward the use of force. In Womenand theuse offorce.See Howes. Geyer,Alan. 1991. Justwar and the burdensof history.Christian Century 108(5): 134-35. Geyer, Alan, and BarbaraGreen. 1992. Lies in the sand:Justice and the Gulf War.New York:Westminster/John Knox. Gilligan, Carol. 1977. Concept of the self and of morality.Harvard Educational Review 47(4): 481-517. .1982. In a differentvoice: Psychological theory and women's development. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Grant, Rebecca. 1991. The sourcesof gender bias in internationalrelations theory.In Genderand internationalrelations. See Grantand Newland. Grant, Rebecca and Rebecca Newland. 1991. Genderand internationalrelations. Bloom- ington: IndianaUniversity. Hartigan, Richard. 1966. Saint Augustine on war and killing: The problem of the innocent. Journalof theHistory of Ideas27(2): 195-204. Hartsock,Nancy. 1982. Prologueto a feminist critiqueof war and politics. In Women's viewsof thepolitical world of men,ed. JudithStiehm. DobbsFerry, N.Y.: Transnational Publishers,Inc. Holmes, Arthur,ed. 1969. Warand Christian ethics. Grand Rapids, MI: BakerBooks.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LucindaJ. Peach 171

Howes,Ruth and Stevenson,Michael, ed. 1993.Women and the use offorce. Boulder, CO: LynneReinner Publishers. Hunter,Anne E., ed. 1991. Genesand gender VI: On peace, war, andgender: A challenge to geneticexplanations. New York:Feminist Press. Johnson,James Turner. 1981.Just war tradition and the restraint of war: A moraland historical inquiry.Princeton: Princeton University Press. Johnson,James Turner, and GeorgeWeigel. 1992.Justwar and the Gulf War. Washington, D.C.: Ethics and PublicPolicy Center. Kehoe, Alice. 1986. Christianityand war.In Peaceand war: Cross-culturalperspectives, ed. M. L. Fosterand RichardRubenstein. New Brunswick,CT: Transaction Books. Langan,John. 1984. The elements of St. Augustine'sjust war theory.Journal of Religious Ethics12(1): 19-38. MacCarthy,Esther. 1978. Catholic women and war:The National Council of Catholic Women, 1919-1946. Peaceand Change 5(1): 23-32. McFague,Sallie. 1987. Modelsof god.Philadelphia: Fortress Press. McMahon,Jeff. 1991. The Gulf War and the traditionaltheory of the just war.Paper presentedat IndianaUniversity, Bloomington, October 1991. Miller,Richard B. 1991. Interpretationsof conflict: Ethics, pacifism and the just-war tradition. Chicago:University of Chicago Press. National Conferenceof Catholic Bishops(NCCB). 1983. The challengeof peace:God's promiseand our response.Washington, D.C.: Catholic Conference, Inc. Niebuhr,Reinhold. 1932. MustWe Do Nothing?Christian Century (March 30): 415-17. .1933. Why I leave the EO.R. ChristianCentury (January 3): 254-59. .1940. Why the ChristianChurch is not pacifist.In Christianityand power politics. New York:Charles Scribner's Sons. . 1956. An interpretationof Christianethics. Cleveland: Meridian Books. Niebuhr,Reinhold, and Angus Dun. 1955. God wills both justiceand peace. Christianity andCrisis 15(June 13): 75-78. Noddings,Nel. 1984. Caring:A feminineapproach to ethicsand moral education. Berkeley: Universityof CaliforniaPress. .1989. Womenand evil. Berkeley:University of CaliforniaPress. O'Brien,William. 1981. Theconduct ofjust and limited war. New York:Praeger Publishers. Pierson,Ruth Roach. 1988. "They'restill women after all":Wartime jitters over femi- ninity. In Womenand the militarysystem, ed. Eva Isaksson.New York:St. Martins Press. Ramsey,Paul. 1968. The just war: Forceand politicalresponsibility. New York:Charles Scribner'sSons. Reardon,Betty. 1985. Womenand thewar system. New York:Teachers College Press. Ruddick,Sarah. 1983. Pacifyingthe forces:Drafting women in the interestsof peace. Signs8(3): 471-89. . 1987. Remarkson the sexualpolitics of reason.In Womenand Moral Theory, ed. Eva Kittay and Diana Meyers. Stonybrook, New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers,Inc. . 1989. Maternalthinking: Towards a politicsof peace.Boston: Beacon Press. Segers,Mary. 1985. The Catholic bishops'pastoral letter on war and peace:A feminist perspective.Feminist Studies 11(3): 619-47. Shanley, Mary. 1983. Afterword:Feminism and families in a liberalpolity. In Families, politicsand public policy, ed. IreneDiamond and MaryShanley. New York:Longman.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 172 Hypatia

Shaughnessy,Joan. 1988. Gilligan'stravels. Law and Inequality7: 1-27. Sizemore,Russell. 1992. Reflectionson the GulfWar. Christian Century 109(30): 945-47. Stephenson, Carolyn. 1986. Pacifismand the roots of feminism in the United States, 1830-1930:individual linkages. In Womenand peace. See Brock-Utne 1986. Swerdlow,Amy. 1989. Women strike for peace. In Rockingthe shipof state: Towarda feministpeace politics. See Harrisand King. Tickner,J. Ann. 1991. Hans Morgenthau'sprinciples of political realism:A feminist reformulation.In Genderand international relations. See Grant and Newland 1991. Tikkuneditors. 1991. On justwars: An interviewwith MichaelWalzer. Tikkun 6(1 ): 40-42. Walzer,Michael. 1977.Just and unjustwars. New York:Basic Books, Inc. .1982. Responseto Lackey.Ethics 92: 547-48. 1991. Perplexed.New Republic(January 28): 13-15. Washburn,Patricia. 1993. Women in the .In Womenand the use offorce. See Howes.

This content downloaded on Tue, 22 Jan 2013 13:58:12 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions