Statistical Mechanics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Statistical Mechanics Statistical Mechanics Henri J.F. Jansen Department of Physics Oregon State University October 12, 2008 II Contents 1 Foundation of statistical mechanics. 1 1.1 Introduction. 1 1.2 Program of statistical mechanics. 4 1.3 States of a system. 5 1.4 Averages. 10 1.5 Thermal equilibrium. 14 1.6 Entropy and temperature. 16 1.7 Laws of thermodynamics. 19 1.8 Problems for chapter 1 . 20 2 The canonical ensemble 23 2.1 Introduction. 23 2.2 Energy and entropy and temperature. 26 2.3 Work and pressure. 28 2.4 Helmholtz free energy. 31 2.5 Changes in variables. 32 2.6 Properties of the Helmholtz free energy. 33 2.7 Energy fluctuations. 35 2.8 A simple example. 37 2.9 Problems for chapter 2 . 39 3 Variable number of particles 43 3.1 Chemical potential. 43 3.2 Examples of the use of the chemical potential. 46 3.3 Di®erential relations and grand potential. 48 3.4 Grand partition function. 50 3.5 Overview of calculation methods. 55 3.6 A simple example. 57 3.7 Ideal gas in ¯rst approximation. 58 3.8 Problems for chapter 3 . 64 4 Statistics of independent particles. 67 4.1 Introduction. 67 4.2 Boltzmann gas again. 74 III IV CONTENTS 4.3 Gas of poly-atomic molecules. 77 4.4 Degenerate gas. 79 4.5 Fermi gas. 80 4.6 Boson gas. 85 4.7 Problems for chapter 4 . 87 5 Fermions and Bosons 89 5.1 Fermions in a box. 89 5.2 Bosons in a box. 106 5.3 Bose-Einstein condensation. 113 5.4 Problems for chapter 5 . 115 6 Density matrix formalism. 119 6.1 Density operators. 119 6.2 General ensembles. 123 6.3 Maximum entropy principle. 125 6.4 Equivalence of entropy de¯nitions for canonical ensemble. 134 6.5 Problems for chapter 6 . 136 7 Classical statistical mechanics. 139 7.1 Relation between quantum and classical mechanics. 139 7.2 Classical formulation of statistical mechanical properties. 142 7.3 Ergodic theorem. 144 7.4 What is chaos? . 146 7.5 Ideal gas in classical statistical mechanics. 149 7.6 Normal systems. 151 7.7 Quadratic variables. 151 7.8 E®ects of the potential energy. 152 7.9 Problems for chapter 7 . 154 8 Mean Field Theory: critical temperature. 157 8.1 Introduction. 157 8.2 Basic Mean Field theory. 161 8.3 Mean Field results. 164 8.4 Density-matrix approach (Bragg-Williams approximation. 168 8.5 Critical temperature in di®erent dimensions. 177 8.6 Bethe approximation. 181 8.7 Problems for chapter 8 . 188 9 General methods: critical exponents. 191 9.1 Introduction. 191 9.2 Integration over the coupling constant. 192 9.3 Critical exponents. 197 9.4 Relation between susceptibility and fluctuations. 203 9.5 Exact solution for the Ising chain. 205 9.6 Spin-correlation function for the Ising chain. 210 CONTENTS V 9.7 Renormalization group theory. 218 9.8 Problems for chapter 9 . 226 A Solutions to selected problems. 229 A.1 Solutions for chapter 1. 229 A.2 Solutions for chapter 2. 237 A.3 Solutions for chapter 3 . 242 A.4 Solutions for chapter 4. 247 A.5 Solutions for chapter 5. 251 A.6 Solutions for chapter 6. 257 VI CONTENTS List of Figures 4.1 Fermi Dirac distribution function. 71 7.1 H¶enon-Heilespotential. 148 ¤ 1 ¤ 8.1 ¯ = 2 , h = 2 . 166 8.2 ¯¤ = 2 , h¤ = 0:1 . 166 8.3 ¯ = 1 , J = 1 , q = 3 . 185 8.4 ¯ = 2 , J = 1 , q = 3 . 186 9.1 Ideal case to ¯nd critical exponent, with wrong guess of critical temperature. 201 9.2 Ideal case to ¯nd critical exponent. 202 9.3 Non-analytic case to ¯nd critical exponent. 202 9.4 Finite sample case to ¯nd critical exponent. 203 9.5 Cluster results to ¯nd critical exponent. 203 9.6 Magnetization of the one dimensional Ising chain. 210 9.7 Magnetization of the one dimensional Ising chain, as a func- tion of log(h). ............................211 VII VIII INTRODUCTION Introduction. Thermodynamics and statistical mechanics are two aspects of the study of large systems, where we cannot describe the majority of all details of that sys- tem. Thermodynamics approaches this problem from the observational side. We perform experiments on macroscopic systems and deduce collective properties of these systems, independent of the macroscopic details of the system. In ther- modynamics we start with a few state variables, and discuss relations between these variables and between the state variables and experimental observations. Many theorists ¯nd this an irrelevant exercise, but I strongly disagree. Thermo- dynamics is the mathematical language of experimental physics, and the nature of this language itself puts constraints on what kind of experimental results are valid. Nevertheless, true understanding needs the details on a microscopic level. We need to describe the behavior of all particles in the sample. That is an impossible task, and we need to resort to some kind of statistical treatment. Discussions on the foundations of statistical mechanics are very interesting, and help us understand the limitations of statistical mechanical treatments. This is analogue to the situation in quantum mechanics. Textbooks in quantum mechanics sue two approaches. One can simply start from SchrÄodinger'sequa- tion and discuss the mathematical techniques needed to solve this equation for important models. Or one can start with a discussion of the fundamentals of quantum mechanics and justify the existence of the SchrÄodingerequation. This is always done in less depth, because if one wants to go in great depth the discus- sion starts to touch on topics in philosophy. Again, I ¯nd that very interesting, but most practitioners do not need it. In statistical mechanics one can do the same. The central role is played by the partition function, and the rules needed to obtain observable data from the partition function. If these procedures are done correctly, all limitations set by thermodynamics are obeyed. In real life, of course, we make approximations, and then things can go wrong. One very important aspect of that discussion is the concept of the thermodynamic limit. We never have in¯nitely large samples, and hence we see e®ects due to the ¯nite size, both in space and in time. In such cases the statistical assumptions made to derive the concept of a partition function are not valid anymore, and we need alternative models. In many cases the modi¯cations are small, but sometimes they are large. Quanti¯cation of small and large now depends on intrinsic time and length scales of our system. The important di®erence between quantum mechanics and statistical me- chanics is the fact that for all atomic systems quantum mechanics is obeyed, but for many systems the ¯nite size of a sample is important. Therefore, in statistical mechanics it is much more important to understand what the as- sumptions are, and how they can be wrong. That is why we need to start with a discussion of the foundations. Again, we can go in greater depth that we INTRODUCTION IX will do here, which leads to important discussions on the arrow of time, for example. We will skip that here, but give enough information to understand the basic ideas. In order to introduce the partition function one needs to de¯ne the entropy. That can be done in many di®erent ways. It is possible to start from chaos and Lyaponov exponents. It is possible to start with information theory and derive a fairness function. Although the latter approach is fundamentally more sounds, it does not illuminate the ideas one needs to consider when discussing validity of the theory. Therefore, I follow the old fashioned approach based on probability of states. Working with statistical approaches is easier when the states of a system are labelled by an integer. Continuous variables need some extra prescriptions, which obscures the mathematics. Therefore we start with quantum mechanical systems. Counting is easiest. We follow the approach in the textbook by Kittel and Kroemer, an excellent textbook for further reference. It is aimed at the undergraduate level. Here we take their ideas, but expand on them. The toy model is a two state model, because counting states is simplest in that case. Almost every introduction to quantum statistical mechanics uses some form of this model, with states labelled up and down, plus and minus, black and white, occupied and empty, and so on. This basic model is simple enough to show mathematically how we use the law of large numbers (ergo, the thermodynamic limit) to arrive at Gaussian distributions. All conclusions follow from there. The ¯rst few chapters discuss the de¯nition of the entropy along these lines (chapter one), the partition function (chapter two), and the grand partition function, where the number of particles varies (chapter three). Remember that in thermodynamics we use N for the number of mols in a material, and use the constant R, the molar gas constant. In statistical mechanics we use N as the number of particles, and use kB, the Boltzmann constant. The ¯rst three chapters describe quantum states for the whole system. A very important application is when the energies of the particles are independent, in which case we can simplify the calculations enormously. This is done in chapter four. In chapter ¯ve we apply this formalism to the important examples of non-interacting fermions and bosons. The mathematical background needed is also explained in the textbook by Huang. This chapter is a must read for anybody who is going to work in solid state physics.
Recommended publications
  • Arxiv:1910.10745V1 [Cond-Mat.Str-El] 23 Oct 2019 2.2 Symmetry-Protected Time Crystals
    A Brief History of Time Crystals Vedika Khemania,b,∗, Roderich Moessnerc, S. L. Sondhid aDepartment of Physics, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138, USA bDepartment of Physics, Stanford University, Stanford, California 94305, USA cMax-Planck-Institut f¨urPhysik komplexer Systeme, 01187 Dresden, Germany dDepartment of Physics, Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey 08544, USA Abstract The idea of breaking time-translation symmetry has fascinated humanity at least since ancient proposals of the per- petuum mobile. Unlike the breaking of other symmetries, such as spatial translation in a crystal or spin rotation in a magnet, time translation symmetry breaking (TTSB) has been tantalisingly elusive. We review this history up to recent developments which have shown that discrete TTSB does takes place in periodically driven (Floquet) systems in the presence of many-body localization (MBL). Such Floquet time-crystals represent a new paradigm in quantum statistical mechanics — that of an intrinsically out-of-equilibrium many-body phase of matter with no equilibrium counterpart. We include a compendium of the necessary background on the statistical mechanics of phase structure in many- body systems, before specializing to a detailed discussion of the nature, and diagnostics, of TTSB. In particular, we provide precise definitions that formalize the notion of a time-crystal as a stable, macroscopic, conservative clock — explaining both the need for a many-body system in the infinite volume limit, and for a lack of net energy absorption or dissipation. Our discussion emphasizes that TTSB in a time-crystal is accompanied by the breaking of a spatial symmetry — so that time-crystals exhibit a novel form of spatiotemporal order.
    [Show full text]
  • Statistical Mechanics
    3 d rB rB 3 d rA rA Statistical Mechanics Daniel F. Styer December 2007 Statistical Mechanics Dan Styer Department of Physics and Astronomy Oberlin College Oberlin, Ohio 44074-1088 [email protected] http://www.oberlin.edu/physics/dstyer December 2007 Although, as a matter of history, statistical mechanics owes its origin to investigations in thermodynamics, it seems eminently worthy of an independent development, both on account of the elegance and simplicity of its principles, and because it yields new results and places old truths in a new light. | J. Willard Gibbs Elementary Principles in Statistical Mechanics Contents 0 Preface 1 1 The Properties of Matter in Bulk 4 1.1 What is Statistical Mechanics About? . 4 1.2 Outline of Book . 4 1.3 Fluid Statics . 5 1.4 Phase Diagrams . 7 1.5 Additional Problems . 7 2 Principles of Statistical Mechanics 10 2.1 Microscopic Description of a Classical System . 10 2.2 Macroscopic Description of a Large Equilibrium System . 14 2.3 Fundamental Assumption . 15 2.4 Statistical Definition of Entropy . 17 2.5 Entropy of a Monatomic Ideal Gas . 19 2.6 Qualitative Features of Entropy . 25 2.7 Using Entropy to Find (Define) Temperature and Pressure . 34 2.8 Additional Problems . 44 3 Thermodynamics 46 3.1 Heat and Work . 46 3.2 Heat Engines . 50 i ii CONTENTS 3.3 Thermodynamic Quantities . 52 3.4 Multivariate Calculus . 55 3.5 The Thermodynamic Dance . 60 3.6 Non-fluid Systems . 67 3.7 Thermodynamics Applied to Fluids . 68 3.8 Thermodynamics Applied to Phase Transitions .
    [Show full text]
  • 8.1. Spin & Statistics
    8.1. Spin & Statistics Ref: A.Khare,”Fractional Statistics & Quantum Theory”, 1997, Chap.2. Anyons = Particles obeying fractional statistics. Particle statistics is determined by the phase factor eiα picked up by the wave function under the interchange of the positions of any pair of (identical) particles in the system. Before the discovery of the anyons, this particle interchange (or exchange) was treated as the permutation of particle labels. Let P be the operator for this interchange. P2 =I → e2iα =1 ∴ eiα = ±1 i.e., α=0,π Thus, there’re only 2 kinds of statistics, α=0(π) for Bosons (Fermions) obeying Bose-Einstein (Fermi-Dirac) statistics. Pauli’s spin-statistics theorem then relates particle spin with statistics, namely, bosons (fermions) are particles with integer (half-integer) spin. To account for the anyons, particle exchange is re-defined as an observable adiabatic (constant energy) process of physically interchanging particles. ( This is in line with the quantum philosophy that only observables are physically relevant. ) As will be shown later, the new definition does not affect statistics in 3-D space. However, for particles in 2-D space, α can be any (real) value; hence anyons. The converse of the spin-statistic theorem then implies arbitrary spin for 2-D particles. Quantization of S in 3-D See M.Alonso, H.Valk, “Quantum Mechanics: Principles & Applications”, 1973, §6.2. In 3-D, the (spin) angular momentum S has 3 non-commuting components satisfying S i,S j =iℏε i j k Sk 2 & S ,S i=0 2 This means a state can be the simultaneous eigenstate of S & at most one Si.
    [Show full text]
  • Many Particle Orbits – Statistics and Second Quantization
    H. Kleinert, PATH INTEGRALS March 24, 2013 (/home/kleinert/kleinert/books/pathis/pthic7.tex) Mirum, quod divina natura dedit agros It’s wonderful that divine nature has given us fields Varro (116 BC–27BC) 7 Many Particle Orbits – Statistics and Second Quantization Realistic physical systems usually contain groups of identical particles such as spe- cific atoms or electrons. Focusing on a single group, we shall label their orbits by x(ν)(t) with ν =1, 2, 3, . , N. Their Hamiltonian is invariant under the group of all N! permutations of the orbital indices ν. Their Schr¨odinger wave functions can then be classified according to the irreducible representations of the permutation group. Not all possible representations occur in nature. In more than two space dimen- sions, there exists a superselection rule, whose origin is yet to be explained, which eliminates all complicated representations and allows only for the two simplest ones to be realized: those with complete symmetry and those with complete antisymme- try. Particles which appear always with symmetric wave functions are called bosons. They all carry an integer-valued spin. Particles with antisymmetric wave functions are called fermions1 and carry a spin whose value is half-integer. The symmetric and antisymmetric wave functions give rise to the characteristic statistical behavior of fermions and bosons. Electrons, for example, being spin-1/2 particles, appear only in antisymmetric wave functions. The antisymmetry is the origin of the famous Pauli exclusion principle, allowing only a single particle of a definite spin orientation in a quantum state, which is the principal reason for the existence of the periodic system of elements, and thus of matter in general.
    [Show full text]
  • Verification, Validation, and Predictive Capability in Computational Engineering and Physics
    SAND REPORT SAND2003-3769 Unlimited Release Printed February 2003 Verification, Validation, and Predictive Capability in Computational Engineering and Physics William L. Oberkampf, Timothy G. Trucano, and Charles Hirsch Prepared by Sandia National Laboratories Albuquerque, New Mexico 87185 and Livermore, California 94550 Sandia is a multiprogram laboratory operated by Sandia Corporation, a Lockheed Martin Company, for the United States Department of Energy’s National Nuclear Security Administration under Contract DE-AC04-94-AL85000. Approved for public release; further dissemination unlimited. Issued by Sandia National Laboratories, operated for the United States Department of Energy by Sandia Corporation. NOTICE: This report was prepared as an account of work sponsored by an agency of the United States Government. Neither the United States Government, nor any agency thereof, nor any of their employees, nor any of their contractors, subcontractors, or their employees, make any warranty, express or implied, or assume any legal liability or responsibility for the accuracy, completeness, or usefulness of any information, apparatus, product, or process disclosed, or represent that its use would not infringe privately owned rights. Reference herein to any specific commercial product, process, or service by trade name, trademark, manufacturer, or otherwise, does not necessarily constitute or imply its endorsement, recommendation, or favoring by the United States Government, any agency thereof, or any of their contractors or subcontractors. The views and opinions expressed herein do not necessarily state or reflect those of the United States Government, any agency thereof, or any of their contractors. Printed in the United States of America. This report has been reproduced directly from the best available copy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Conventionality of Parastatistics
    The Conventionality of Parastatistics David John Baker Hans Halvorson Noel Swanson∗ March 6, 2014 Abstract Nature seems to be such that we can describe it accurately with quantum theories of bosons and fermions alone, without resort to parastatistics. This has been seen as a deep mystery: paraparticles make perfect physical sense, so why don't we see them in nature? We consider one potential answer: every paraparticle theory is physically equivalent to some theory of bosons or fermions, making the absence of paraparticles in our theories a matter of convention rather than a mysterious empirical discovery. We argue that this equivalence thesis holds in all physically admissible quantum field theories falling under the domain of the rigorous Doplicher-Haag-Roberts approach to superselection rules. Inadmissible parastatistical theories are ruled out by a locality- inspired principle we call Charge Recombination. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Paraparticles in Quantum Theory 6 ∗This work is fully collaborative. Authors are listed in alphabetical order. 1 3 Theoretical Equivalence 11 3.1 Field systems in AQFT . 13 3.2 Equivalence of field systems . 17 4 A Brief History of the Equivalence Thesis 20 4.1 The Green Decomposition . 20 4.2 Klein Transformations . 21 4.3 The Argument of Dr¨uhl,Haag, and Roberts . 24 4.4 The Doplicher-Roberts Reconstruction Theorem . 26 5 Sharpening the Thesis 29 6 Discussion 36 6.1 Interpretations of QM . 44 6.2 Structuralism and Haecceities . 46 6.3 Paraquark Theories . 48 1 Introduction Our most fundamental theories of matter provide a highly accurate description of subatomic particles and their behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • Subject Benchmark Statement: Physics, Astronomy and Astrophysics
    QAA MEMBERSHIP Subject Benchmark Statement Physics, Astronomy and Astrophysics October 2019 Contents How can I use this document? ................................................................................................. 1 About the Statement ................................................................................................................ 2 Relationship to legislation ......................................................................................................... 2 Summary of changes from the previous Subject Benchmark Statement (2017) ....................... 2 1 Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 3 2 Nature and extent of physics, astronomy and astrophysics ............................................. 4 3 Subject-specific knowledge and understanding ............................................................... 6 4 Teaching, learning and assessment ................................................................................ 9 5 Benchmark standards ................................................................................................... 11 Appendix: Membership of the benchmarking and review groups for the Subject Benchmark Statement for Physics, Astronomy and Astrophysics ............................................................. 13 How can I use this document? This is the Subject Benchmark Statement for Physics, Astronomy and Astrophysics. It defines the academic standards that can be expected
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 6: Entropy
    Matthew Schwartz Statistical Mechanics, Spring 2019 Lecture 6: Entropy 1 Introduction In this lecture, we discuss many ways to think about entropy. The most important and most famous property of entropy is that it never decreases Stot > 0 (1) Here, Stot means the change in entropy of a system plus the change in entropy of the surroundings. This is the second law of thermodynamics that we met in the previous lecture. There's a great quote from Sir Arthur Eddington from 1927 summarizing the importance of the second law: If someone points out to you that your pet theory of the universe is in disagreement with Maxwell's equationsthen so much the worse for Maxwell's equations. If it is found to be contradicted by observationwell these experimentalists do bungle things sometimes. But if your theory is found to be against the second law of ther- modynamics I can give you no hope; there is nothing for it but to collapse in deepest humiliation. Another possibly relevant quote, from the introduction to the statistical mechanics book by David Goodstein: Ludwig Boltzmann who spent much of his life studying statistical mechanics, died in 1906, by his own hand. Paul Ehrenfest, carrying on the work, died similarly in 1933. Now it is our turn to study statistical mechanics. There are many ways to dene entropy. All of them are equivalent, although it can be hard to see. In this lecture we will compare and contrast dierent denitions, building up intuition for how to think about entropy in dierent contexts. The original denition of entropy, due to Clausius, was thermodynamic.
    [Show full text]
  • Dirty Tricks for Statistical Mechanics
    Dirty tricks for statistical mechanics Martin Grant Physics Department, McGill University c MG, August 2004, version 0.91 ° ii Preface These are lecture notes for PHYS 559, Advanced Statistical Mechanics, which I’ve taught at McGill for many years. I’m intending to tidy this up into a book, or rather the first half of a book. This half is on equilibrium, the second half would be on dynamics. These were handwritten notes which were heroically typed by Ryan Porter over the summer of 2004, and may someday be properly proof-read by me. Even better, maybe someday I will revise the reasoning in some of the sections. Some of it can be argued better, but it was too much trouble to rewrite the handwritten notes. I am also trying to come up with a good book title, amongst other things. The two titles I am thinking of are “Dirty tricks for statistical mechanics”, and “Valhalla, we are coming!”. Clearly, more thinking is necessary, and suggestions are welcome. While these lecture notes have gotten longer and longer until they are al- most self-sufficient, it is always nice to have real books to look over. My favorite modern text is “Lectures on Phase Transitions and the Renormalisation Group”, by Nigel Goldenfeld (Addison-Wesley, Reading Mass., 1992). This is referred to several times in the notes. Other nice texts are “Statistical Physics”, by L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz (Addison-Wesley, Reading Mass., 1970) par- ticularly Chaps. 1, 12, and 14; “Statistical Mechanics”, by S.-K. Ma (World Science, Phila., 1986) particularly Chaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Physics and Medicine: a Historical Perspective
    Series Physics and Medicine 1 Physics and medicine: a historical perspective Stephen F Keevil Nowadays, the term medical physics usually refers to the work of physicists employed in hospitals, who are concerned Lancet 2011; 379: 1517–24 mainly with medical applications of radiation, diagnostic imaging, and clinical measurement. This involvement in Published Online clinical work began barely 100 years ago, but the relation between physics and medicine has a much longer history. In April 18, 2012 this report, I have traced this history from the earliest recorded period, when physical agents such as heat and light DOI:10.1016/S0140- 6736(11)60282-1 began to be used to diagnose and treat disease. Later, great polymaths such as Leonardo da Vinci and Alhazen used See Comment pages 1463 physical principles to begin the quest to understand the function of the body. After the scientifi c revolution in the and 1464 17th century, early medical physicists developed a purely mechanistic approach to physiology, whereas others applied This is the fi rst in a Series of ideas derived from physics in an eff ort to comprehend the nature of life itself. These early investigations led directly fi ve papers about physics to the development of specialties such as electrophysiology, biomechanics, and ophthalmology. Physics-based medical and medicine technology developed rapidly during the 19th century, but it was the revolutionary discoveries about radiation and Department of Medical radioactivity at the end of the century that ushered in a new era of radiation-based medical diagnosis and treatment, Physics, Guy’s and St Thomas’ thereby giving rise to the modern medical physics profession.
    [Show full text]
  • NASA Goddard Space Flight Center Laboratory for High Energy Astrophysics Greenbelt, Maryland 20771
    1 NASA Goddard Space Flight Center Laboratory for High Energy Astrophysics Greenbelt, Maryland 20771 This report covers the period from July 1, 2002 to June Stephen Henderson, Hans Krimm, John Krizmanic, Jeongin 30, 2003. Lee, John Lehan, James Lochner, Thomas McGlynn, Paul This Laboratory’s scientific research is directed toward McNamara, Alex Moiseev, Koji Mukai, James Reeves, Na- experimental and theoretical investigations in the areas of dine Saudraix, Chris Shrader, Steven Snowden, Yang Soong, X-ray, gamma-ray, gravitational wave and cosmic-ray astro- Martin Still, Steve Sturner, and Vigdor Teplitz. physics. The range of interests of the scientists includes the The following investigators are University of Maryland Sun and the solar system, stellar objects, binary systems, Scientists: Drs. Keith Arnaud, David Band ͑UMBC͒, Simon neutron stars, black holes, the interstellar medium, normal Bandler, Patricia Boyd ͑UMBC͒, John Cannizzo ͑UMBC͒, and active galaxies, galaxy clusters, cosmic ray particles, David Davis ͑UMBC͒, Ian George ͑UMBC͒, Masaharu gravitational wave astrophysics, extragalactic background ra- Hirayama ͑UMBC͒, Una Hwang, Yasushi Ikebe ͑UMBC͒, diation, and cosmology. Scientists and engineers in the Kip Kuntz ͑UMBC͒, Mark Lindeman, Michael Loewenstein, Laboratory also serve the scientific community, including Craig Markwardt, Julie McEnery ͑UMBC͒, Igor Moskalenko project support such as acting as project scientists and pro- ͑UMBC͒, Chee Ng, Patrick Palmeri, Dirk Petry ͑UMBC͒, viding technical assistance for various space missions. Also Christopher Reynolds, Ian Richardson, and Jane Turner at any one time, there are typically between ten and fifteen ͑UMBC͒. graduate students involved in Ph.D. research work in this Visiting scientists from other institutions: Drs. Hilary Laboratory.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Molecular Chaos Hypothesis and the H-Theorem: Problem of Constraints and Amendment of Nonextensive Statistical Mechanics
    Generalized molecular chaos hypothesis and the H-theorem: Problem of constraints and amendment of nonextensive statistical mechanics Sumiyoshi Abe1,2,3 1Department of Physical Engineering, Mie University, Mie 514-8507, Japan*) 2Institut Supérieur des Matériaux et Mécaniques Avancés, 44 F. A. Bartholdi, 72000 Le Mans, France 3Inspire Institute Inc., McLean, Virginia 22101, USA Abstract Quite unexpectedly, kinetic theory is found to specify the correct definition of average value to be employed in nonextensive statistical mechanics. It is shown that the normal average is consistent with the generalized Stosszahlansatz (i.e., molecular chaos hypothesis) and the associated H-theorem, whereas the q-average widely used in the relevant literature is not. In the course of the analysis, the distributions with finite cut-off factors are rigorously treated. Accordingly, the formulation of nonextensive statistical mechanics is amended based on the normal average. In addition, the Shore- Johnson theorem, which supports the use of the q-average, is carefully reexamined, and it is found that one of the axioms may not be appropriate for systems to be treated within the framework of nonextensive statistical mechanics. PACS number(s): 05.20.Dd, 05.20.Gg, 05.90.+m ____________________________ *) Permanent address 1 I. INTRODUCTION There exist a number of physical systems that possess exotic properties in view of traditional Boltzmann-Gibbs statistical mechanics. They are said to be statistical- mechanically anomalous, since they often exhibit and realize broken ergodicity, strong correlation between elements, (multi)fractality of phase-space/configuration-space portraits, and long-range interactions, for example. In the past decade, nonextensive statistical mechanics [1,2], which is a generalization of the Boltzmann-Gibbs theory, has been drawing continuous attention as a possible theoretical framework for describing these systems.
    [Show full text]