Animal Welfare

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Animal Welfare Animal Welfare Series Editor Clive Phillips School of Veterinary Science University of Queensland Gatton, QLD Australia Advisory Editors Marieke Cassia Gartner Atlanta, GA, USA Karen F. Mancera Mexico City, Mexico Fiona C. Rioja-Lang Mérida, Yucatán, Mexico More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/5675 Claudio Carere • Jennifer Mather Editors The Welfare of Invertebrate Animals Editors Claudio Carere Jennifer Mather Department of Ecological and Biological Department of Psychology Sciences, Ichthyogenic Experimental University of Lethbridge Marine Centre (CISMAR) Lethbridge, Alberta, Canada University of Tuscia Tarquinia, Viterbo, Italy ISSN 1572-7408 Animal Welfare ISBN 978-3-030-13946-9 ISBN 978-3-030-13947-6 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-13947-6 © Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG. The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland Editor Fiona C. Rioja-Lang deceased in 2019 at the time of publication My Vote for the “Invertebrates” At the time when I was a young student and quite some time beyond, most biologists were convinced: if you can’t even know what your best friend is thinking and feeling, how can you ever know what is going on in an animal? It was considered unscientific for such dogmatic reasons to seriously ask a question regarding the mental life, the thinking and feeling of an animal. You could not hope to find answers but would rather get lost, if you dared to delve into this black hole. Among widespread beliefs and attitudes were the following: (1) that we can never say anything about feelings or thoughts of animals; (2) that man is too distinct from animals to be compared with them; (3) that man is the centre of the world and human society has to take care of humanity only; and (4) that animals are dull and “bêtes machines”, as Descartes said, just things, which automatically follow their instincts in a preprogrammed way. I am of course exaggerating. Darwin had firmly embedded man in the process of evolution and placed us on a continuum with animals a long time ago, and there have always been keepers of cats, dogs and horses and maybe even birds who would insist that their pets do think and feel and have emotions and personality. Obviously, it is easier to assign such capabilities to animals the closer these are to us humans phylogenetically. But invertebrates like crickets and fruit flies? For most listeners, it was at best an entertaining joke when I talked about the individuality of spider males, impressed by the differences of their courtship behaviour. Remember that Jane Goodall even met with difficulties when giving her chimpanzees in Gombe human names and personality in the 1960s. Although much of the attitude prevailing at my time as a biology student still exists outside our field of expertise, big changes of our view of the world have occurred since. Many of us (though not enough yet) now better understand that humankind has responsibilities beyond itself or, put in another way, that we have to take care of the entire planet with all its diversity of life and environmental com- plexities. Nature is not just a machine endlessly producing for us only, or a big buffet table at which we can endlessly serve ourselves without paying. And wilderness is not just luxury. We have instead begun to better understand that all living beings are vii viii My Vote for the “Invertebrates” interconnected on this planet and depend on each other, that sustainability is a big issue and that nature cannot be treated as if it existed to serve our human needs and pleasures only. I hopefully assume that there is more awareness of biophilia now, following the psychoanalyst Erich Fromm and even more so the biologist Edward O Wilson: the appreciation of all living beings and a feeling of deep-seated connect- edness. Some unpleasant changes critically endangering our own human welfare like overpopulation, food and energy shortage and climate change have helped to promote this point of view. A few societies only, mostly small and of little global influence, have kept the old traditions of their balanced view of nature. Unfortu- nately, they are unable to stop the dramatic impact of industrialization and the unlimited endeavour for our human well-being and materialistic success. I am not an expert on questions of animal welfare but instead an experimental physiologist doing basic research. As is true for many biologists, my own biophilia implies a sense for the deep value of nature and an interest in its increasingly profound understanding, including an understanding of our human place in it. Apart from my professional interest in science, it is this background and wishful thinking which underlies my interest in animal welfare and the invertebrates. I read through this book on the welfare of invertebrate animals with great interest and much appreciate that the topic is given so much attention. Apart from the presentation of practical cases like that of butterfly houses, bee keeping, spiders in captivity and captive cephalopods, experts also address questions of philosophy and ethics. I was pleased to find so many honest “might”, “could”, “probably” and subjunctives. No wonder we are still far from a clear understanding of nociception and pain, the integration of sensory information in the central nervous systems of most invertebrates and the selection pressures and fitness gains associated with much of invertebrate behaviour. Feelings and thoughts of a snail or an earthworm or a cockroach are still obscure issues. And of course, one cannot expect any overarching general recipe to provide welfare for such a large and diverse group of animals as are the invertebrates. From a zoological point of view, the “animals without backbones” are much too heterogeneous to be put into one phylum. Their diversity could not be greater, considering their Bauplan, their habitat, nervous and sensory systems and behaviour. A sessile sponge filter feeding in the sea, an earthworm digging through the soil, a spider building mechanical masterpieces of aery silken webs, a cricket singing love songs or a dragonfly manoeuvring masterly through the air: the differences could not be greater. For the zoologist, the so-called invertebrates (not a serious terminology in taxonomy) comprise as many as 26 of a total of 27 phyla, the only additional one being the chordates which include us and all other vertebrates. “Invertebrates” make up for at least 95% of all animal species so far described. A few numbers illustrate their dominance impressively: insects c. 1,000,000 described species (and probably some 10 million existing) as opposed to vertebrates with only c. 66,000 species; even the arachnids are good for more than 100,000 species, with the spiders alone representing almost 50,000 described species. We are living in an age of insects and even more so of arthropods. Seen from this and an evolutionary point of view, it My Vote for the “Invertebrates” ix is frustrating that some people still talk about “insects (or even bugs) and animals”. Aren’t insects like all other “invertebrates” worth being called animals as well? When we talk about the welfare of the “invertebrates”, we should also gratefully appreciate how important they have become in research, allowing us to reveal many fundamental secrets of life at all levels of organization, from molecular to organis- mal. The fruit fly Drosophila, the nematode Caenorhabditis, the honeybee Apis, the coelenterate Nematostella and others have become outstandingly important model organisms. Even spiders, disliked by many for no good reason, have made their way into experimental research asking serious questions of cognition and personality. Neurobiology owes the understanding of action potentials to the giant fibres of the squid Loligo, that of lateral inhibition to the horseshoe crab Limulus and that of learning and memory to a large extent to the sea hare Aplysia. And who had thought only some thirty years ago that the fruit fly and bees and jumping spiders might play a significant role in cognition research? Cognitive abilities of sometimes startling complexity now reach down far in the phylogenetic tree. Man is not so distinct from the rest of the animal kingdom anymore, including the “invertebrates”. Latest research has brought to light rather surprising deep homologies conserved through- out the metazoans. There are many correspondences of neural circuits in arthropods and chordates (vertebrates), and there is evidence for the conservation of neural ground patterns and genetic mechanisms underlying brain development.
Recommended publications
  • Practical Ethics, Third Edition
    This page intentionally left blank Practical Ethics Third Edition For thirty years, Peter Singer’s Practical Ethics has been the classic introduction to applied ethics. For this third edition, the author has revised and updated all the chapters and added a new chapter addressing climate change, one of the most important ethical chal- lenges of our generation. Some of the questions discussed in this book concern our daily lives. Is it ethical to buy luxuries when others do not have enough to eat? Should we buy meat produced from intensively reared animals? Am I doing something wrong if my carbon footprint is above the global average? Other questions confront us as concerned citizens: equality and discrimination on the grounds of race or sex; abortion, the use of embryos for research, and euthanasia; political violence and terrorism; and the preservation of our planet’s environment. This book’s lucid style and provocative arguments make it an ideal text for university courses and for anyone willing to think about how she or he ought to live. Peter Singer is currently Ira W. DeCamp Professor of Bioethics at the University Center for Human Values at Princeton University and Laureate Professor at the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics at the University of Melbourne. He is the author or editor of more than forty books, including Animal Liberation (1975), Rethinking Life and Death (1996) and, most recently, The Life You Can Save (2009). In 2005, he was named one of the 100 most influential people in the world by Time magazine. Practical Ethics Third Edition PETER SINGER Princeton University and the University of Melbourne cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao˜ Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City Cambridge University Press 32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, ny 10013-2473, usa www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521707688 C Peter Singer 1980, 1993, 2011 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • The Welfare of Invertebrate Animals Series: Animal Welfare
    springer.com Claudio Carere, Jennifer Mather (Eds.) The Welfare of Invertebrate Animals Series: Animal Welfare Takes animal welfare into a wholly new and challenging dimension Provides essays across various taxa Illustrates how and why welfare should be achieved and formally anchored Shares cutting-edge findings, helping readers understand invertebrates in care This book is devoted to the welfare of invertebrates, which make up 99% of animal species on earth. Addressing animal welfare, we do not often think of invertebrates; in fact we seldom consider them to be deserving of welfare evaluation. And yet we should. Welfare is a broad concern for any animal that we house, control or utilize – and we utilize invertebrates a lot. The Authors start with an emphasis on the values of non-vertebrate animals and discuss the 1st ed. 2019, XVIII, 248 p. 21 illus., 16 need for a book on the present topic. The following chapters focus on specific taxa, tackling illus. in color. questions that are most appropriate to each one. What is pain in crustaceans, and how might we prevent it? How do we ensure that octopuses are not bored? What do bees need to thrive, Printed book pollinate our plants and give us honey? Since invertebrates have distinct personalities and Hardcover some social animals have group personalities, how do we consider this? And, as in the 179,99 € | £159.99 | $219.99 European Union’s application of welfare consideration to cephalopods, how do the practical [1]192,59 € (D) | 197,99 € (A) | CHF regulatory issues play out? We have previously relegated invertebrates to the category ‘things’ 212,50 and did not worry about their treatment.
    [Show full text]
  • Role of Lactobacillus Reuteri DSM 17938 in Survival of Artemia Franciscana
    Role of Lactobacillus reuteri DSM 17938 in survival of Artemia franciscana Development of a new experimental model for probiotic studies Tiziana Racca Master Degree Project in Infection Biology, 45 hp. VT 2020 Department of Molecular Sciences, SLU Supervisor: Stefan Roos Co-supervisor: Ludwig Lundqvist To my parents, who simply made it possible TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. POPULAR SCIENCE SUMMARY ..................................................................................................... 1 2. ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................................... 2 3. INTRODUCTION 3.1. Probiotics ................................................................................................................................ 3 3.2. Lactobacillus reuteri ............................................................................................................... 4 3.3. Artemia franciscana ................................................................................................................ 5 4. AIM ................................................................................................................................................ 7 5. ETHICAL CONSIDERATIONS ................................................................................................... 7 6. MATERIAL AND METHODS 6.1. Bacterial strains ....................................................................................................................... 8 6.2. Bacterial cultures
    [Show full text]
  • Bringing Animal Protection Legislation Into Line with Its Purported Purposes: a Proposal for Equality Amongst Non- Human Animals
    Pace Environmental Law Review Volume 37 Issue 2 Spring 2020 Article 1 May 2020 Bringing Animal Protection Legislation Into Line With its Purported Purposes: A Proposal for Equality Amongst Non- Human Animals Jane Kotzmann Deakin University Gisela Nip Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/pelr Part of the Animal Law Commons, Energy and Utilities Law Commons, Environmental Law Commons, International Law Commons, and the Natural Resources Law Commons Recommended Citation Jane Kotzmann and Gisela Nip, Bringing Animal Protection Legislation Into Line With its Purported Purposes: A Proposal for Equality Amongst Non-Human Animals, 37 Pace Envtl. L. Rev. 247 (2020) Available at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/pelr/vol37/iss2/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Law at DigitalCommons@Pace. It has been accepted for inclusion in Pace Environmental Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Pace. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLE Bringing Animal Protection Legislation Into Line With its Purported Purposes: A Proposal for Equality Amongst Non-Human Animals JANE KOTZMANN* & GISELA NIP† The United States has a strong history of enacting laws to pro- tect animals from the pain and suffering inflicted by humans. In- deed, the passage of the Massachusetts’ Body of Liberties in 1641 made it the first country in the world to pass such laws. Neverthe- less, contemporary animal protection laws in all jurisdictions of the United States are limited in their ability to adequately realize their primary purpose of protecting animals from unnecessary or unjus- tifiable pain and suffering.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lobster Considered
    6 ! e Lobster Considered Robert C. Jones ! e day may come, when the rest of the animal creation may acquire those rights which never could have been withholden from them but by the hand of tyranny. — Jeremy Bentham Is it not possible that future generations will regard our present agribusiness and eating practices in much the same way we now view Nero ’ s entertainments or Mengele ’ s experiments? — David Foster Wallace ! e arguments to prove man ’ s superiority cannot shatter this hard fact: in su" ering the animals are our equals. — Peter Singer In 1941 M. F. K. Fisher " rst asked us to consider the oyster,1 n o t a s a m o r a l but as a culinary exploration. Sixty-three years later when David Foster Wallace asked us to consider the lobster2 for ostensibly similar reasons, the investigation quickly abandoned the gustatory and took a turn toward the philosophical and ethical. In that essay, originally published in Gourmet magazine, Wallace challenges us to think deeply about the troubling ethical questions raised by the issue of lobster pain and our moral (mis)treatment of these friendly crustaceans. Since the publication of that essay, research on nonhuman animal sentience has exploded. News reports of the " ndings of research into animal behavior and cognition are common; 2010 saw the publication of a popular book of the title Do Fish Feel Pain? 3 In this essay, I accept Wallace ’ s challenge and argue not only that according to our best 1 M. F. K. Fisher, Consider the Oyster (New York: Still Point Press, 2001).
    [Show full text]
  • The Takeover Chicken Farming and the Roots of American Agribusiness 1St Edition Download Free
    THE TAKEOVER CHICKEN FARMING AND THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN AGRIBUSINESS 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Monica Gisolfi | 9780820349718 | | | | | Journal of Southern History Drawing on USDA files, oral history, congressional records, and poultry publications, Gisolfi puts a local The Takeover Chicken Farming and the Roots of American Agribusiness 1st edition on one of the twentieth century's silent agribusiness revolutions. Book Description Condition: New. A United Nations press release states: "Governments, local authorities and international agencies need to take a greatly increased role in combating the role of factory-farming, commerce in live poultry, and wildlife markets which provide ideal conditions for the virus to spread and mutate into a more dangerous form Animal euthanasia Cruelty to animals Pain in animals Pain in amphibians Pain in cephalopods Pain in crustaceans Pain in fish Pain in invertebrates Pain and suffering in laboratory animals Welfare of farmed insects. Poultry producers routinely use nationally approved medications, such as antibiotics, in feed or drinking water, to treat disease or to prevent disease outbreaks. Delaware Online. Following a trajectory from Reconstruction through the Great Depression to the present day, Monica R. How did the modern poultry industry emerge from a region of cotton farms? Australian Broadcasting Corp. Main article: Yarding. Osteoporosis may be prevented by free range and cage-free housing systems, as they have shown to have a beneficial impact on the skeletal system of the hens compared to those housed in caged systems. New Quantity Available: 3. In the UK, the Department for Environment, Food and Rural Affairs Defra states that a free-range chicken must have day- time access to open-air runs during at least half of its life.
    [Show full text]
  • Humane Slaughter of Edible Decapod Crustaceans
    animals Review Humane Slaughter of Edible Decapod Crustaceans Francesca Conte 1 , Eva Voslarova 2,* , Vladimir Vecerek 2, Robert William Elwood 3 , Paolo Coluccio 4, Michela Pugliese 1 and Annamaria Passantino 1 1 Department of Veterinary Sciences, University of Messina, Polo Universitario Annunziata, 981 68 Messina, Italy; [email protected] (F.C.); [email protected] (M.P.); [email protected] (A.P.) 2 Department of Animal Protection and Welfare and Veterinary Public Health, Faculty of Veterinary Hygiene and Ecology, University of Veterinary Sciences Brno, 612 42 Brno, Czech Republic; [email protected] 3 School of Biological Sciences, Queen’s University, Belfast BT9 5DL, UK; [email protected] 4 Department of Neurosciences, Psychology, Drug Research and Child Health (NEUROFARBA), University of Florence-Viale Pieraccini, 6-50139 Firenze, Italy; paolo.coluccio@unifi.it * Correspondence: [email protected] Simple Summary: Decapods respond to noxious stimuli in ways that are consistent with the experi- ence of pain; thus, we accept the need to provide a legal framework for their protection when they are used for human food. We review the main methods used to slaughter the major decapod crustaceans, highlighting problems posed by each method for animal welfare. The aim is to identify methods that are the least likely to cause suffering. These methods can then be recommended, whereas other methods that are more likely to cause suffering may be banned. We thus request changes in the legal status of this group of animals, to protect them from slaughter techniques that are not viewed as being acceptable. Abstract: Vast numbers of crustaceans are produced by aquaculture and caught in fisheries to Citation: Conte, F.; Voslarova, E.; meet the increasing demand for seafood and freshwater crustaceans.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| Do Fish Feel Pain? 1St Edition
    DO FISH FEEL PAIN? 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Victoria Braithwaite | 9780199551200 | | | | | Do fish feel pain? The king pulls the smaller bird into the palace, infuriating the hawk, which demands replacement for its lost meal, so he slices off his own arm and foot to feed it. Thank you for taking your time to send in your valued opinion to Science X editors. The argument over fish feeling pain has driven a wedge between anglers and animal-rights activists, but one of the study's authors feels the divisive debate is unproductive. Share Twit Share Email. You can be assured our editors closely monitor every feedback sent and will take Do Fish Feel Pain? 1st edition actions. User comments. Fish and Fisheries. ILAR Journal. Do Fish Feel Pain? 1st edition Read Edit View history. In a study, fish were injected in the lips with bee venom or an acid solution. Movement groups, parties. The monk was wearing a white mask like those that some Jains wear to avoid inhaling insects and other tiny creatures. Emotional pain is the pain experienced in the absence of physical trauma, e. The places where they worship and tend to animals seemed, to me, like good places to contemplate the Do Fish Feel Pain? 1st edition frontier of animal-consciousness research. Do Fish Feel Pain? 1st edition Bees love getting high on caffeine. Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology C. Independent Premium comments 0 Independent Premium comments Open comments 0 open comments. These receptors send electrical signals through nerve-lines and the spinal cord to the cerebral cortex neocortex.
    [Show full text]
  • Abdominal Cutaneous Nerve Entrapment Syndrome (ACNES): a Commonly Overlooked Cause of Abdominal Pain
    clinical contributions Abdominal Cutaneous Nerve Entrapment Syndrome (ACNES): A Commonly Overlooked Cause of Abdominal Pain By William V Applegate, MD, FABFP Introduction two patients with this diagnosis for every 150 patients Abdominal cutaneous nerve entrapment syndrome overall but have seen as many as three such patients (ACNES) may sound like an esoteric condition rarely per consultation session in a busy evening clinic where seen by clinicians but is a common condition. When a 15 or more clinicians were on duty. patient is seen for abdominal pain without other clini- Acute cases of ACNES are usually seen in the evening, cally significant symptoms, ACNES should be high on especially in spring and summer, when people are more the list of likely diagnoses. active. Chronic and recurrent cases are more likely to Beginning in 1792 with J P Frank’s description of the be seen in the daytime throughout the year. condition he named “peritonitis muscularis,”1 a sam- To avoid causing the patient unnecessary anxiety and pling of pertinent medical literature on this subject2-9 tension, loss of work time, and both the expense and shows how often the subject has been written about possible hazard of multiple diagnostic procedures, the over the years. These articles state that abdominal wall first physician examining the patient must establish the pain is often wrongly attributed to intra-abdominal dis- diagnosis of ACNES if this condition is present. Com- orders and that this misdirected diagnosis can lead to piled from my own experience and that of other inves- unnecessary consultation, testing, and even abdominal tigators who have written about ACNES, the informa- surgery, all of which can be avoided if the initial exam- tion presented here should give readers the tools iner makes the right diagnosis.
    [Show full text]
  • RESEARCH ARTICLE Shock Avoidance by Discrimination Learning in the Shore Crab (Carcinus Maenas) Is Consistent with a Key Criterion for Pain
    353 The Journal of Experimental Biology 216, 353-358 © 2013. Published by The Company of Biologists Ltd doi:10.1242/jeb.072041 RESEARCH ARTICLE Shock avoidance by discrimination learning in the shore crab (Carcinus maenas) is consistent with a key criterion for pain Barry Magee and Robert W. Elwood* School of Biological Sciences, Queenʼs University, Belfast, Medical Biology Centre, 97 Lisburn Road, Belfast BT9 7BL, UK *Author for correspondence ([email protected]) SUMMARY Nociception allows for immediate reflex withdrawal whereas pain allows for longer-term protection via rapid learning. We examine here whether shore crabs placed within a brightly lit chamber learn to avoid one of two dark shelters when that shelter consistently results in shock. Crabs were randomly selected to receive shock or not prior to making their first choice and were tested again over 10 trials. Those that received shock in trial 2, irrespective of shock in trial 1, were more likely to switch shelter choice in the next trial and thus showed rapid discrimination. During trial 1, many crabs emerged from the shock shelter and an increasing proportion emerged in later trials, thus avoiding shock by entering a normally avoided light area. In a final test we switched distinctive visual stimuli positioned above each shelter and/or changed the orientation of the crab when placed in the chamber for the test. The visual stimuli had no effect on choice, but crabs with altered orientation now selected the shock shelter, indicating that they had discriminated between the two shelters on the basis of movement direction. These data, and those of other recent experiments, are consistent with key criteria for pain experience and are broadly similar to those from vertebrate studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Protect Decapod Crustaceans Used As Models in Biomedical Research and in Ecotoxicology? Ethical and Legislative Considerations
    animals Article Why Protect Decapod Crustaceans Used as Models in Biomedical Research and in Ecotoxicology? Ethical and Legislative Considerations Annamaria Passantino 1,* , Robert William Elwood 2 and Paolo Coluccio 3 1 Department of Veterinary Sciences, University of Messina-Polo Universitario Annunziata, 98168 Messina, Italy 2 School of Biological Sciences, Queen’s University, Belfast BT9 5DL, Northern Ireland, UK; [email protected] 3 Department of Neurosciences, Psychology, Drug Research and Child Health (NEUROFARBA), University of Florence, Viale Pieraccini 6, 50139 Firenze, Italy; paolo.coluccio@unifi.it * Correspondence: [email protected] Simple Summary: Current European legislation that protects animals used for scientific purposes excludes decapod crustaceans (for example, lobster, crab and crayfish) on the grounds that they are non-sentient and, therefore, incapable of suffering. However, recent work suggests that this view requires substantial revision. Our current understanding of the nervous systems and behavior of decapods suggests an urgent need to amend and update all relevant legislation. This paper examines recent experiments that suggest sentience and how that work has changed current opinion. It reflects on the use of decapods as models in biomedical research and in ecotoxicology, and it recommends that these animals should be included in the European protection legislation. Abstract: Decapod crustaceans are widely used as experimental models, due to their biology, their sensitivity to pollutants and/or their convenience of collection and use. Decapods have been Citation: Passantino, A.; Elwood, viewed as being non-sentient, and are not covered by current legislation from the European Par- R.W.; Coluccio, P. Why Protect liament. However, recent studies suggest it is likely that they experience pain and may have the Decapod Crustaceans Used as capacity to suffer.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract the Wrongness of Killing
    Copyright Rainer Ebert May 2016 Abstract The Wrongness of Killing by Rainer Ebert There are few moral convictions that enjoy the same intuitive plausibility and level of acceptance both within and across nations, cultures, and traditions as the conviction that, normally, it is morally wrong to kill people. Attempts to provide a philosophical explanation of why that is so broadly fall into three groups: Consequentialists argue that killing is morally wrong, when it is wrong, because of the harm it inflicts on society in general, or the victim in particular, whereas personhood and human dignity accounts see the wrongness of killing people in its typically involving a failure to show due respect for the victim and his or her intrinsic moral worth. I argue that none of these attempts to explain the wrongness of killing is successful. Consequentialism generates too many moral reasons to kill, cannot account for deeply felt and widely shared intuitions about the comparative wrongness of killing, and gives the wrong kind of explanation of the wrongness of killing. Personhood and human dignity accounts each draw a line that is arbitrary and entirely unremarkable in terms of empirical reality, and hence ill-suited to carry the moral weight of the difference in moral status between the individuals below and above it. Paying close attention to the different ways in which existing accounts fail to convince, I identify a number of conditions that any plausible account of the wrongness of killing must meet. I then go on to propose an account that does. iv I suggest that the reason that typically makes killing normal human adults wrong equally applies to atypical human beings and a wide range of non-human animals, and hence challenge the idea that killing a non-human animal is normally easier to justify than killing a human being.
    [Show full text]