Of Social Ecology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Of Social Ecology 104 RET}IINKING ECOFEMINIST POLMICS clearly are, we wiII pay dearly for the loss of rational poli activity. A mystical tendency that indulges our fantasiesand st renders us captive to a commodified society may eventually, spite its good intentions, help to deprive us of our freedom individuals and to diminish our activism as social beings' Chapter 5 Historically, the Left has always tried to appeal to the best people, to their highest moral and intellectual selves'Mind, cri initttittg, and intellectuality are precious human attributes cannot be surrendered without leading to easily manipulated ceral reactions evoked by magic, rituals, and ultimately " Dialectics in the Ethics sive leaders" for ends other than freedom. As the Senecawriter Mohawk has forthrightly put it, "[t seems like every time say they'll do the thinking for you, they fuck you over"'I w of Social Ecology responsible people, doing the best thinking, not somebody v dreamed something."" As the forms of our domination increasinglysophisticated, it behoovesus to boldly "dare to know, in Kant's phrase, rather than to play childish games of "truth As a dialectical philosophy, social ecology arguesthat hu- dare." manity must be understood os the history of humanity, and that nature must be understood as the history of nature. ]ust so, it also arguesthat sciencemust be understood as tle history of science.It advancesthe view that there is much to be gained from examining the role that previous cosmologistsplayed in the developmentof our own in considering the problem of nature and humanity's relationship to each other, and that earlier peoples in Western culture have asked important questions tlat our present-day sci- enceignores. In particular, earlier cosmologistsaddressed and tried to explain-to the best of their ability-at least one very important question that modern science, to its detriment, fails to confront. This is the fact that, on the one hand, there is order in the natural world, and, on the other hand, that human beings have a rational faculty that is capable of comprehending it in varying degrees.Indeed, the human mind sometimesseems as if it were magnificently developed for understanding the order in the natural world. ]ust as the world is, at least in part, ordered in a certain way, the human mind is so organized as to be able to comprehend it at various levels of adequacy. 105 POLMCS 106 RETHINKING ECOFEMINIST Ethics of SocialEcology 707 This fact must have struck people in early periods of social in the world," without attempdng to justify it metaphysically, development as a remarkable "correspondence."For millennia, philosophically, or cosmologically,let alone scientificalv.' human reason and Despite they explained the "correspondence" between science's efficacy in bringing some understanding of The the inteltigible order in nature by at organismic analogy' nature'soperations, "science, in effect,has been permitted to iive rational human mind could understand the world because the a lie," writes Murray Bookchin. Science cosmic macrocosm-Iike the individual microcosm-had a human kind of mind. The various meanings of the Greek word logos has presupposed,with astonishingsuccess, tlat nature is encompassboth the mind's power of comprehension and the fact orderly, and that this order lends itself to rational interpretation of the cosmos' comprehensibility. Logosreferred both to the imma- by the human mind, but that reasonis exclusively the nent intelligibility that is discoverable in nature, as well as to the subjectiveattribute of the h observer,not of the phenomena mind that could discover it. This congruency between the rational 'man observed....science,in effect, hal becomea mind and the rational cosmosexplained how thinking can compre- temple built on the foundation of seemingly hend the world. Hence, the origin of the word "logic" from logos. .,ruins,', animistic and metaphysical without implied the ability to discuss in a rational way, as in Logos also which it would sink into the watery morassof its dialogues (from the Greek dia-logos),how ideas undergo develop- own contradictions.3 ment. Far from defining reason ot Iogos as opposed to nature, mind or nous that "was Mind was Socrates,Plato, and Aristotle studied a "erected into a second type of substancethat served as R. G. Colling- always first and foremost mind in nature," writes a ready dumping-ground for everything in experiencewhich phys_ notes, the fact ics did wood. For Aristotle, as fohn Herman Randall, fr., not read in mechanical naturej, as Randall obserues.lThe not a problem, but the most qualities "that men can know their world [was] of things, like the wetness of water and the coldness of world."' ice, were significant fact, both about us and about the shoved into this "dumping-ground," as Griffin and other through the ancient and ecofeminists This tradition of /ogoswas continued argue.Butit was not simply the qualities of things that it was transformedinto a rigid were so medieval periods.On the one hand, dispensed with. so was the deveripmenfal causality so and immutable natural law by the Stoics and Christians. On the typical of organismic life. serf-directiveness and tenden"v-th"r" developmental and dialectical too were other hand, it was perpetuated in its relegated to the merely subjective, by virtue of their association form by mystics. With the emergenceof modern science,the order with the "final causes"of medieval scholasticism. human mind in a new form: mathe- Indeed, of nature seemedopen to the modern sciencedefined itself most expricitly not by comprehensibleand irrr open book in trying to matics. The cosmos was dominate women and nature but by its attack on the But mathematics preserved logos in only its Scholastics' matlematical terms. "final causes,,,an issue that perhaps the from the mathe- major "orrriitrrt"d most rigid hypothetico-deductive form. Missing battleground between science and schorastic thlorogjr. ..To to explain Aristotle's "most signifi- the extent .paradijm, matical /ogos was any ability that mechanism became the prevalent of was Renaissance cant fact," or why it was that the now-mathematical cosmos and Enlightenment science,i writes Bookchin, ..the It becamea merely "metaphysical" notion intelligible to the human mind' of 'final cause' became the gristmiil on which science sharpened question, and the successorsof Descartes"abandoned the attempt its scalpel of 'obleciivity,' sc"ientistic.disinterestedness,, to prove this conespondence," as Randall observes.Ratler, they total rejection of $,,e". values in the scientific organon.,, The that "the order of men's scientifrc oacklash simply made the assumption against scholasticism was accompanied by a backrash ideas was, in the nature of things, the same as the order of obiects 108 RETHINKING ECOFEMINIST POLITICS Ethics of SocialEcology 109 against organicism generally, in "an exaggeratedrejection of nature was cast in largely antagonistic tems, and progress was organicism."u identified as the technical ability to use nonhuman nature to serve In delivering its "sustained polemic," to use Collingwood's the ends of the marketplace. Human destiny was conceived as the phrase, againstthe Scholastic theory of final causeswith its immu- redemption of society from a "demonic" natural world. Writes table, predetermined teleological ends, early science eliminated Bookchin, "The subjugationof human by human...was now cele- any notion that there was any potentiality or nisus in nature to brated asa common human enterpriseto bring nature under human realize implicit forms that have not been fully actualized. In short, control."' mechanistic science, Iike the putatively organismic approach many ecofeminists, spilled out the baby with the bathwater' In course of fighting one extreme, Scholasticism, it moved to anol The Problem of Instuumentalism extreme, mechanism. When the laws of physics, so suitable for understanding The mind had become a dumping ground of sorts inorganic nature, were applied to human society in various scien- mechanism established no intelligible place for mind in the tistic branches of knowledge, the result was to fuel the rise of an world that it was describing. The mechanistic worldview and instrumental social ethos. Human society doesnot operate accord- mathematical /ogoscould explain everything, it seemed,except ing to physicalist laws; to try to induce it to do so meansrendering human mind that perceived it, Descartes' res cogitans. The humanity homogeneous,lifeless, passive, and malleable.This was mind in its Newtonian aspect could not explain organisms organi not simply a matter of ideology. Forceswere at work in Western ismically; developments, developmentally; history, historically; society that stood to make great use of the instrumental ethos that society in ways appropriate to human social development' In explained people in terms of collections of isolated bodies in with the mathematical logos,the human mind and human eternally lawful motion. For one, the ethos of instrumentalism could not be explained intelligibly at all, let alone explain perfectly suited the emerging nation-state and its unrelenting cen- human ability to comprehend mathematical order. The tralization, bureaucratization,and domination. If people could be between nature and mind, writes Bookchin, was "replaced by reduced to units, they could be manageableand susceptibleto unbridgeable dualismbetween mentality and the external world. administration.If they could be instrumentalizedas workers, they Despite the social
Recommended publications
  • First Thoughts on the 25 January 2015 Election in Greece
    GPSG Pamphlet No 4 First thoughts on the 25 January 2015 election in Greece Edited by Roman Gerodimos Copy editing: Patty Dohle Roman Gerodimos Pamphlet design: Ana Alania Cover photo: The Zappeion Hall, by Panoramas on Flickr Inside photos: Jenny Tolou Eveline Konstantinidis – Ziegler Spyros Papaspyropoulos (Flickr) Ana Alania Roman Gerodimos Published with the support of the Politics & Media Research Group, Bournemouth University Selection and editorial matter © Roman Gerodimos for the Greek Politics Specialist Group 2015 All remaining articles © respective authors 2015 All photos used with permission or under a Creative Commons licence Published on 2 February 2015 by the Greek Politics Specialist Group (GPSG) www.gpsg.org.uk Editorial | Roman Gerodimos Continuing a tradition that started in 2012, a couple of weeks ago the Greek Politics Specialist Group (GPSG) invited short commentaries from its members, affiliates and the broader academ- ic community, as a first ‘rapid’ reaction to the election results. The scale of the response was humbling and posed an editorial dilemma, namely whether the pamphlet should be limited to a small number of indicative perspectives, perhaps favouring more established voices, or whether it should capture the full range of viewpoints. As two of the founding principles and core aims of the GPSG are to act as a forum for the free exchange of ideas and also to give voice to younger and emerging scholars, it was decided that all contributions that met our editorial standards of factual accuracy and timely
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise of Syriza: an Interview with Aristides Baltas
    THE RISE OF SYRIZA: AN INTERVIEW WITH ARISTIDES BALTAS This interview with Aristides Baltas, the eminent Greek philosopher who was one of the founders of Syriza and is currently a coordinator of its policy planning committee, was conducted by Leo Panitch with the help of Michalis Spourdalakis in Athens on 29 May 2012, three weeks after Syriza came a close second in the first Greek election of 6 May, and just three days before the party’s platform was to be revealed for the second election of 17 June. Leo Panitch (LP): Can we begin with the question of what is distinctive about Syriza in terms of socialist strategy today? Aristides Baltas (AB): I think that independently of everything else, what’s happening in Greece does have a bearing on socialist strategy, which is not possible to discuss during the electoral campaign, but which will present issues that we’re going to face after the elections, no matter how the elections turn out. We haven’t had the opportunity to discuss this, because we are doing so many diverse things that we look like a chicken running around with its head cut off. But this is precisely why I first want to step back to 2008, when through an interesting procedure, Synaspismos, the main party in the Syriza coalition, formulated the main elements of the programme in a book of over 300 pages. The polls were showing that Syriza was growing in popularity (indeed we reached over 15 per cent in voting intentions that year), and there was a big pressure on us at that time, as we kept hearing: ‘you don’t have a programme; we don’t know who you are; we don’t know what you’re saying’.
    [Show full text]
  • Election and Aftermath
    Order Code RS20575 Updated June 9, 2000 CRS Report for Congress Received through the CRS Web Greece: Election and Aftermath (name redacted) Specialist in Middle Eastern Affairs Foreign Affairs, Defense, and Trade Division Summary Prime Minister Simitis of Greece called an early election for April 9, 2000 because he believed that his government’s achievement in meeting the criteria for entry into the European Monetary Union (EMU) would return his PanHellenic Socialist Movement (PASOK) party to power. PASOK’s narrow victory endorsed Simitis’s decision, but the opposition New Democracy’s (ND) strong showing also validated Costas Karamanlis’s leadership of that party. The election continued a trend toward bipolarism, as votes for smaller parties, except for the Communists, declined appreciably. Simitis reappointed most key members of his previous government, and brought in close allies and technocrats to carry out a revitalized domestic agenda. In foreign policy, the government will try to continue the Greek-Turkish rapprochement, to help stabilize the Balkans, and to move closer to Europe through the EMU and the European Security and Defense Policy. Greek-U.S. relations are warm, but intermittently troubled by differences over the future of the former Yugoslavia, terrorism and counterterrorism in Greece, and minor issues. This report will be updated if developments warrant. Introduction1 On February 4, 2000, Prime Minister Costas Simitis called an early election for April 9, six months before his government’s term was to expire. On March 9, parliament reelected President Costas Stephanopoulos and Greece applied for membership in the European Monetary Union (EMU) single currency zone.
    [Show full text]
  • Systems Theory and Complexity: a Potential Tool for Radical Analysis Or the Emerging Social Paradigm for the Internationalised Market Economy?
    DEMOCRACY & NATURE: The International Journal of INCLUSIVE DEMOCRACY Vol. 6, No. 3 (November 2000) Systems theory and complexity: a potential tool for radical analysis or the emerging social paradigm for the internationalised market economy? TAKIS FOTOPOULOS Abstract: The aim of this paper is to critically assess the claims of systems theory and complexity in the analysis of social change and particularly to examine the view that ―if certain conditions are met― both could potentially be useful tools for radical analysis. The conclusion drawn from this analysis is that, although systems theory and complexity are useful tools in the natural sciences in which they offer many useful insights, they are much less useful in social sciences and indeed are incompatible, both from the epistemological point of view and that of their content, with a radical analysis aiming to systemic change towards an inclusive democracy. Introduction It was almost inevitable that the present demise of Marxism would bring about a revised form of functionalism/evolutionism, which had almost eclipsed in the sixties and the seventies, particularly in areas like the sociology of development where it had been replaced by neo-Marxist and dependency theories. The new version of functionalism/evolutionism is much more sophisticated than the original Parsonian functionalist paradigm and incorporates recent developments in “hard” sciences to produce a new “general” theory of social systems. A primary example of such an attempt is Niklas Luhmann’s Social Systems[1] which we
    [Show full text]
  • Social Ecology and Communalism
    Murray Bookchin Bookchin Murray $ 12,95 / £ xx,xx Social Ecology and Communalism Replace this text Murray Bookchin ocial cology Social Ecology and Communalism and Communalism Social Ecology S E and Communalism AK Press Social Ecology and Communalism Murray Bookchin Social Ecology and Communalism Bookchin, Murray Social Ecology and Communalism Library of Congress Control Number 2006933557 ISBN 978-1-904859-49-9 Published by AK Press © Eirik Eiglad and Murray Bookchin 2006 AK Press 674–A 23rd St. Oakland, CA 94612 USA www.akpress.org [email protected] AK Press UK PO Box 12766 Edinburgh, EH8 9YE Scotland (0131) 555–5165 www.akuk.com [email protected] Design and layout by Eirik Eiglad Contents An Introduction to Social Ecology and Communalism 7 What is Social Ecology? 19 Radical Politics in an Era of Advanced Capitalism 53 The Role of Social Ecology in a Period of Reaction 68 The Communalist Project 77 After Murray Bookchin 117 An Introduction to Social Ecology and Communalism We are standing at a crucial crossroads. Not only does the age- old “social question” concerning the exploitation of human labor remain unresolved, but the plundering of natural resources has reached a point where humanity is also forced to politically deal with an “ecological question.” Today, we have to make conscious choices about what direction society should take, to properly meet these challenges. At the same time, we see that our very ability to make the necessary choices are being undermined by an incessant centralization of economic and political power. Not only is there a process of centralization in most modern nation states that divests humanity of any control over social affairs, but power is also gradually being transferred to transnational institutions.
    [Show full text]
  • Harbinger, a Journal of Social Ecology
    a journal of social ecology Harbinger What is Social Ecology? VOL. 3, NO. 1 SPRING 2003 Harbinger - SPRING 2003 { 1 } Harbinger, a Journal of Social Ecology, publishes analysis relevant to the growing social ecology movement and news of the activities of the Institute for Social Ecology (ISE). It is our intention to explore the theory and practice needed to help create an ecological society, and to cultivate a generous intellectual outlook that can inform the principle of hope. Just as the outlook proposed by social ecology is concerned with both what is and what ought to be, so too is Harbinger and we will explore the tensions between the two. The central questions we address in the pages of Harbinger regard the process with which we must engage to create an ecological society, a society free of hierarchy and domination in all of its forms. A harbinger is a messenger, or a sign indicating that a major event or change is coming. It was the name given to the journal published by Emerson, the Alcotts, Thoreau and other New England transcendentalists associated with Brook Farm in the 19th century. The name was revived in the early 1980s by the ISE for our literary and philosophical journal. In its current incarnation Harbinger will continue the tradition of critically examining theory and practice, attempt to bring you stimulating work by talented authors, and, in addition, update you on the important work of the ISE. Our intention is to publish twice a year and we invite your comments and contributions. While Harbinger will entertain many points of view, our primary focus will be on a clarification and expansion of those ideas and practices that contribute to social ecology.
    [Show full text]
  • Takis Fotopoulos[1]
    Social Ecology, Eco- Communitarianism and Inclusive Democracy Takis Fotopoulos[1] Social Ecology and Inclusive Democracy John Clark’s critique of the politics of social ecology has no direct bearing on the Inclusive Democracy project ―only to the extent that the latter constitutes a synthesis of, among other traditions, some elements of libertarian municipalism. Readers of this journal are, anyway, well aware of the fact that the project of inclusive democracy represents a synthesis as well as a transcendence of the two major historical traditions, the socialist and the democratic ones, as well as of the radical currents in the new social movements (the open in browser PRO version Are you a developer? Try out the HTML to PDF API pdfcrowd.com feminist and particularly the ecological, of which social ecology is the most important radical component). Therefore, John Clark’s exclusive reliance on Murray Bookchin’s work on democracy in order to carry out an outright attack against direct democracy, ignoring, in the process, the work of Castoriadis and of this journal on the matter, seems —superficially at least— to be bizarre. However, this significant omission could easily be explained if one notes that what is from Clark’s viewpoint ‘one of the greatest strengths of Bookchin's politics’, is also, from a democratic perspective, the greatest weakness of this politics. Thus, according to Clark: One of the greatest strengths of Bookchin's politics is its grounding in ethics and the philosophy of nature (...) For Bookchin, politics is ultimately grounded in the process of evolutionary unfolding and self- realisation that has been taking place over the natural and social history of this planet.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Title of Dissertation: for the END IS a LIMIT
    ABSTRACT Title of Dissertation: FOR THE END IS A LIMIT: THE QUESTION CONCERNING THE ENVIRONMENT Ozguc Orhan, Doctor of Philosophy, 2007 Dissertation Directed By: Professor Charles E. Butterworth Department of Government and Politics Professor Ken Conca Department of Government and Politics This dissertation argues that Aristotle’s philosophy of praxis (i.e., ethics and politics) can contribute to our understanding of the contemporary question concerning the environment. Thinking seriously about the environment today calls for resisting the temptation to jump to conclusions about Aristotle’s irrelevance to the environment on historicist grounds of incommensurability or the fact that Aristotle did not write specifically on environmental issues as we know them. It is true that environmental problems are basically twentieth-century phenomena, but the larger normative discourses in which the terms “environmental” and “ecological” and their cognates are situated should be approached philosophically, namely, as cross-cultural and trans-historical phenomena that touch human experience at a deeper level. The philosophical perspective exploring the discursive meaning behind contemporary environmental praxis can reveal to us that certain aspects of Aristotle’s thought are relevant, or can be adapted, to the ends of environmentalists concerned with developmental problems. I argue that Aristotle’s views are already accepted and adopted in political theory and the praxis of the environment in many respects. In the first half of the dissertation, I
    [Show full text]
  • Social Ecology and the Non-Western World
    Speech delivered at the conference “Challenging Capitalist Modernity II: Dissecting Capitalist Modernity–Building Democratic Confederalism”, 3–5 April 2015, Hamburg. Texts of the conference are published at http://networkaq.net/2015/speeches 2.5 Federico Venturini Social Ecology and the non-Western World Murray Bookchin was the founder of the social ecology, a philosophical perspective whose political project is called libertarian municipalism or Communalism. Recently there has been a revival of interest in this project, due to its influence on the socio-political organization in Rojava, a Kurdish self-managed region in the Syrian state. This should not be a surprise because Bookchin's works influenced Abdul Öcalan for a more than a decade, a key Kurdish leader who developed a political project called Democratic Confederalism. We should all welcome this renewed interest in social ecology and take lessons from the Rojava experience. Bookchin's analyses have always been more focussed on North-American or European experiences and so libertarian municipalism draws from these traditions. Moreover, Bookchin, who was writing in a Cold war scenario, was suspicious of the limits of national movements struggling for independence. The aim of this paper is to develop and enlarge Bookchin's analysis, including experiences and traditions from different cultures and movements, and their interrelations on a global scale. First, it explores social ecology perspective in non- Western contexts. Second, it will introduce new tools to deal with inter-national relations based on world system theory. Third, it will suggests that new experiences coming from non-Western regions can strength social ecology understanding and practices.
    [Show full text]
  • Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements [Full Text, Not Including Figures] J.L
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements Art July 2000 Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements [full text, not including figures] J.L. Benson University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/art_jbgc Benson, J.L., "Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements [full text, not including figures]" (2000). Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements. 1. Retrieved from https://scholarworks.umass.edu/art_jbgc/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Art at ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Greek Color Theory and the Four Elements by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cover design by Jeff Belizaire ABOUT THIS BOOK Why does earlier Greek painting (Archaic/Classical) seem so clear and—deceptively— simple while the latest painting (Hellenistic/Graeco-Roman) is so much more complex but also familiar to us? Is there a single, coherent explanation that will cover this remarkable range? What can we recover from ancient documents and practices that can objectively be called “Greek color theory”? Present day historians of ancient art consistently conceive of color in terms of triads: red, yellow, blue or, less often, red, green, blue. This habitude derives ultimately from the color wheel invented by J.W. Goethe some two centuries ago. So familiar and useful is his system that it is only natural to judge the color orientation of the Greeks on its basis. To do so, however, assumes, consciously or not, that the color understanding of our age is the definitive paradigm for that subject.
    [Show full text]
  • The Necessity of Dialectical Naturalism: Marcuse, Bookchin and Dialectics in the Midst of Ecological Crises
    The Necessity of Dialectical Naturalism: Marcuse, Bookchin, and Dialectics in the Midst of Ecological Crises Author Brincat, Shannon, Gerber, Damian Published 2015 Journal Title Antipode Version Accepted Manuscript (AM) DOI https://doi.org/10.1111/anti.12140 Copyright Statement © 2015 Antipode Foundation. This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: The Necessity of Dialectical Naturalism: Marcuse, Bookchin, and Dialectics in the Midst of Ecological Crises, Antipode, Volume 47, Issue 4, September 2015, Pages 871–893, which has been published in final form at 10.1111/anti.12140. This article may be used for non- commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving (http:// olabout.wiley.com/WileyCDA/Section/id-828039.html) Downloaded from http://hdl.handle.net/10072/124939 Griffith Research Online https://research-repository.griffith.edu.au The Necessity of Dialectical Naturalism: Marcuse, Bookchin and dialectics in the midst of ecological crises “… the environmental crisis involves a crisis of the imagination the amelioration of which depends on finding better ways of imagining nature and humanity’s relation to it.” - Lawrence Buell (1995: 2) Introduction Central to dialectics is its account of totality, the historical (temporal), environmental (spatial) and social (cultural) whole. For it is in this totality – that expansive concept of the whole and all its parts – that the complex interactions, tensions and contradictions that generate transformation, take place. As such, how dialectical approaches understand and conceive of the totality takes on acute ontological significance and function. Dialectical analysis, then, requires the utmost precision to ensure its ontological postulates (interconnectivity, contradiction, negation, sublation, flux, amongst others) are directly reflected in how it accounts for the temporal, spatial and cultural context in which transformations take place.
    [Show full text]
  • SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY Ecofeminism: 2. Adams, Carol. J. (
    SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. AdamsJ Carol. J. 'The Feminist Trafic' in G. Garrd (ed) Ecofeminism: Women, Animals and N(ilture, Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1993 2. Adams, Carol. J. ( ed): Aris(Qtle 's on Ecofeminism and the Sacred, Continuun Press, New York~ 1993. 3. Agatwal, Anil and Narairi S&nith : 'The Second Citizen's Report, State of lndia'·s Environment Centre for Science and Environment Publications 1996'. I , I ' ' ' ' II' :i . I·,· •. '•! :' ' ' ':· '.: '•' :· : . .... + 4. Barnhill, Davtd Landis and Gottlieb Roger (ed): Deep Ecology and World Religions, State University ofNew York Press, 2001. 5; Bentin Ted: ~atural Relations: E"ology, Animal Rights and Social Justice, • Verso, London, 1993. 6. Bihel, Janet: Rethinking Ecofeminist Politics, South End Press, Boston, .::..0' 1991. 7. Bookchin Murray: Ecology ofFreedom, Black Rose Book, Montreal, 1991. 8. Bookchin Murray: Philosophy of Social Ecology (Dialectical Naturalism), Rawat Publication, Jaipur, 1996. 9. Bookchin Murray: Philosophy of Ecology: Essays on Dialectical Naturalism, Black Rose Books, New York, 1990. 10. Bookchin Murray: Towards an Ecological Society, Black Rose Books, Montreal, 1980. 11. Breanford George: How Deep is Deep Ecology? Times Change Press, Orai, California, 1989. 12. Brian Easlea: Patriarchy's confrontation with Women and Nature, W eidenfeld & Nicholson, London, 1981. 13. Bryant, Bunyan (ed): Environmental Justice: Issues, Policies and Solutions, Island Press, Washington D.C., 1995. 14. Bullard Robert: Unequal Protection, Sierra Club Booka, San Francisco, 1994. 15. Callicott J. Baird: On the Intrinsic value of Non-human Species in B.G. Norton, Princeton University Press, 1964. 170 16. Callicott J. Baird: In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays on Environmental Philosophy, State University, New York Press, Albany, 1989.
    [Show full text]