6-2: the 2 2 × Exchange Economy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

6-2: the 2 2 × Exchange Economy ©John Riley 4 May 2007 6-2: THE 2× 2 EXCHANGE ECONOMY In this section we switch the focus from production efficiency to the allocation of goods among consumers. We begin by focusing on a simple exchange economy in which there are two consumers, Alex and Bev. Each consumer has an endowment of two commodities. Commodities are private. That is, each consumer cares only about his own consumption. Consumer h h 2 h h h, h= AB , has an endowment ω , a consumption set X = R+ and a utility function U( x ) that is strictly monotonic. Pareto Efficiency With more than one consumer, the social ranking of allocations requires weighing the utility of one individual against that of another. Suppose that the set of possible utility pairs (the “utility possibility set”) associated with all possible allocations of the two commodities is as depicted below. B U2 45 line A W U+ U = k 1 2 U 1 6.2-1: Utility Possibility Set Setting aside the question of measuring utility, one philosophical approach to social choice places each individual behind a “veil of ignorance.” Not knowing which consumer you are going 1 to be, it is natural to assign a probability of 2 to each possibility. Then if individuals are neutral Section 6.2 page 1 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 towards risk while behind the veil of ignorance, they will prefer allocations with a higher expected utility 1+ 1 2U1 2 U 2 . This is equivalent to maximizing the sum of utilities, a proposal first put forth by Jeremy Bentham. In Fig. 6.2-1, the Benthamite criterion picks the point B. A more recent philosophical argument developed by John Rawls argues that, behind the veil of ignorance consumers will be highly averse to risk and thus place most weight on the worst possible outcome. Rawls takes the extreme position of infinite risk aversion so that all weight is placed on the worst possible outcome. The social criterion then become the Max Min criterion. Maximizing the minimum utility is achieved by moving out along the 45 line to the utility possibility frontier; the point W in the figure. Economists tend to be agnostic when it comes to theorizing about social choice rankings. Instead they focus on minimizing unnecessary waste. The utility allocation A in the figure is wasteful or “inefficient” because there are alternative allocations of goods which would make both individuals better off. Both the Benthamite allocation and the Rawlsian allocations are said to be Pareto Efficient (or simply “efficient”) since the only way to raise the utility of one individual is by reducing the utility of the other. Generalizing to more than two individuals we have the following definition. Pareto Efficiency A feasible allocation of commodities is Pareto efficient if there is no other feasible allocation that is strictly preferred by at least one consumer and is weakly preferred by all consumers. × ω= ω ω For the special 2 2 case, Alex and Bev must share the aggregate endowment (1 , 2 ) . Any feasible consumption bundle for Alex, xA = x must lie in the “Edgeworth Box” created by drawing perpendiculars from the aggregate endowment to the axes. Bev’s consumption bundle is then xB =ω − x . Thus Bev’s consumption bundle is measured from the North-West corner of the Edgeworth Box. We can therefore draw the indifference curves for both consumers through the allocation x. At the endowment point ω A , Alex’s marginal rate of substitution MRS A(ω A ) Section 6.2 page 2 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 exceeds MRSBB()ω= MRS B ( ω − ω A ) . Thus Alex is willing to give up more of commodity 2 than Bev for an additional unit of commodity 1. It follows that there is a set of allocations (shaded in the figure) that are strictly preferred by both consumers. x 2 ω B 1 OB ω ω (1 , 2 ) ω A ω B 2 2 A ω BB BB U() x= U ()ω AA AA U() x= U ()ω x1 A ω A O 1 Fig. 6.2-2: Edgeworth Box Diagram Note that the axes for the two consumers and the indifference curves extend beyond the boundaries of the Edgeworth Box. This is important. The consumers’ preferences are defined over their consumption sets (the positive consumption bundles) without reference to the availability of commodities. Suppose we consider all alternative allocations {xA , x B } such that UxBB()≥ Ux BB () and choose the allocation {xˆA , x ˆ B } that maximizes Alex’s utility. Mathematically, we solve the following optimization problem. MaxUx{()|()AA Ux BB≥ Ux BB (), x AB + x = ω } . xA, x B In the diagram, we seek Alex’s most preferred allocation that is in the shaded region of points at least weakly preferred by Bev. Consider any other allocation {xA , x B } which is weakly preferred Section 6.2 page 3 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 by Bev. That is UxBB()≥ Ux BB () . Since xˆ A is optimal for Alex, it cannot be the case that UxAA()> Ux AA ()ˆ . Then the allocation is Pareto Efficient. x2 OB A ˆ A x x UxAA()= Ux AA ()ˆ UxBB()= Ux BB () x O A 1 Fig. 6.2-3: Pareto Efficient Allocations By changing the initial allocation we can then map out the entire set of Pareto Efficient allocations. Example: Identical CES Preferences If preferences are CES with elasticity of substitution σ , both consumers have a marginal rate of h x σ h h = 2 1/ substitution, MRS() x k (h ) . From Fig. 6.3-2, if a PE allocation is in the interior of the x1 Edgeworth Box the indifference curves of the two consumers must have the same slope. Then xA x B 2= 2 A B . x1 x 1 Section 6.2 page 4 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 Appealing to the Ratio Rule 1 and then setting demand equal to supply, xA x B x A+ x B ω 2= 2 = 22 = 2 . A B A+ B ω x11 x xa x 11 Thus, in a Pareto efficient allocation each consumer is allocated a fraction of the aggregate endowment. It follows that for each consumer the marginal rate of substitution is h ω MRSh () x* = k (2 ) 1/ σ . (6.2-1) ω 1 Walrasian Equilibrium for an Exchange Economy In a Walrasian equilibrium all consumers are price-takers. Consumer h, h= AB , , with endowment ω h has preferences represented by the utility function Uh( x h ) where xh is his private consumption. His wealth is therefore Wh= p ⋅ ω h and so he chooses a consumption bundle xh( p , W h ) that solves Max{()| Uh x p⋅≤ x W h =⋅ p ω h } x There is no production. Let p ≥ 0 be a price vector of this exchange economy. Define ω= ∑ ω h to be the vector of total endowments in the economy and xp()=∑ xpph (, ⋅ ω h ) to h h be total (or “market”) demand. Then the vector of excess demands, ep()= xp () − ω . Definition: Market Clearing Prices ≥ Let ej ( p ) be the excess demand for commodity j at the price vector p 0 . The market for ≤ = commodity j clears if ej ( p ) 0 and pj e j ( p ) 0 . = That is, either excess demand for commodity j is zero or it is negative and the price p j 0 . a b a+ b 1 If 1= 1 = k then 1 1 = k + b2 b 2 a2 b 2 Section 6.2 page 5 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 Walras Law We now show that the market value of excess demands must be zero. First note that peppx⋅()()(( =⋅−=⋅ω p∑ xhh − ω )) = ∑ ( pxp ⋅−⋅ hh ω ) . h h By hypothesis utility is strictly increasing. Therefore each consumer spends all his wealth, that is p⋅ xh = p ⋅ ω h . Then the right hand expression is zero. Hence + = pe11() p pe 22 ()0 p . Thus, if one market clears, so must the other. This is known as Walras Law. 2 Definition: Walrasian Equilibrium The price vector p ≥ 0 is a Walrasian equilibrium price vector if all markets clear. For our two commodity model, it follows from Walras Law that we need only consider market = clearing in one market. Take any price vector p( p1 , p 2 ) . Given an endowment allocation {ωA , ω B ) , each consumer chooses his utility maximizing consumption bundle. As depicted, in Figure 6.2-4, Alex wants to trade from the endowment point N to C A , while Bev wishes to trade from N to C B . Thus, there is excess supply of commodity 1. The Walrasian auctioneer therefore lowers the price of commodity 1 (relative to commodity 2) and so flattens the budget line until supply equals demand. The Walrasian equilibrium E is depicted in Fig. 6.2-5. 2 With H consumers and n commodities an identical argument establishes that p⋅ e( p ) = 0 . Thus if n-1 markets clear, the n-th market must also clear. Section 6.2 page 6 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 x2 B O ω ω (1 , 2 ) C A C B N ωA ω A (1 , 2 ) A O x1 Fig. 6.2-4: Excess supply of commodity 1 x2 B O ω ω (1 , 2 ) E N B= B B U() x U () x O A x1 Fig. 6.2-5: Walrasian equilibrium Section 6.2 page 7 ©John Riley 4 May 2007 Equilibrium and Efficiency From the figure it is clear that any redistribution of commodities that raises the utility of Alex ( the North-East shaded region) must reduce Bev’s utility.
Recommended publications
  • Estimating the Benefits of New Products* by W
    Estimating the Benefits of New Products* by W. Erwin Diewert University of British Columbia and NBER Robert C. Feenstra University of California, Davis, and NBER January 26, 2021 Abstract A major challenge facing statistical agencies is the problem of adjusting price and quantity indexes for changes in the availability of commodities. This problem arises in the scanner data context as products in a commodity stratum appear and disappear in retail outlets. Hicks suggested a reservation price methodology for dealing with this problem in the context of the economic approach to index number theory. Hausman used a linear approximation to the demand curve to compute the reservation price, while Feenstra used a reservation price of infinity for a CES demand curve, which will lead to higher gains. The present paper evaluates these approaches, comparing the CES gains to those obtained using a quadratic utility function using scanner data on frozen juice products. We find that the CES gains from new frozen juice products are about six times greater than those obtained using the quadratic utility function, and the confidence intervals of these estimates do not overlap. * We thank the organizers and participants at the Big Data for 21st Century Economic Statistics conference, and especially Marshall Reinsdorf and Matthew Shapiro, for their helpful comments. We also thank Ninghui Li for her excellent research assistance. Financial support was received from a Digging into Data multi-country grant, provided by the United States NSF and the Canadian SSHRC. We acknowledge the James A. Kilts Center, University of Chicago Booth School of Business, https://www.chicagobooth.edu/research/kilts/datasets/dominicks, for the use of the Dominick’s Dataset.
    [Show full text]
  • Choice Models in Marketing: Economic Assumptions, Challenges and Trends
    Foundations and TrendsR in Marketing Vol. 2, No. 2 (2007) 97–184 c 2008 S. R. Chandukala, J. Kim, T. Otter, P. E. Rossi and G. M. Allenby DOI: 10.1561/1700000008 Choice Models in Marketing: Economic Assumptions, Challenges and Trends Sandeep R. Chandukala1, Jaehwan Kim2, Thomas Otter3, Peter E. Rossi4 and Greg M. Allenby5 1 Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN 47405-1701, USA, [email protected] 2 Korea University Business School, Korea University, Korea, [email protected] 3 Department of Marketing, Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universit¨at Frankfurt, Germany, [email protected] 4 Graduate School of Business, University of Chicago, USA, [email protected] 5 Fisher College of Business, Ohio State University, USA, allenby 1@fisher.osu.edu Abstract Direct utility models of consumer choice are reviewed and developed for understanding consumer preferences. We begin with a review of statistical models of choice, posing a series of modeling challenges that are resolved by considering economic foundations based on con- strained utility maximization. Direct utility models differ from other choice models by directly modeling the consumer utility function used to derive the likelihood of the data through Kuhn-Tucker con- ditions. Recent advances in Bayesian estimation make the estimation of these models computationally feasible, offering advantages in model interpretation over models based on indirect utility, and descriptive models that tend to be highly parameterized. Future trends are dis- cussed in terms of the antecedents and enhancements of utility function specification. 1 Introduction and Scope Understanding and measuring the effects of consumer choice is one of the richest and most challenging aspects of research in marketing.
    [Show full text]
  • Market Equilibrium in Exchange Economies with Some Families of Concave Utility Functions
    Market Equilibrium in Exchange Economies with Some Families of Concave Utility Functions Bruno Codenotti¤ Kasturi Varadarajany Abstract We consider the problem of computing equilibrium prices for exchange economies. We tackle this problem under the assumption that the traders have either CES (constant elasticity of sub- stitution) utility functions or a subfamily of ASC (additively separable concave) utilities. For the subfamily of ASC functions, and for a range of CES functions which include some CES functions that do not satisfy weak gross substitutability, we translate the equilibrium conditions into a convex feasibility problem. This enables us to obtain new, polynomial time algorithms for com- puting the equilibrium. As a byproduct of our work, we prove the uniqueness of equilibrium in an interesting setting where such a result was not known. 1 Introduction Theoretical computer scientists have, in the last few years, become aware of the importance of the computation of market equilibria, originally a central concept of Theoretical Economics [2, 3, 4]. Informally, in an exchange economy there is a collection of goods, initially distributed among \actors" who trade them. The preference of each of these independent actors for each bundle of goods is expressed by a \utility function". Each actor tries to maximize her utility, but is constrained by her budget (as determined by the value that the \market" { consisting of herself and all the other actors { gives to the goods she has). An equilibrium is a set of prices at which there are allocations of goods to traders such that two conditions are simultaneously satis¯ed: each trader's allocation maximizes her utility, subject to the constraints induced by her budget, and the market clears.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Microeconomic Foundations of Linear Demand for Differentiated
    On the microeconomic foundations of linear demand for di¤erentiated products Rabah Amiry, Philip Ericksonz, and Jim Jinx Nov 19, 2015 Abstract This paper provides a thorough exploration of the microeconomic foundations for the multi- variate linear demand function for di¤erentiated products that is widely used in industrial or- ganization. A key …nding is that strict concavity of the quadratic utility function is critical for the demand system to be well de…ned. Otherwise, the true demand function may be quite com- plex: Multi-valued, non-linear and income-dependent. The solution of the …rst order conditions for the consumer problem, which we call a local demand function, may have quite pathological properties. We uncover failures of duality relationships between substitute products and com- plementary products, as well as the incompatibility between high levels of complementarity and concavity. The two-good case emerges as a special case with strong but non-robust properties. A key implication is that all conclusions derived via the use of linear demand that does not satisfy the law of Demand ought to be regarded with some suspiscion. JEL codes: D43, L13, C72. Key words and phrases: linear demand, substitutes, complements, representative consumer, Law of Demand. We gratefully acknowledge helpful conversations with Wayne Barrett and Heracles Polemarchakis. yDepartment of Economics, University of Iowa (e-mail: [email protected]). zDepartment of Economics, University of Iowa (e-mail: [email protected]). xDepartment of Economics, University of St Andrews, U.K. 1 1 Introduction The emergence of the modern theory of industrial organization owes much to the development of game theory.
    [Show full text]
  • When Do Market Games Have Transferable Utility?
    JOURNAL OF ECONOMIC THEORY 35, 222-233 (1985) When Do Market Games Have Transferable Utility? THEODORE C. BERGSTROM AND HAL R. VARIAN Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109 Received September 13, 1983; revised August 23. 1984 A pure exchange economy generates a “market game” in which the allocations achievable by any coalition are determined by the initial endowments of its members. Subject to certain regularity conditions, it is shown that for a market game it is possible to find utility representations for each consumer so that the game can be treated as a game with transferable utility if and only if indirect utility of all consumers can be represented in the Gorman polar form. This is the class for which aggregate demand behaves as if it were the demand of a single consumer. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: 021, 022. cc: 1985 Academic Press, Inc. Game theorists like to work with transferable utility. In fact, several well- known solution concepts of game theory were, in their original formulations, defined only for games with transferable utility.’ Economists are uncom- fortable with transferable utility because it is not in general.possible to model a well-behaved exchange economy as a transferable utility game. It is known that in an exchange economy if preferences are of the quasilinear form, Uj(X, ,.-., x,> = x1 +fi(x, >‘.*3x,,,), for all i, then there is transferable utility over a range of utility distributions.’ However, quasilinear utility implies that individual demands for all goods except one are independent of income. For many economic problems, this is not an attractive assumption.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Microeconomic Foundations of Linear Demand for Differentiated
    On the microeconomic foundations of linear demand for differentiated products Rabah Amiry, Philip Ericksonz, and Jim Jinx July 9, 2015 Abstract This paper provides a thorough exploration of the microeconomic foundations for the multi- variate linear demand function for differentiated products that is widely used in industrial or- ganization. A key finding is that strict concavity of the quadratic utility function is critical for the demand system to be well defined. Otherwise, the true demand function may be quite com- plex: Multi-valued, non-linear and income-dependent. The solution of the first order conditions for the consumer problem, which we call a local demand function, may have quite pathological properties. We uncover failures of duality relationships between substitute products and com- plementary products, as well as the incompatibility between high levels of complementarity and concavity. The two-good case emerges as a special case with strong but non-robust properties. A key implication is that all conclusions derived via the use of linear demand that does not satisfy the law of Demand ought to be regarded with some suspiscion. JEL codes: D43, L13, C72. Key words and phrases: linear demand, substitutes, complements, representative consumer, Law of Demand. We gratefully acknowledge helpful conversations with Wayne Barrett and Heracles Polemarchakis. yDepartment of Economics, University of Iowa (e-mail: [email protected]). zDepartment of Economics, University of Iowa (e-mail: [email protected]). xDepartment of Economics, University of St Andrews, U.K. 1 1 Introduction The emergence of the modern theory of industrial organization owes much to the development of game theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Microeconomics Review Course LECTURE NOTES
    Microeconomics Review Course LECTURE NOTES Lorenzo Ferrari [email protected] August 30, 2019 Disclaimer: These notes are for exclusive use of the students of the Microeconomics Review Course, M.Sc. in European Economy and Business Law, University of Rome Tor Vergata. Their aim is purely instructional and they are not for circulation. Course Information Expected Audience: Students interested in starting a Master’s in economics. In partic- ular, students enrolled in the M.Sc. in European Economy and Business Law. Preliminary Requirements: No background in economics is needed. Final Exam: None. Schedule We 11 Sept (10:00 – 13:00 / 14:00 – 18:00), Fr 12 Sept (10:00 – 13:00 / 14:00 – 17:00). Office Hours: By appointment. Outline • Consumer theory: budget constraint, preferences, utility, optimal choice, demand. • Production theory: production set, production function, short-run and long-run. • Market structure: demand-supply curve, comparative statics, monopoly. References • Main reference: Varian, H.R. (2010), Intermediate Microeconomics: a modern approach, 8th edition, WW Norton & Company. 1 Introduction Microeconomics is a branch of economics dealing with individual choice: a consumer must choose what and how much to consume given her income, a firm decides the quantity to be produced or the price to set in the market. Microeconomic theories look for the individual’s optimal choice. In particular, microeconomics deal with • Theory of consumption (demand) • Theory of production (supply) • Market structure • Game theory (covered in another course) We follow what is known as the neoclassical approach. The latter assumes rational economic agents (e.g. consumers, firms) whose objectives are expressed using quantitative functions (utilities and profits), maximised subject to certain constraints.
    [Show full text]
  • Consumer Theory Introduction Outline Preferences
    Introduction Consumer Theory In this chapter, we formalize the concept of consumer choice. Lecture 2 We see how an individual, with certain preferences, makes decisions when faced with a constraint. Reading: Perlo¤ Chapter 3 It is the foundation of the demand curve we saw yesterday. August 2015 1 / 70 2 / 70 Outline Preferences Preferences - Assumptions we make about how individuals rank di¤erent options. Utility - A convenient way to summarize preferences. Individuals prefer certain sets of goods to others Budget Constraint - What can people a¤ord? In order to formalize this abstract concept in a useful way, we need to Constrained Consumer Choice - Given income, prices and make a few assumptions about these preferences preferences, what is the best choice I can make? Behavioral Economics - Do individuals behave in reality how we have assumed? 3 / 70 4 / 70 Preferences Preferences But rst lets go over some notation. Consumers rank bundles in terms of desirability. a bundle (or basket) is simply of a combination of goods and services. a % b. I like bundle a at least as much as b. I weakly prefer a to b bundle a is two haircuts and a can of Pepsi. a b. I de nitely like a more than b. I strictly prefer a to b bundle b is four cans of Pepsi and no haircuts. a b. I like the bundles equally. I am indi¤erent between a and b. 5 / 70 6 / 70 Preferences Preferences We make three assumptions about preferences. If the rst two are met, an individual is considered to be rational.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes: Public Economics
    Lecture Notes: Public Economics Fall 2018 Contents I Public Goods 6 0.1 Introduction . 7 0.1.1 What are Public Goods? . 7 0.2 The Model . 7 0.3 Optimal Provision of Pure Public Good . 8 0.4 Can the Optimal Allocation be Decentralized? . 12 0.5 Lindahl Equilibria . 14 0.5.1 Is Lindahl Equilibrium a Reasonable Market Mechanism? . 16 0.5.2 Nash Implementation . 20 0.6 Positive Models of Private Provision of Public Goods . 23 0.6.1 A Static Model of Private Contributions . 24 0.6.2 Comparative Statics Regarding Changes in the Wealth Distribution 30 0.6.3 Multiple Public Goods and Spheres of Influence . 32 0.7 Does Public Provision Crowd Out Private Provision? . 33 0.7.1 Guide to the Recent Literature . 34 0.8 Dynamic Voluntary Provision of Public Goods . 40 0.8.1 Admati and Perry (ReStud, 1991) . 40 0.8.2 Marx and Matthews (ReStud 2000) . 44 0.9 Provision of Public Goods with Private Information . 46 0.9.1 An Illustrative Example: two agent case . 46 0.9.2 Impossibility Result for Large Economies (Mailath and Postlewaite, REStud (1990) . 48 0.10 Local Public Goods . 51 0.10.1 A Class of Tiebout Models (Bewley Econometrica 1981) . 52 2 CONTENTS 3 0.10.2 Are Tiebout Equilibria Pareto Effi cient? . 54 0.10.3 A Tiebout Model with Effi cient Equilibrium . 57 0.10.4 Empirical Studies Related to Tiebout Hypothesis . 60 0.11 Public Goods Bibliography . 62 II Social Arrangements 63 0.12 A model incorporating social arrangements: .
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes for Macroeconomics I, 2004
    Lecture notes for Macroeconomics I, 2004 Per Krusell Please do NOT distribute without permission! Comments and suggestions are welcome. 1 2 Chapter 1 Introduction These lecture notes cover a one-semester course. The overriding goal of the course is to begin provide methodological tools for advanced research in macroeconomics. The emphasis is on theory, although data guides the theoretical explorations. We build en- tirely on models with microfoundations, i.e., models where behavior is derived from basic assumptions on consumers' preferences, production technologies, information, and so on. Behavior is always assumed to be rational: given the restrictions imposed by the primi- tives, all actors in the economic models are assumed to maximize their objectives. Macroeconomic studies emphasize decisions with a time dimension, such as various forms of investments. Moreover, it is often useful to assume that the time horizon is in¯nite. This makes dynamic optimization a necessary part of the tools we need to cover, and the ¯rst signi¯cant fraction of the course goes through, in turn, sequential maximization and dynamic programming. We assume throughout that time is discrete, since it leads to simpler and more intuitive mathematics. The baseline macroeconomic model we use is based on the assumption of perfect com- petition. Current research often departs from this assumption in various ways, but it is important to understand the baseline in order to fully understand the extensions. There- fore, we also spend signi¯cant time on the concepts of dynamic competitive equilibrium, both expressed in the sequence form and recursively (using dynamic programming). In this context, the welfare properties of our dynamic equilibria are studied.
    [Show full text]
  • Consumer Theory with Misperceived Tastes
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics De Clippel, Geoffroy; Rozen, Kareen Working Paper Consumer theory with misperceived tastes Working Paper, No. 2018-10 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, Brown University Suggested Citation: De Clippel, Geoffroy; Rozen, Kareen (2018) : Consumer theory with misperceived tastes, Working Paper, No. 2018-10, Brown University, Department of Economics, Providence, RI This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/202602 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu CONSUMER THEORY WITH MISPERCEIVED TASTES Geoffroy de Clippel∗ and Kareen Rozeny July 2018 Abstract Incorporating bounded rationality into the classic consumer theory setting, we study the testable implications of a consumer who may have trouble consistently assessing her subjective tastes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Algebraic Geometry of Competitive Equilibrium
    The Algebraic Geometry of Competitive Equilibrium Lawrence E. Blume Cornell University and William R. Zame The Johns Hopkins University and UCLA 1 Introduction The classical tools of general equilibrium theory are convexity and general topology. One of Debreu’s lasting contributions has been to show how the tools of differential topology may serve to yield more refined information about equilibrium. In par- ticular, Debreu (1970) showed that differential topology could provide a rigorous formalization of “counting equations and unknowns” to provide a satisfactory result on the determinacy of equilibrium. Debreu required that preferences be representable by C2 utility functions with non-vanishing gradients and that indifference surfaces have non-vanishing curvature. Following Debreu, a natural question to ask is: Are there other interesting classes of preferences (or demands) exhibiting regularity of behavior sufficient to guarantee the generic local determinacy of equilibrium prices? The first results in this direc- tion were obtained by Rader (1972, 1973), who showed that generic finiteness of the equilibrium price set was a consequence of demand being differentiable almost everywhere and satisfying condition N: that the image of a null set is null. Rader also gave conditions on preferences sufficient to generate demand meeting these hy- potheses; a further set of sufficient conditions was developed in a later paper (1979). The concave-utility requirement of Rader (1973) has only recently been relaxed to local concavifiability of the preference relation, by Pascoa and Werlang (1989). The work reported here extends the work of Debreu in a different direction. Its motivation comes from two sources. The first is a remark made by Rader at an NBER Conference in the 1970’s about the nature of demand when preferences are analytic.
    [Show full text]